additum: f. addo ,
dĭdi, dĭtum, 3, v. a. 2. do (addues for addideris, Paul. ex Fest. p. 27 Müll.),addition.
Strawson Wiggins p. 520. The utterer implies something more or different from
what he explicitly conveys. Cfr. Disimplicaturum, ‘less’ under ‘different from’
How seriously are we taking the ‘more.’ Not used by Grice. They seem
cross-categorial. If emissor draws a skull and then a cross he means that there
is danger and death in the offing. He crosses the cross, so it means death is
avoidable. Urmson says that Warnock went to bed and took off his boots. He
implicates in that order. So he means MORE than the ‘ampersand.” The “and” is
expanded into “and then.” But in not every case things are so easy that it’s a
matter of adding stuff. Cf. summatum, conjunctum. And then there’s the
‘additive implicaturum.’ By uttering
‘and,’ Russell means the Boolean adition. Whitehead means ‘and then’.
Whithead’s implicaturum is ADDITIVE, as opposed to diaphoron. Grice considers
the conceptual possibilities here: One may explicitly convey that p, and
implicitly convey q, where q ADDS to p (e. g. ‘and’ implicates ‘and then’).
Sometimes it does not, “He is a fine fine,” (or a ‘nice fellow,’ Lecture IV)
implying, “He is a scoundrel.” Sometimes it has nothing to do with it, “The
weather has been nice” implying, “you committed a gaffe.” With disimplicaturum,
you implicate LESS than you explicitly convey. When did you last see your
father? “Yesterday night, in my drams.” Grice sums this up with the phrase,
“more or other.” By explicitly conveying that p, the emissor implicates MORE OR
OTHER than he explicitly conveys.
adornoian implicaturum. Grice enjoyed
Adorno’s explorations on the natural/non-natural distinction; adorno, t. w. a
philosopher of the first generation of the Frankfurt School of critical theory.
With Horkheimer, Adorno gave philosophical direction to the Frankfurt School
and its research projects in its Institute for Social Research. An accomplished
musician and composer, Adorno first focused on the theory of culture and art, working
to develop a non-reductionist but materialist theory of art and music in many
essays. Under the influence of Walter Benjamin, he turned toward developing a
“micrological” account of cultural artifacts, viewing them as “constellations”
of social and historical forces. As his collaboration with Horkheimer
increased, Adorno turned to the problem of a self-defeating dialectic of modern
reason and freedom. Under the influence of the seemingly imminent victory of
the Nazis in Europe, this analysis focused on the “entwinement of myth and
Enlightenment.” The Dialectic of Enlightenment argues that instrumental reason
promises the subject autonomy from the forces of nature only to enslave it
again by its own repression of its impulses and inclinations. The only way
around this self-domination is “non-identity thinking,” found in the unifying
tendencies of a non-repressive reason. This self-defeating dialectic is
represented by the striking image of Ulysses tied to the mast to survive his
encounter with the Sirens. Adorno initially hoped for a positive analysis of
the Enlightenment to overcome this genealogy of modern reason, but it is never
developed. Instead, he turned to an increasingly pessimistic analysis of the
growing reification of modern life and of the possibility of a “totally
administered society.” Adorno held that “autonomous art” can open up
established reality and negate the experience of reification. Aesthetic Theory develops
this idea of autonomous art in terms of aesthetic form, or the capacity of the
internal organization of art to restructure existing patterns of meaning.
Authentic works of art have a “truth-value” in their capacity to bring to
awareness social contradictions and antinomies. In Negative Dialectics 6 Adorno
provides a more general account of social criticism under the “fragmenting”
conditions of modern rationalization and domination. These and other writings
have had a large impact on cultural criticism, particularly through Adorno’s
analysis of popular culture and the “culture industry.”
adparitum: --- apparitio –
Latin for ‘appear’ – ADPARITUM -- theory of appearing, the theory that to
perceive an object is simply for that object to appear present itself to one as
being a certain way, e.g., looking round or like a rock, smelling vinegary,
sounding raucous, or tasting bitter. Nearly everyone would accept this
formulation on some interpretation. But the theory takes this to be a
rock-bottom characterization of perception, and not further analyzable. It
takes “appearing to subject S as so-and-so” as a basic, irreducible relation,
one readily identifiable in experience but not subject to definition in other
terms. The theory preserves the idea that in normal perception we are directly
aware of objects in the physical environment, not aware of them through
non-physical sense-data, sensory impressions, or other intermediaries. When a
tree looks to me a certain way, it is the tree and nothing else of which I am
directly aware. That involves “having” a sensory experience, but that experience
just consists of the tree’s looking a certain way to me. After enjoying a
certain currency early in this century the theory was largely abandoned under
the impact of criticisms by Price, Broad, and Chisholm. The most widely
advertised difficulty theoretical underdetermination is this. What is it that
appears to the subject in completely hallucinatory experience? Perhaps the
greatest strength of the theory is its fidelity to what perceptual experience
seems to be. ap-pārĕo (adp- , Ritschl, Fleck., B. and K.; app- , Lachm., Merk.,
Weissenb., Halm, Rib.), ui, itum, 2, v. n.,
I.to come in sight, to appear, become visible, make one's appearance
(class. in prose and poetry). I. A.. Lit.: “ego adparebo domi,” Plaut. Capt. 2,
3, 97: “ille bonus vir nusquam adparet,” Ter. Eun. 4, 3, 18; Lucr. 3, 25; so
id. 3, 989: “rem contra speculum ponas, apparet imago,” id. 4, 157: unde tandem
adpares, Cic. Fragm. ap. Prisc. p. 706 P.; id. Fl. 12 fin.: “equus mecum una
demersus rursus adparuit,” id. Div. 2, 68; so id. Sull. 2, 5: “cum lux
appareret (Dinter, adpeteret),” Caes. B. G. 7, 82: “de sulcis acies apparuit
hastae,” Ov. M. 3, 107: “apparent rari nantes,” Verg. A. 1, 118, Hor. C. S. 59
al.—With dat.: “anguis ille, qui Sullae adparuit immolanti,” Cic. Div. 2, 30
fin.; id. Clu. 53: “Quís numquam candente dies adparuit ortu,” Tib. 4, 1,
65.—Once in Varro with ad: quod adparet ad agricolas, R. R. 1, 40.— B. In gen.,
to be seen, to show one's self, be in public, appear: “pro pretio facio, ut
opera adpareat Mea,” Plaut. Ps. 3, 2, 60: “fac sis nunc promissa adpareant,”
Ter. Eun. 2, 3, 20; cf. id. Ad. 5, 9, 7: “illud apparere unum,” that this only
is apparent, Lucr. 1, 877; Cato, R. R. 2, 2: “ubi merces apparet? i. e. illud
quod pro tantā mercede didiceris,” Cic. Phil. 2, 34: “quo studiosius opprimitur
et absconditur, eo magis eminet et apparet,” id. Rosc. Am. 41 fin.: “Galbae
orationes evanuerunt, vix jam ut appareant,” id. Brut. 21, 82: “apparet adhuc
vetus mde cicatrix,” Ov. M. 12, 444; 2, 734: “rebus angustis animosus atque
fortis appare,” Hor. C. 2, 10, 22: “cum lamentamur, non apparere labores
Nostros,” are not noticed, considered, id. Ep. 2, 1, 224, so id. ib. 2, 1, 250
al.; Plaut. Men. 2, 1, 14; cf. id. Am. 2, 2, 161 and 162.—Hence, apparens (opp.
latens), visible, evident: “tympana non apparentia Obstrepuere,” Ov. M. 4, 391:
“apparentia vitia curanda sunt,” Quint. 12, 8, 10; so id. 9, 2, 46.— II. Trop.:
res apparet, and far more freq. impers. apparet with acc. and inf. or
rel.-clause, the thing (or it) is evident, clear, manifest, certain, δῆλόν ἐστι,
φαίνεται (objective certainty, while videtur. δοκεῖ, designates subjective
belief, Web. Uebungssch. 258): “ratio adparet,” Plaut. Trin. 2, 4, 17: “res
adparet, Ter Ad. 5, 9, 7: apparet id etiam caeco, Liv 32, 34. cui non id
apparere, id actum esse. etc.,” id. 22, 34; 2, 31 fin.: “ex quo adparet
antiquior origo,” Plin. 36, 26, 67, § 197 al.: “adparet servom nunc esse domini
pauperis,” Ter. Eun. 3, 2, 33: “non dissimulat, apparet esse commotum,” Cic.
Phil. 2, 34: apparet atque exstat, utrum simus earum (artium) rudes, id. de Or.
1, 16, 72: “quid rectum sit, adparet,” id. Fam. 5, 19; 4, 7: “sive confictum
est, ut apparet, sive, etc.,” id. Fl. 16 fin.; Nep. Att. 4, 1; Liv. 42, 43:
“quo adparet antiquiorem hanc fuisse scientiam,” Plin. 35, 12, 44, § 153
al.—Also with dat. pers.: “quas impendere jam apparebat omnibus,” Nep. Eum. 10,
3; and, by attraction, with nom. and inf., as in Gr. δῆλός ἐστι, Varr. R. R. 1,
6, 2: “membra nobis ita data sunt, ut ad quandam rationem vivendi data esse
adpareant,” Cic. Fin. 3, 7, 23, ubi v. Otto: “apparet ita degenerāsse Nero,”
Suet. Ner. 1; or without the inf., with an adj. as predicate: “apparebat atrox
cum plebe certamen (sc. fore, imminere, etc.),” Liv. 2, 28; Suet. Rhet. 1.—
III. To appear as servant or aid (a lictor, scribe, etc.), to attend, wait
upon, serve; cf. apparitor (rare): “sacerdotes diis adparento,” Cic. Leg. 2, 8,
21: “cum septem annos Philippo apparuisset,” Nep. Eum. 13, 1: “cum appareret
aedilibus,” Liv. 9, 46 Drak.: “lictores apparent consulibus,” id. 2, 55:
“collegis accensi,” id. 3, 33: tibi appareo atque aeditumor in templo tuo,
Pompon. ap. Gell. 12, 10: “Jovis ad solium Apparent,” Verg. A. 12, 850 (=
praestant ad obsequium, Serv.). Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Bradley and the misuses of
‘appearance.’”
æqui-pollence: term used by
Grice, après Sextus Empiricus, to express the view that there are arguments of
equal strength on all sides of any question and that therefore we should
suspend judgment on every question that can be raised.
æqui-probable: having the same
probability. Sometimes used in the same way as ‘equipossible’, the term is
associated with Laplace’s the “classical” interpretation of probability, where
the probability of an event is the ratio of the number of equipossibilities favorable
to the event to the total number of equipossibilities. For example, the
probability of rolling an even number with a “fair” six-sided die is ½ there being three equipossibilities 2, 4, 6
favorable to even, and six equipossibilities 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6 in all and 3 /6 %
½. The concept is now generally thought not to be widely applicable to the
interpretation of probability, since natural equipossibilities are not always
at hand as in assessing the probability of a thermonuclear war tomorrow.
æqui-valence: mutual
inferability. The following are main kinds: two statements are materially
equivalent provided they have the same truthvalue, and logically equivalent
provided each can be deduced from the other; two sentences or words are
equivalent in meaning provided they can be substituted for each other in any
context without altering the meaning of that context. In truth-functional
logic, two statements are logically equivalent if they can never have
truthvalues different from each other. In this sense of ‘logically equivalent’
all tautologies are equivalent to each other and all contradictions are
equivalent to each other. Similarly, in extensional set theory, two classes are
equivalent provided they have the same numbers, so that all empty classes are regarded
as equivalent. In a non-extensional set theory, classes would be equivalent
only if their conditions of membership were logically equivalent or equivalent
in meaning.
Grice’s æqui-vocality
thesis
-- aequivocation, the use of an expression in two or more different senses in a
single context. For example, in ‘The end of anything is its perfection. But the
end of life is death; so death is the perfection of life’, the expression ‘end’
is first used in the sense of ‘goal or purpose,’ but in its second occurrence
‘end’ means ‘termination.’ The use of the two senses in this context is an
equivocation. Where the context in which the expression used is an argument,
the fallacy of equivocation may be committed.
æstheticum: Grice is well
aware that ‘aesthetica,’ qua discipline, was meant to refer to the ‘sensibile,’
as opposed to the ‘intellectus.’ With F. N. Sibley (who credits Grice
profusely), Grice explored the ‘second-order’ quality of the so-called
‘aesthetic properties.’ It influenced Scruton. The aesthetic attitude is the appropriate
attitude or frame of mind for approaching art or nature or other objects or
events so that one might both appreciate its intrinsic perceptual qualities,
and as a result have an aesthetic experience. The aesthetic attitude has been
construed in many ways: 1 as disinterested, so that one’s experience of the
work is not affected by any interest in its possible practical uses, 2 as a
“distancing” of oneself from one’s own personal concerns, 3 as the
contemplation of an object, purely as an object of sensation, as it is in
itself, for its own sake, in a way unaffected by any cognition or knowledge one
may have of it. These different notions of aesthetic attitude have at times
been combined within a single theory. There is considerable doubt about whether
there is such a thing as an aesthetic attitude. There is neither any special
kind of action nor any special way of performing an ordinary action that
ensures that we see a work as it “really is,” and that results in our having an
aesthetic experience. Furthermore, there are no purely sensory experiences,
divorced from any cognitive content whatsoever. Criticisms of the notion of
aesthetic attitude have reinforced attacks on aesthetics as a separate field of
study within philosophy. On the other hand, there’s aesthetic formalism,
non-iconic, the view that in our interactions with works of art, form should be
given primacy. Rather than taking ‘formalism’ as the name of one specific
theory in the arts, it is better and more typical to take it to name that type
of theory which emphasizes the form of the artwork. Or, since emphasis on form
is something that comes in degrees, it is best to think of theories of art as
ranged on a continuum of more formalist and less formalist. It should be added
that theories of art are typically complex, including definitions of art,
recommendations concerning what we should attend to in art, analyses of the
nature of the aesthetic, recommendations concerning the making of aesthetic
evaluations, etc.; and each of these components may be more formalist or less
so. Those who use the concept of form mainly wish to contrast the artifact
itself with its relations to entities outside itself with its representing various things, its
symbolizing various things, its being expressive of various things, its being
the product of various intentions of the artist, its evoking various states in
beholders, its standing in various relations of influence and similarity to
preceding, succeeding, and contemporary works, etc. There have been some,
however, who in emphasizing form have meant to emphasize not just the artifact
but the perceptible form or design of the artifact. Kant, e.g., in his theory
of aesthetic excellence, not only insisted that the only thing relevant to determining
the beauty of an object is its appearance, but within the appearance, the form,
the design: in visual art, not the colors but the design that the colors
compose; in music, not the timbre of the individual sounds but the formal
relationships among them. It comes as no surprise that theories of music have
tended to be much more formalist than theories of literature and drama, with
theories of the visual arts located in between. While Austin’s favourite
aesthetic property is ‘dumpty,’ Grice is more open minded, and allows for more
of a property or quality such as being dainty, garish, graceful, balanced,
charming, majestic, trite, elegant, lifeless, ugly, or beautiful. By contrast,
non-aesthetic properties are properties that require no special sensitivity or
perceptiveness to perceive such as a
painting’s being predominantly blue, its having a small red square in a corner
or a kneeling figure in the foreground, or that the music becomes louder at a
given point. Sometimes it is argued that a special perceptiveness or taste is
needed to perceive a work’s aesthetic qualities, and that this is a defining
feature of a property’s being aesthetic. A corollary of this view is that
aesthetic qualities cannot be defined in terms of non-aesthetic qualities, though
some have held that aesthetic qualities supervene on non-aesthetic qualities.
As a systematic philosopher, Grice goes back to the etymological root of the
aesthetic as the philosophy of the sensible. He would make fun of the
specialization. “If at the philosophy department I am introduced to Mr. Puddle,
our man in nineteenth-century continental aesthetics, I can grasp he is either
underdescribed or not good at nineteenth-century continental aesthetics!’ The
branch of philosophy that examines the nature of art and the character of our
adventitious ideas and experience of art and of the natural environment. It
emerged as a separate field of philosophical inquiry during the eighteenth
century in England and on the Continent. Recognition of aesthetics as a separate
branch of philosophy coincided with the development of theories of art that
grouped together painting, poetry, sculpture, music, and dance and often
landscape gardening as the same kind of thing, les beaux arts, or the fine
arts. Baumgarten coined the term ‘aesthetics’ in his Reflections on Poetry 1735
as the name for one of the two branches of the study of knowledge, i.e., for
the study of sensory experience coupled with feeling, which he argued provided
a different type of knowledge from the distinct, abstract ideas studied by
“logic.” He derived it from the ancient Grecian aisthanomai ‘to perceive’, and
“the aesthetic” has always been intimately connected with sensory experience
and the kinds of feelings it arouses. Questions specific to the field of
aesthetics are: Is there a special attitude, the aesthetic attitude, which we
should take toward works of art and the natural environment, and what is it
like? Is there a distinctive type of experience, an aesthetic experience, and
what is it? Is there a special object of attention that we can call the
aesthetic object? Finally, is there a distinctive value, aesthetic value,
comparable with moral, epistemic, and religious values? Some questions overlap
with those in the philosophy of art, such as those concerning the nature of
beauty, and whether there is a faculty of taste that is exercised in judging
the aesthetic character and value of natural objects or works of art.
Aesthetics also encompasses the philosophy of art. The most central issue in
the philosophy of art has been how to define ‘art’. Not all cultures have, or
have had, a concept of art that coincides with the one that emerged in Western
Europe during the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. What justifies our
applying our concept to the things people in these other cultures have
produced? There are also many pictures including paintings, songs, buildings,
and bits of writing, that are not art. What distinguishes those pictures,
musical works, etc., that are art from those that are not? Various answers have
been proposed that identify the distinguishing features of art in terms of
form, expressiveness, intentions of the maker, and social roles or uses of the
object. Since the eighteenth century there have been debates about what kinds
of things count as “art.” Some have argued that architecture and ceramics are
not art because their functions are primarily utilitarian, and novels were for
a long time not listed among the “fine arts” because they are not embodied in a
sensuous medium. Debates continue to arise over new media and what may be new
art forms, such as film, video, photography, performance art, found art,
furniture, posters, earthworks, and computer and electronic art. Sculptures
these days may be made out of dirt, feces, or various discarded and
mass-produced objects, rather than marble or bronze. There is often an explicit
rejection of craft and technique by twentieth-century artists, and the subject
matter has expanded to include the banal and everyday, and not merely
mythological, historical, and religious subjects as in years past. All of these
developments raise questions about the relevance of the category of “fine” or
“high” art. Another set of issues in philosophy of art concerns how artworks
are to be interpreted, appreciated, and understood. Some views emphasize that
artworks are products of individual efforts, so that a work should be
understood in light of the producer’s knowledge, skill, and intentions. Others
see the meaning of a work as established by social conventions and practices of
the artist’s own time, but which may not be known or understood by the
producer. Still others see meaning as established by the practices of the
users, even if they were not in effect when the work was produced. Are there
objective criteria or standards for evaluating individual artworks? There has
been much disagreement over whether value judgments have universal validity, or
whether there can be no disputing about taste, if value judgments are relative
to the tastes and interests of each individual or to some group of individuals
who share the same tastes and interests. A judgment such as “This is good”
certainly seems to make a claim about the work itself, though such a claim is
often based on the sort of feeling, understanding, or experience a person has
obtained from the work. A work’s aesthetic or artistic value is generally
distinguished from simply liking it. But is it possible to establish what sorts
of knowledge or experiences any given work should provide to any suitably
prepared perceiver, and what would it be to be suitably prepared? It is a
matter of contention whether a work’s aesthetic and artistic values are
independent of its moral, political, or epistemic stance or impact. Philosophy
of art has also dealt with the nature of taste, beauty, imagination,
creativity, repreaesthetics aesthetics 12 4065A- 12 sentation, expression, and
expressiveness; style; whether artworks convey knowledge or truth; the nature
of narrative and metaphor; the importance of genre; the ontological status of
artworks; and the character of our emotional responses to art. Work in the
field has always been influenced by philosophical theories of language or
meaning, and theories of knowledge and perception, and continues to be heavily
influenced by psychological and cultural theory, including versions of
semiotics, psychoanalysis, cognitive psychology, feminism, and Marxism. Some
theorists in the late twentieth century have denied that the aesthetic and the
“fine arts” can legitimately be separated out and understood as separate,
autonomous human phenomena; they argue instead that these conceptual categories
themselves manifest and reinforce certain kinds of cultural attitudes and power
relationships. These theorists urge that aesthetics can and should be eliminated
as a separate field of study, and that “the aesthetic” should not be conceived
as a special kind of value. They favor instead a critique of the roles that
images not only painting, but film, photography, and advertising, sounds,
narrative, and three-dimensional constructions have in expressing and shaping
human attitudes and experiences.
a fortiori argument: According to
Grice, an argument that moves from the premises that everything which possesses
a certain characteristics will possess some further characteristics and that
certain things possess the relevant characteristics to an eminent degree to the
conclusion that a fortiori even more so these things will possess the further
characteristics. The second premise is often left implicit – or implicated, as
Grice prefers, so a fortiori arguments are often enthymemes. A favourite
illustration by Grice of an a fortiori argument can be found in Plato’s Crito. We
owe gratitude and respect to our parents and so should do nothing to harm them.
However, athenians owe even greater gratitude and respect to the laws of
Athens. Therefore, a fortiori, Athenians should do nothing to harm those
laws.
agape: Grice would often
contrast ‘self-love’ with ‘agape’ and ‘benevolence.’ Strictly, agape, “a lovely
Grecian word,” is best rendered as the unselfish love for all persons. An
ethical theory according to which such love is the chief virtue, and actions
are good to the extent that they express it, is sometimes called agapism. Agape
is the Grecian word most often used for love in the New Testament, and is often
used in modern languages to signify whatever sort of love the writer takes to
be idealized there. In New Testament Grecian, however, it was probably a quite
general word for love, so that any ethical ideal must be found in the text’s
substantive claims, rather than in the linguistic meaning of the word. R.M.A.
agathon, Grecian word meaning ‘a good’ or ‘the good’. From Socrates onward,
agathon was taken to be a central object of philosophical inquiry; it has frequently
been assumed to be the goal of all rational action. Plato in the simile of the
sun in the Republic identified it with the Form of the Good, the source of
reality, truth, and intelligibility. Aristotle saw it as eudaimonia,
intellectual or practical virtue, a view that found its way, via Stoicism and
Neoplatonism, into Christianity. Modern theories of utility can be seen as
concerned with essentially the same Socratic question.
agitation: a Byzantine
feeling is a Ryleian agitation. If Grice
were to advance the not wholly plausible thesis that ‘to feel Byzantine’ is
just to have a an anti-rylean agitation which is caused by the thought that
Grice is or might *be* Byzantine, it would surely be ridiculous to criticise
Grice on the grounds that Grice saddles himself with an ontological commitment
to feelings, or to modes of feeling. And why? Well, because, alla Parsons, if a
quantifier is covertly involved at all, it will only be a universal quantifier
which in such a case as this is more than adequately handled by a
substitutional account of quantification. Grice’s situation vis-a-vis the
‘proposition’ is in no way different. In the idiolect of Ryle, “a serious
student of Grecian philosophy,” as Grice puts it, ‘emotion’ designates at least
three or four different kinds of things, which Ryle calls an ‘inclination, or
‘motive,’ a ‘mood’, an ‘agitation,’ or a ‘commotion,’ and a ‘feeling.’ An
inclination or a mood, including an agitation, is not occurrences and doest not
therefore take place either publicly or privately. It is a propensity, not an
act or state. An inclination is, however, a propensity of this or that kind,
and the kind is important. A feeling, on the other hand, IS an occurrence, but
the place that mention of it should take in a description of human behaviour is
very different from that which the standard theories accord to it. A
susceptibility to a specific agitation is on the same general footing with an
inclination, viz. that each is a general propensity and not an occurrence. An
agitation is not a motive. But an agitation does presuppose a motive, or rather
an agitataion presupposes a behaviour trend of which a motive is for us the
most interesting sort. There is however a matter of expression which
is the source of some confusion, even among Oxonian Wilde readers, and that did
confuse philosophical psychologists of the ability of G. F. Stout. An
expression may signify both an inclination and an agitation. But an expression
may signify anything but an agitations. Again, some other expression may signify
anything but an inclination. An expression like ‘uneasy’, ‘anxious’,
‘distressed’, ‘excited’, ‘startled’ always signifies an agitations. An
expression like ‘fond of fishing’, ‘keen on gardening’, ‘bent on becoming a
bishop’ never signifies an agitation. But an expression like ‘love’, ‘want’,
‘desire’, ‘proud’, ‘eager,’ or many others, stands sometimes for a simple
inclination and sometimes for an agitations which is resultant upon the
inclinations and interferences with the exercise of it. Thus ‘hungry’ for
‘having a good appetite’ means roughly ‘is eating or would eat heartily and
without sauces, etc..’ This is different from ‘hungry’ in which a person might
be said to be ‘too hungry to concentrate on his work’. Hunger in this second
expression is a distress, and requires for its existence the conjunction of an
appetite with the inability to eat. Similarly the way in which a boy is proud
of his school is different from the way in which he is speechless with pride on
being unexpectedly given a place in a school team. To remove a possible
misapprehension, it must be pointed out that an agitation may be quite
agreeable. A man may voluntarily subject himself to suspense, fatigue,
uncertainty, perplexity, fear and surprise in such practices as angling,
rowing, travelling, crossword puzzles, rock-climbing and joking. That a thing
like a thrill, a rapture, a surprise, an amusement and an relief is an
agitation is shown by the fact that we can say that someone is too much
thrilled, amused or relieved to act, think or talk coherently. It
is helpful to notice that, anyhow commonly, the expression which completes ‘pang of . . .’ or ‘chill of . . .’ denotes an
agitation. A feeling, such as a man feeling Byzantine, is intrinsically
connected with an agitation. But a feeling, e. g. of a man who is feeling
Byzantine, is not intrinsically connected with an inclination, save in so far
as the inclination is a factor in the agitation. This is no novel psychological
hypothesis; It is part of the logic of our descriptions of a feeling that a
feeling (such as a man feeling Byzantine) is a sign of an agitation and is not
an exercise of an inclination. A feeling, such as a man feeling Byzantine, in
other words, is not a thing of which it makes sense to ask from what motive it
issues. The same is true, for the same reasons, of any sign of any agitation. This
point shows why we were right to suggest above that a feeling (like a man
feeling Byzantine) does not belong directly to a simple inclination. An
inclination is a certain sort of proneness or readiness to do certain sorts of
things on purpose. These things are therefore describable as being done from
that motive. They are the exercises of the disposition that we call ‘a motive’.
A feeling (such as a man feeling Byzantine) is not from a motive and is
therefore not among the possible exercise of such a propensiy. The widespread
theory that a motive such as vanity, or affection, is in the first instance a
disposition to experience certain specific feeling is therefore absurd. There
may be, of course, a tendency to have a feeling, such as feeling Byzantine;
being vertiginous and rheumatic are such tendencies. But we do not try to
modify a tendency of these kinds by a sermon. What a feeling, such as being
Byzantine, does causally belong to is the agitation. A feeling (such as feeling
Byzantine) is a sign of an agitation in the same sort of way as a stomach-ache
is a sign of indigestion. Roughly, we do not, as the prevalent theory holds,
act purposively because we experience a feeling (such as feeling Byzantine); we
experience a feeling (such as feeling Byzantine), as we wince and shudder,
because we are inhibited from acting purposively.
A
sentimentalist is a man who indulges in this or that induced feeling (such as
feeling Byzantine) without acknowledging the fictitiousness of his agitation.
It seems to be generally supposed that ‘pleasure’ or ‘desire’ is always used to
signify a feeling. And there certainly are feelings which can be described as a
feeling of pleasure or desire. Some thrills, shocks, glows and ticklings are
feelings of delight, surprise, relief and amusement; and things like a
hankering, an itche, a gnawing and a yearning is a sign that something is both
wanted and missed. But the transports, surprises, reliefs and distresses of
which such a feeling is diagnosed, or mis-diagnosed, as a sign is not itself a
feeling. It is an agitation or a mood, just as are the transports and
distresses which a child betrays by his skips and his whimpers. Nostalgia is an
agitation and one which can be called a ‘desire’; but it is not merely a
feeling or series of feelings. There is the sense of ‘pleasure’ in which it is
commonly replaced by such expressions as ‘delight’, ‘transport’, ‘rapture’,
‘exultation’ and ‘joy’. These are expressions of this or that mood signifying this
or that agitation. There are two quite different usages of ‘emotion’, in which
we explain people’s behaviour by reference to emotions. In the first usage of
‘emotion,’ we are referring to the motives or inclinations from which more or
less intelligent actions are done. In a second usage we are referring to a
mood, including the agitation or perturbation of which some aimless movement
may be a sign. In neither of these usages are we asserting or implicating that
the overt behaviour is the effect of a felt turbulence in the agent’s stream of
consciousness. In a third usage of ‘emotion’, pangs and twinges are feelings or
emotions, but they are not, save per accidens, things by reference to which we
explain behaviour. They are things for which diagnoses are required, not things
required for the diagnoses of behaviour. Since a convulsion of merriment is not
the state of mind of the sober experimentalist, the enjoyment of a joke is also
not an introspectible happening. States of mind such as these more or less
violent agitations can be examined only in retrospect. Yet nothing disastrous
follows from this restriction. We are not shorter of information about panic or
amusement than about other states of mind. If retrospection can give us the
data we need for our knowledge of some states of mind, there is no reason why
it should not do so for all. And this is just what seems to be suggested by the
popular phrase ‘to catch oneself doing so and so’. We catch, as we pursue and
overtake, what is already running away from us. I catch myself daydreaming
about a mountain walk after, perhaps very shortly after, I have begun the
daydream; or I catch myself humming a particular air only when the first few
notes have already been hummed. Retrospection, prompt or delayed, is a genuine
process and one which is exempt from the troubles ensuing from the assumption
of multiply divided attention; it is also exempt from the troubles ensuing from
the assumption that violent agitations could be the objects of cool,
contemporary scrutiny. One may be aware that he is whistling ‘Tipperary’ and
not know that he is whistling it in order to give tte appearance of a
sang-froid which he does not feel. Or, again, he may be aware that he is
shamming sang-froid without knowing that the tremors which he is trying to hide
derive from the agitation of a guilty conscience.
agnoiologicum: Grice loved a
negative prefix. He was proud that he was never vulgar in publishing, like some
of his tutees – and that the number of his unpublications by far exceed the
number of his publications. To refute Hampshire with this intention and
certainty, he regaled the British Academy with the annual philosophical lecture
on intention and Uncertainty. While Grice thought that ‘knowledge’ was
overreated at Oxford (“Surely an examinee can be said to know that date of the
battle of Waterloo”) he could be agnoiological at times. From Grecian agnoia,
‘ignorance’, the study of ignorance, its quality, and its conditions. And then
there’s ‘agnosticism,’ from Grecian a-, ‘not’, and gnastos, ‘known’, term
invented by Thomas Henry Huxley in 1869 to denote the philosophical and
religious attitude of those who claim that metaphysical ideas can be neither
proved nor disproved. Huxley wrote, “I neither affirm nor deny the immortality
of man. I see no reason for believing it, but on the other hand, I have no
means of disproving it. I have no a priori objection to the doctrine.”
Agnosticism is a form of skepticism applied to metaphysics, especially theism.
The position is sometimes attributed to Kant, who held that we cannot have
knowledge of God or immortality but must be content with faith. Agnosticism
should not be confused with atheism, the belief that no god exists.
causatum: aetiologicum: from aitia: while Grice
would prefer ‘cause,’ he thought that the etymology of Grecian ‘aitia,’ in a
legal context, was interesting. On top, he was dissatisfied that Foucault never
realised that ‘les mots et les choses,’ etymologically, means, ‘motus et
causae.’ Grecian, cause. Originally referring to responsibility for a crime,
this Grecian term came to be used by philosophers to signify causality in a
somewhat broader sense than the English ‘cause’
the traditional rendering of aitia
can convey. An aitia is any answer to a why-question. According to
Aristotle, how such questions ought to be answered is a philosophical issue
addressed differently by different philosophers. He himself distinguishes four
types of answers, and thus four aitiai, by distinguishing different types of
questions: 1 Why is the statue heavy? Because it is made of bronze material
aitia. 2 Why did Persians invade Athens? Because the Athenians had raided their
territory moving or efficient aitia. 3 Why are the angles of a triangle equal
to two right angles? Because of the triangle’s nature formal aitia. 4 Why did
someone walk after dinner? Because or for the sake of his health final aitia.
Only the second of these would typically be called a cause in English. Though
some render aitia as ‘explanatory principle’ or ‘reason’, these expressions
inaptly suggest a merely mental existence; instead, an aitia is a thing or
aspect of a thing. The study of the causatum in Grice is key. It appears in
“Meaning,” because he starts discussing Stevenson whom Grice dubs a
‘causalist.’ It continues with Grice on ‘knowledge,’ and ‘willing’ in
“Intention and Uncertainty.” Also in “Aspects of reasoning.”
albertus de saxonia: “Saxonia sounds
like a large place – but we do not know where in Saxony came from – I often wonder
if Albertus of Saxony is not underinformative.” – Grice. Like Grice, a
terminist logician, from lower Saxony who taught in the arts faculty at Paris.
Under the influence of Buridan and Nicholas of Oresme, he turned to playful
dialectics. He was a founder of the “Universitas Vienna” and was bishop of
Halberstadt. His works on logic include Logic, Questions on the Posterior
Analytics, Sophismata, Treatise on Obligations, and Insolubilia. He also wrote
questions on Aristotle’s physical works and on John of Sacrobosco’s De Sphaera,
and short treatises on squaring the circle and on the ratio of the diameter to
the side of a square. His work is competent but rarely original. Grice read
most of them, and was surprised that Albertus never coined ‘implicaturum’!
albertus magnus: Dominican
Griceian philosopher. As a Parisian master of theology, he served on a
commission that condemned the Talmud. He left Paris to found the first
Dominican studium generale at Cologne. Albert was repeatedly asked to be an
arbiter and peacemaker. After serving briefly as bishop of Regensburg, he was
ordered to preach the crusade. He spent his last years writing in Cologne.
Albert contributed to philosophy chiefly as a commentator on Aristotle,
although he occasionally reached different conclusions from Aristotle.
Primarily, Albert was a theologian, as is evident from his extensive commentary
on Peter Lombard’s Sentences and his commentaries on the Old and New
Testaments. As a theologian, he customarily developed his thought by commenting
on traditional texts. For Albert, Aristotle offered knowledge ascertainable
using reason, just as Scripture, based on God’s word, tells of the
supernatural. Albert saw Aristotle’s works, many newly available, as an
encyclopedic compendium of information on the natural universe; included here
is the study of social and political conditions and ethical obligations, for
Aristotelian “natural knowledge” deals with human nature as well as natural
history. Aristotle is the Philosopher; however, unlike Holy Scripture, he must
be corrected in places. Like Holy Scripture, though, Aristotle is occasionally
obscure. To rectify these shortcomings one must rely on other authorities: in
the case of Holy Scripture, reference is to the church fathers and established
interpreters; in the case of Aristotle, to the Peripatetics. The term
‘Peripatetics’ extends to modern as well as ancient authors al-Farabi, Avicenna Ibn-Sina, and Averroes
Ibn-Rushd, as well as Themistius and Alexander of Aphrodisias; even Seneca,
Maimonides, and “our” Boethius are included. For the most part, Albert saw
Plato through the eyes of Aristotle and Averroes, since apart from the Timaeus
very little of Plato’s work was available in Latin. Albert considered the Liber
de causis a work of Aristotle, supplemented by alFarabi, Avicenna, and
al-Ghazali and tr. into Latin. When he commented on the Liber de causis, Albert
was not aware that this Neoplatonic work
which speaks of the world emanating from the One as from a first
cause was based on Proclus and
ultimately on Plotinus. But Albert’s student, Aquinas, who had better
translations of Aristotle, recognized that the Liber de causis was not an
Aristotelian work. Albert’s metaphysics, which is expounded in his commentaries
on Aristotle’s Metaphysics on the Liber de causis, contains profoundly
contradictory elements. His inclination to synthesis led him to attempt to
reconcile these elements as on social
and ecclesiastical questions he often sought peace through compromise. In his
Metaphysics and Physics and in his On the Heavens and On Generation and
Corruption, Aristotle presented the world as ever-changing and taught that an
unmoved mover “thought thinking itself” maintained everything in movement and
animation by allowing its spiritual nature to be seen in all its cold,
unapproachable beauty. The Liber de causis, on the other hand, develops the
theory that the world emanates from the One, causing everything in the world in
its pantheistic creativity, so that the caused world returns in mystic harmony
to the One. Thus Albert’s Aristotelian commentaries culminated with his
commentary on a work whose pseudo-Aristotelian character he was unable to
recognize. Nevertheless, the Christian Neoplatonism that Albert placed on an
Aristotelian basis was to exert an influence for centuries. In natural
philosophy, Albert often arrived at views independent of Aristotle. According
to Aristotle’s Physics, motion belongs to no single category; it is incomplete
being. Following Avicenna and Averroes, Albert asks whether “becoming black,”
e.g. which ceases when change ceases and
blackness is finally achieved differs
from blackness essentially essentia or only in its being esse. Albert establishes,
contrary to Avicenna, that the distinction is only one of being. In his discussions
of place and space, stimulated by Avicenna, Albert also makes an original
contribution. Only two dimensions width
and breadth are essential to place, so
that a fluid in a bottle is framed by the inner surface of the bottle.
According to Albert, the significance of the third dimension, depth, is more
modest, but nonetheless important. Consider a bucket of water: its base is the
essential part, but its round walls maintain the cohesion of the water. For
Aristotle, time’s material foundation is distinct from its formal definition.
Materially, the movement of the fixed stars is basic, although time itself is
neither movement nor change. Rather, just as before and after are continuous in
space and there are earlier and later moments in movement as it proceeds
through space, so time being the number
of motion has earlier and later moments
or “nows.” The material of time consists of the uninterrupted flow of the
indivisible nows, while time’s form and essential expression is number.
Following al-Farabi and Avicenna, Albert’s interpretation of these doctrines
emphasizes not only the uninterrupted continuity of the flow of “nows,” but
also the quantity of time, i.e., the series of discrete, separate, and clearly
distinct numbers. Albert’s treatment of time did not lend itself well to later
consideration of time as a dimension; his concept of time is therefore not well
suited to accommodate our unified concept of space-time. The use of the
pseudo-Aristotelian De proprietatibus elementorum in De causis proprietatum
elementorum gave Albert’s worldview a strong astrological flavor. At issue here
is how the planets influence the earth and mankind. Particularly important is
the influence of Jupiter and Saturn on fire and the seas; when increased, it
could produce fiery conflagrations, and when circumscribed, floods. Albert was
encyclopedic: a scientist and scholar as well as a philosopher and theologian.
In addition to the works mentioned, he produced commentaries on
Pseudo-Dionysius, a Summa de creaturis, a Summa Theologica, and many other
treatises. Unlike other commentators, his exposition was continuous, an
extensive paraphrase; he provided a complete Latin and Christian philosophy.
Even in his lifetime, he was a named authority; according to Roger Bacon, his views
were often given as much weight as those of Aristotle, Avicenna, and Averroes.
His students or followers include Aquinas, Ulrich of Strassburg, Theodoric of
Freiberg, Giles of Lessines, Meister Eckhart, Johannes Tauler, Henry Suso, Jan
van Ruysbroeck, and H. P. Grice.
alethic: Grice could not
find a good word for ‘verum,’ and so he borrowed ‘alethic’ from, but never
returned it to, von Wright. Under the alethic modalities, Grice, as
historically, included the four central ways or modes in which a given
proposition might be true or false: necessity, contingency, possibility, and
impossibility. The term ‘alethic’ derives from Grecian aletheia, ‘truth’. These
modalities, and their logical interconnectedness, can be characterized as
follows. A proposition that is true but possibly false is contingently true
e.g., that Aristotle taught Alexander; one that is true and not-possibly i.e.,
“impossibly” false is necessarily true e.g., that red things are colored.
Likewise, a proposition that is false but possibly true is contingently false
e.g., that there are no tigers; and one that is false and not-possibly true is
necessarily false e.g., that seven and five are fourteen. Though any one of the
four modalities can be defined in terms of any other, necessity and possibility
are generally taken to be the more fundamental notions, and most systems of
alethic modal logic take one or the other as basic. Distinct modal systems
differ chiefly in regard to their treatment of iterated modalities, as in the
proposition It is necessarily true that it is possibly true that it is possibly
true that there are no tigers. In the weakest of the most common systems,
usually called T, every iterated modality is distinct from every other. In the
stronger system S4, iterations of any given modality are redundant. So, e.g.,
the above proposition is equivalent to It is necessarily true that it is
possibly true that there are no tigers. In the strongest and most widely
accepted system S5, all iteration is redundant. Thus, the two propositions
above are both equivalent simply to It is possibly true that there are no
tigers.
alexanderian: s.– what Grice
called “A Balliol hegelian,” philosopher, tuteed at Balliol by A. C. Bradley,
Oxford, and taught for most of his career at the of Manchester. His aim, which he most fully
realized in Space, Time, and Deity 0, was to provide a realistic account of the
place of mind in nature. He described nature as a series of levels of existence
where irreducible higher-level qualities emerge inexplicably when lower levels
become sufficiently complex. At its lowest level reality consists of
space-time, a process wherein points of space are redistributed at instants of
time and which might also be called pure motion. From complexities in
space-time matter arises, followed by secondary qualities, life, and mind.
Alexander thought that the still-higher quality of deity, which characterizes
the whole universe while satisfying religious sentiments, is now in the process
of emerging from mind.
alexanderian: related to
Alexander de Aphrodisias: ““Alexander of Aphrodisias” should not be confused
with Samuel Alexander, a fellow of Bradley, even if they are next in your
philosophical dictionary!” – Grice. Grecian philosopher, one of the foremost
commentators on Aristotle in late antiquity. He exercised considerable
influence on later Grecian and Roman philosophy through to the Renaissance. On
the problem of universals, Alexander endorses a brand of conceptualism:
although several particulars may share a single, common nature, this nature
does not exist as a universal except while abstracted in thought from the
circumstances that accompany its particular instantiations. Regarding
Aristotle’s notorious distinction between the “agent” and “patient” intellects
in On the Soul III.5, Alexander identifies the agent intellect with God, who,
as the most intelligible entity, makes everything else intelligible. As its own
self-subsistent object, this intellect alone is imperishable; the human
intellect, in contrast, perishes at death. Of Alexander’s many commentaries,
only those on Aristotle’s Metaphysics Ad, Prior Analytics I, Topics, On the
Senses, and Meterologics are extant. We also have two polemical treatises, On
Fate and On Mixture, directed against the Stoics; a psychological treatise, the
De anima based on Aristotle’s; as well as an assortment of essays including the
De intellectu and his Problems and Solutions. Nothing is known of Alexander’s
life apart from his appointment by the emperor Severus to a chair in Aristotelian
philosophy between and 209.
hales: from Alexander of
Hales. Grice called William of Occam “Occam,” William of Sherwood, “Shyrewood,”
and Alexander of Hales “Hales,” – why, I wish people would call me “Harborne,”
and not Grice!” – Grice. English Franciscan theologian, known as the Doctor
Irrefragabilis. The first to teach theology by lecturing on the Sentences of
Peter Lombard, Alexander’s emphasis on speculative theology initiated the
golden age of Scholasticism. Alexander wrote commentaries on the Psalms and the
Gospels; his chief works include his Glossa in quattuor libros sententiarum,
Quaestiones disputatatae antequam esset frater, and Quaestiones quodlibetales.
Alexander did not complete the Summa fratris Alexandri; Pope Alexander IV
ordered the Franciscans to complete the Summa Halesiana in 1255. Master of
theology in 1222, Alexander played an important role in the history of Paris,
writing parts of Gregory IX’s Parens scientiarum 1231. He also helped negotiate
the peace between England and France. He gave up his position as canon of
Lichfield and archdeacon of Coventry to become a Franciscan, the first
Franciscan master of theology; his was the original Franciscan chair of
theology at Paris. Among the Franciscans, his most prominent disciples include
St. Bonaventure, Richard Rufus of Cornwall, and John of La Rochelle, to whom he
resigned his chair in theology near the end of his life.
algorithm: Grice’s term for
‘decision procedure,’ a clerical or effective procedure that can be applied to
any of a class of certain symbolic inputs and that will in a finite time and
number of steps eventuate in a result in a corresponding symbolic output. A
function for which an algorithm sometimes more than one can be given is an
algorithmic function. The following are common examples: a given n, finding the
nth prime number; b differentiating a polynomial; c finding the greatest common
divisor of x and y the Euclidean algorithm; and d given two numbers x, y,
deciding whether x is a multiple of y. When an algorithm is used to calculate
values of a numerical function, as in a, b, and c, the function can also be
described as algorithmically computable, effectively computable, or just
computable. Algorithms are generally agreed to have the following properties which made them essential to the theory of
computation and the development of the Church-Turing thesis i an algorithm can be given by a finite
string of instructions, ii a computation device or agent can carry out or compute
in accordance with the instructions, iii there will be provisions for
computing, storing, and recalling steps in a computation, iv computations can
be carried out in a discrete and stepwise fashion in, say, a digital computer,
and v computations can be carried out in a deterministic fashion in, say, a
deterministic version of a Turing machine.
allais’s paradox: a puzzle about
rationality, discussed by H. P. Grice, “Aspects of reason,” devised by Maurice
Allais b. 1. Leonard Savage advanced the
sure-thing principle, which states that a rational agent’s ranking of a pair of
gambles having the same consequence in a state S agrees with her ranking of any
other pair of gambles the same as the first pair except for having some other
common consequence in S. Allais devised an apparent counterexample with four
gambles involving a 100-ticket lottery. The table lists prizes in units of
$100,000. Ticket Numbers Gambles 1 2 11
12 100 A 5 5 5 B 0 25 5 C 5 5 0 D 0 25 0
Changing A’s and B’s common consequence for tickets 12100 from 5 to 0 yields C
and D respectively. Hence the sure-thing principle prohibits simultaneously
preferring A to B, and D to C. Yet most people have these preferences, which
seem coherent. This conflict generates the paradox. Savage presented the
sure-thing principle in The Foundations of Statistics 4. Responding to
preliminary drafts of that work, Allais formulated his counterexample in “The
Foundations of a Positive Theory of Choice Involving Risk and a Criticism of
the Postulates and Axioms of the School”
2.
alnwick: English
Franciscan theologian. William studied under Duns Scotus at Paris, and wrote
the Reportatio Parisiensia, a central source for Duns Scotus’s teaching. In his
own works, William opposed Scotus on the univocity of being and haecceitas.
Some of his views were attacked by Ockham.
alstonian: w. p. cites H. P.
Grice as ideationist. Philosopher widely acknowledged as one of the most
important contemporary epistemologists and one of the most important
philosophers of religion of the twentieth century. He is particularly known for
his argument that putative perception of God is epistemologically on all fours
with putative perception of everyday material objects. Alston graduated from
Centenary and the U.S. Army. A fine musician, he had to choose between
philosophy and music. Philosophy won out; he received his Ph.D. from the of Chicago and began his philosophical career
at the of Michigan, where he taught for
twenty-two years. Since 0 he has taught at Syracuse. Although his dissertation
and some of his early work were on Whitehead, he soon turned to philosophy of
language Philosophy of Language, 4. Since the early 0s Alston has concentrated
on epistemology and philosophy of religion. In epistemology he has defended
foundationalism although not classical foundationalism, investigated epistemic
justification with unusual depth and penetration, and called attention to
important levels distinctions. His chief works here are Epistemic
Justification, a collection of essays; and The Reliability of Sense Perception.
His chief work in philosophy of religion is Divine Nature and Human Language, a
collection of essays on metaphysical and epistemological topics; and Perceiving
God. The latter is a magisterial argument for the conclusion that experiential
awareness of God, more specifically perception of God, makes an important
contribution to the grounds of religious belief. In addition to this scholarly
work, Alston was a founder of the Society of Christian Philosophers, a
professional society with more than 1,100 members, and the founding editor of
Faith and Philosophy.
althusserian: a philosopher
Grice called a ‘hegelian’. LouisL Marxist philosopher whose publication in 5 of
two collections of essays, Pour Marx “For Marx” and Lire le Capital “Reading
Capital”, made him a sensation in
intellectual circles and attracted a large international readership. The
English translations of these texts in 9 and 0, respectively, helped shape the
development of Marxist thought in the English-speaking world throughout the 0s.
Drawing on the work of non-positivist
historians and philosophers of science, especially Bachelard, Althusser
proclaimed the existence of an “epistemological break” in Marx’s work,
occurring in the mid-1840s. What preceded this break was, in Althusser’s view,
a prescientific theoretical humanism derived from Feuerbach and ultimately from
Hegel. What followed it, Althusser maintained, was a science of history a
all-things-considered reason Althusser, Louis 23 4065A- 23 development as monumental, potentially,
as the rise of the new sciences of nature in the seventh century. Althusser
argued that the nature and even the existence of this new kind of science had
yet to be acknowledged, even by Marx himself. It therefore had to be
reconstructed from Marx’s writings, Das Kapital especially, and also discerned
in the political practice of Lenin and other like-minded revolutionaries who
implicitly understood what Marx intended. Althusser did little, however, to
elaborate the content of this new science. Rather, he tirelessly defended it
programmatically against rival construals of Marxism. In so doing, he took
particular aim at neo-Hegelian and “humanistic” currents in the larger Marxist
culture and implicitly in the Communist
Party, to which he belonged throughout his adult life. After 8, Althusser’s
influence in France faded. But he continued to teach at l’École Normale
Superieure and to write, making important contributions to political theory and
to understandings of “ideology” and related concepts. He also faced increasingly
severe bouts of mania and depression. In 0, in what the courts deemed an episode of “temporary
insanity,” he strangled his wife. Althusser avoided prison, but spent much of
the 0s in mental institutions. During this period he wrote two extraordinary memoirs,
L’avenir dure longtemps “The Future Lasts Forever” and Les faits “The Facts”,
published posthumously in 2.
altogether nice
girl:
Or Grice’s altogether nice girl. Grice quotes from the music-hall ditty, “Every
[sic] nice girl loves a sailor” (WoW:33). He uses this for his account of
multiple quantification. There is a reading where the emissor may implicate
that every nice girl is such that he loves one sailor, viz. Grice. But if the
existential quantifier is not made dominant, the uniqueness is disimplicated.
Grice admits that not every nominalist will be contented with the
‘metaphysical’ status of ‘the altogether nice girl.’ The ‘one-at-a-time sailor’
is her counterpart. And they inhabit the class of LOVE.
ambrosius: saint. Grice:
“Not to be confused with Ambrose and his orchestra – sweet!” – on altruism.
known as Ambrose of Milan c.33997, Roman church leader and theologian. While
bishop of Milan, he not only led the struggle against the Arian heresy and its
political manifestations, but offered new models for preaching, for Scriptural
exegesis, and for hymnody. His works also contributed to medieval Latin
philosophy. Ambrose’s appropriation of Neoplatonic doctrines was noteworthy in
itself, and it worked powerfully on and through Augustine. Ambrose’s commentary
on the account of creation in Genesis, his Hexaemeron, preserved for medieval
readers many pieces of ancient natural history and even some altruism Ambrose,
Saint 24 4065A- 24 elements of physical
explanation. Perhaps most importantly, Ambrose engaged ancient philosophical
ethics in the search for moral lessons that marks his exegesis of Scripture; he
also reworked Cicero’s De officiis as a treatise on the virtues and duties of
Christian living.
amicus: philia and eros –
Grice on Aristotle’s aporia of friendship -- Eros, the Grecian god of erotic
love. Eros came to be symbolic of various aspects of love, first appearing in
Hesiod in opposition to reason. In general, however, Eros was seen by Grecians
e.g., Parmenides as a unifying force. In Empedocles, it is one of two external
forces explaining the history of the cosmos, the other being Strife. These
forces resemble the “hidden harmony” of Heraclitus. The Symposium of Plato is
the best-known ancient discussion of Eros, containing speeches from various
standpoints mythical, sophistic, etc.
Socrates says he has learned from the priestess Diotima of a nobler form of
Eros in which sexual desire can be developed into the pursuit of understanding
the Form of beauty. The contrast between agape and Eros is found first in
Democritus. This became important in Christian accounts of love. In
Neoplatonism, Eros referred to the mystical union with Being sought by
philosophers. Eros has become important recently in the work of Continental
writers.
ammonius: saccas early
third century A.D., Platonist philosopher. He apparently served early in the
century as the teacher of the philosopher Origen. He attracted the attention of
Plotinus, who came to the city in 232 in search of philosophical enlightenment
Porphyry, Life of Plotinus 3. Ammonius the epithet ‘Saccas’ seems to mean ‘the
bagman’ was undoubtedly a charismatic figure, but it is not at all clear what,
if any, were his distinctive doctrines, though he seems to have been influenced
by Numenius. He wrote nothing, and may be thought of, in E. R. Dodds’s words,
as the Socrates of Neoplatonism.
analyticum: Porphyry couldn’t
find a Latinate for ‘analyticum’ – ‘analyisis’ is like ‘se-paratio.’ But even
in Grecian, ‘analysis’ and synthesis are not real opposite – since ‘synthesis’
neatly comes as ‘compositio’ -- analysis, the process of breaking up a concept,
proposition, linguistic complex, or fact into its simple or ultimate
constituents. That on which the analysis is done is called the analysandum, and
that which does the analysis is called the analysans. A number of the most
important philosophers of the twentieth century, including Russell, Moore, and
the early Vitters, have argued that philosophical analysis is the proper method
of philosophy. But the practitioners of analytic philosophy have disagreed
about what kind of thing is to be analyzed. For example, Moore tried to analyze
sense-data into their constituent parts. Here the analysandum is a complex
psychological fact, the having of a sense-datum. More commonly, analytic
philosophers have tried to analyze concepts or propositions. This is conceptual
analysis. Still others have seen it as their task to give an analysis of
various kinds of sentences e.g., those involving
proper names or definite descriptions. This is linguistic analysis. Each of
these kinds of analysis faces a version of a puzzle that has come to be called
the paradox of analysis. For linguistic analyses, the paradox can be expressed
as follows: for an analysis to be adequate, the analysans must be synonymous
with the analysandum; e.g., if ‘male sibling’ is to analyze ‘brother’, they
must mean the same; but if they are synonymous, then ‘a brother is a male
sibling’ is synonymous with ‘a brother is a brother’; but the two sentences do not
seem synonymous. Expressed as a dilemma, the paradox is that any proposed
analysis would seem to be either inadequate because the analysans and the
analysandum are not synonymous or uninformative because they are synonymous. Analytic philosophy is an umbrella term
currently used to cover a diverse assortment of philosophical techniques and
tendencies. As in the case of chicken-sexing, it is relatively easy to identify
analytic philosophy and philosophers, though difficult to say with any
precision what the criteria are. Analytic philosophy is sometimes called Oxford
philosophy or linguistic philosophy, but these labels are, at least,
misleading. Whatever else it is, analytic philosophy is manifestly not a
school, doctrine, or body of accepted propositions. At Cambridge, analytic
philosophers are the intellectual heirs of Russell, Moore, and Vitters,
philosophers who self-consciously pursued “philosophical analysis” in the early
part of the twentieth century. Analysis, as practiced by Russell and Moore, concerned
not language per se, but concepts and propositions. In their eyes, while it did
not exhaust the domain of philosophy, analysis provided a vital tool for laying
bare the logical form of reality. Vitters, in the Tractatus
Logico-Philosophicus, contended, though obliquely, that the structure of
language reveals the structure of the world; every meaningful sentence is
analyzable into atomic constituents that designate the finegrained constituents
of reality. This “Tractarian” view was one Vitters was to renounce in his later
work, but it had considerable influence within the Vienna Circle in the 0s, and
in the subsequent development of logical positivism in the 0s and 0s. Carnap
and Ayer, both exponents of positivism, held that the task of philosophy was not
to uncover elusive metaphysical truths, but to provide analyses of scientific
sentences. Other sentences, those in ethics, for instance, were thought to lack
“cognitive significance.” Their model was Russell’s theory of descriptions,
which provided a technique for analyzing away apparent commitments to
suspicious entities. Meanwhile, a number of former proponents of analysis,
influenced by Vitters, had taken up what came to be called ordinary language
philosophy. Philosophers of this persuasion focused on the role of words in the
lives of ordinary speakers, hoping thereby to escape long-standing
philosophical muddles. These muddles resulted, they thought, from a natural
tendency, when pursuing philosophical theses, to be misled by the grammatical
form of sentences in which those questions were posed. A classic illustration
might be Heidegger’s supposition that ‘nothing’ must designate something,
though a very peculiar something. Today, it is difficult to find much unanimity
in the ranks of analytic philosophers. There is, perhaps, an implicit respect
for argument and clarity, an evolving though informal agreement as to what
problems are and are not tractable, and a conviction that philosophy is in some
sense continuous with science. The practice of analytic philosophers to address
one another rather than the broader public has led some to decry philosophy’s
“professionalization” and to call for a return to a pluralistic,
community-oriented style of philosophizing. Analytic philosophers respond by
pointing out that analytic techniques and standards have been well represented
in the history of philosophy. Analyticity. H. P. Grice, “In defence of a
dogma,” in Studies in the way of words. the analyticsynthetic distinction, the
distinction, made famous by Kant, according to which an affirmative
subject-predicate statement proposition, judgment is called analytic if the
predicate concept is contained in the subject concept, and synthetic otherwise.
The statement ‘All red roses are red’ is analytic, since the concept ‘red’ is
contained in the concept ‘red roses’. ‘All roses are red’ is synthetic, since
the concept ‘red’ is not contained in the concept ‘roses’. The denial of an
affirmative subject-predicate statement entails a contradiction if it is
analytic. E.g., ‘Not all red roses are red’ entails ‘Some roses are both red
and not red’. One concept may be contained in another, in Kant’s sense, even
though the terms used to express them are not related as part to whole. Since
‘biped’ means ‘two-footed animal’, the concept ‘two-footed’ is contained in the
concept ‘biped’. It is accordingly analytic that all bipeds are two-footed. The
same analytic statement is expressed by the synonymous sentences ‘All bipeds
are two-footed’ and ‘All two-footed animals are two-footed’. Unlike statements,
sentences cannot be classified as analytic or synthetic except relative to an
interpretation. analytical jurisprudence analyticsynthetic distinction 26
4065A- 26 Witness ‘All Russian teachers
are Russian’, which in one sense expresses the analytic statement ‘All teachers
that are Russian are Russian’, and in another the synthetic statement ‘All
teachers of Russian are Russian’. Kant’s innovation over Leibniz and Hume lay
in separating the logicosemantic analyticsynthetic distinction from the
epistemological a prioria posteriori distinction and from the modalmetaphysical
necessarycontingent distinction. It seems evident that any analytic statement
is a priori knowable without empirical evidence and necessary something that
could not be false. The converse is highly controversial. Kant and his
rationalist followers maintain that some a priori and necessary statements are
synthetic, citing examples from logic ‘Contradictions are impossible’, ‘The
identity relation is transitive’, mathematics ‘The sum of 7 and 5 is 12’, ‘The
straight line between two points is the shortest’, and metaphysics ‘Every event
is caused’. Empiricists like J. S. Mill, Carnap, Ayer, and C. I. Lewis argue
that such examples are either synthetic a posteriori or analytic a priori.
Philosophers since Kant have tried to clarify the analyticsynthetic
distinction, and generalize it to all statements. On one definition, a sentence
is analytic on a given interpretation provided it is “true solely in virtue of
the meaning or definition of its terms.” The truth of any sentence depends in
part on the meanings of its terms. `All emeralds are green’ would be false,
e.g., if ‘emerald’ meant ‘ruby’. What makes the sentence synthetic, it is
claimed, is that its truth also depends on the properties of emeralds, namely,
their being green. But the same holds for analytic sentences: the truth of ‘All
red roses are red’ depends on the properties of red roses, namely, their being
red. Neither is true solely in virtue of meaning. A more adequate
generalization defines an analytic statement as a formal logical truth: one
“true in virtue of its logical form,” so that all statements with the same form
are true. In terms of sentences under an interpretation, an analytic truth is
an explicit logical truth one whose surface structure represents its logical
form or one that becomes an explicit logical truth when synonyms are
substituted. The negative statement that tomorrow is not both Sunday and not
Sunday is analytic by this definition, because all statements of the form : p
& - p are true. Kant’s definition is obtained as a special case by
stipulating that the predicate of an affirmative subjectpredicate statement is
contained in the subject provided the statement is logically true. On a third
generalization, ‘analytic’ denotes any statement whose denial entails a
contradiction. Subject S contains predicate P provided being S entails being P.
Whether this is broader or narrower than the second generalization depends on
how ‘entailment’, ‘logical form’, and ‘contradiction’ are defined. On some
construals, ‘Red is a color’ counts as analytic on the third generalization its
denial entails ‘Something is and is not a color’ but not on the second ‘red’
and ‘colored’ are logically unstructured, while the rulings are reversed for a
counterfactual conditional like ‘If this were a red rose it would be red’.
Following Quine, many have denied any distinction between analytic and
synthetic statements. Some arguments presume the problematic “true by meaning”
definition. Others are that: 1 the distinction cannot be defined without using
related notions like ‘meaning’, ‘concept’, and ‘statement’, which are neither
extensional nor definable in terms of behavior; 2 some statements like ‘All
cats are animals’ are hard to classify as analytic or synthetic; and 3 no
statement allegedly is immune from rejection in the face of new empirical
evidence. If these arguments were sound, however, the distinction between
logical truths and others would seem equally dubious, a conclusion seldom
embraced. Some describe a priori truths, both synthetic and analytic, as
conceptual truths, on the theory that they are all true in virtue of the nature
of the concepts they contain. Conceptual truths are said to have no “factual
content” because they are about concepts rather than things in the actual
world. While it is natural to classify a priori truths together, the proffered
theory is questionable. As indicated above, all truths hold in part because of
the identity of their concepts, and in part because of the nature of the
objects they are about. It is a fact that all emeralds are emeralds, and this
proposition is about emeralds, not concepts.
analyticum-a-priori: For Grice, an oxymoron, since surely
‘analyticum-a-posteriori’ is an oxymoron. R. A. Wollheim. London-born
philosopher, BPhil Oxon, Balliol (under D. Marcus) and All Souls. Examined by H. P. Grice. “What’s two times
two?” Wollheim treasured that examination. It was in the context of a
discussion of J. S. Mill and I. Kant, for whom addition and multiplication are
‘synthetic’ – a priori for Kant, a posteriori for Mill. Grice was trying to
provide a counterexample to Mill’s thesis that all comes via deduction or
induction.
necessitatum: ananke, when
feeling very Grecian, Grice would use ‘ananke,’ instead of ‘must,’ which he
thought too English! Grecian, necessity. The term was used by early Grecian
philosophers for a constraining or moving natural force. In Parmenides frg. 8,
line 30 ananke encompasses reality in limiting bonds; according to Diogenes
Laertius, Democrianamnesis ananke 27 4065A-
27 tus calls the vortex that generates the cosmos ananke; Plato Timaeus
47e ff. refers to ananke as the irrational element in nature, which reason
orders in creating the physical world. As used by Aristotle Metaphysics V.5,
the basic meaning of ‘necessary’ is ‘that which cannot be otherwise’, a sense
that includes logical necessity. He also distinguishes Physics II.9 between
simple and hypothetical necessity conditions that must hold if something is to
occur.
anaxagoras: Grecian and
pre-Griceian philosopher who was the first of the pre-Socratics to teach in
Athens c.480450, where he influenced leading intellectuals such as Pericles and
Euripides. He left Athens when he was prosecuted for impiety. Writing in
response to Parmenides, he elaborated a theory of matter according to which
nothing comes into being or perishes. The ultimate realities are stuffs such as
water and earth, flesh and bone, but so are contraries such as hot and cold,
likewise treated as stuffs. Every phenomenal substance has a portion of every
elemental stuff, and there are no minimal parts of anything, but matter takes
on the phenomenal properties of whatever predominates in the mixture.
Anaxagoras posits an indefinite number of elemental stuffs, in contrast to his
contemporary Empedocles, who requires only four elements; but Anaxagoras
follows Parmenides more rigorously, allowing no properties or substances to
emerge that were not already present in the cosmos as its constituents. Thus
there is no ultimate gap between appearance and reality: everything we perceive
is real. In Anaxagoras’s cosmogony, an initial chaos of complete mixture gives
way to an ordered world when noûs mind begins a vortex motion that separates
cosmic masses of ether the bright upper air, air, water, and earth. Mind is
finer than the stuffs and is found in living things, but it does not mix with
stuffs. Anaxagoras’s theory of mind provides the first hint of a mindmatter
dualism. Plato and Aristotle thought his assigning a cosmic role to mind made
him sound like “a sober man” among his contemporaries, but they were
disappointed that he did not exploit his idea to provide teleological explanations
of natural phenomena.
anaximander:: Grecian and
pre-Griceian philosopher and cosmologist, reputedly the student and successor
of Thales in the Milesian school. He described the cosmos as originating from
apeiron the boundless by a process of separating off; a disk-shaped earth was
formed, surrounded by concentric heavenly rings of fire enclosed in air. At
“breathing holes” in the air we see jets of fire, which are the stars, moon,
and sun. The earth stays in place because there is no reason for it to tend one
way or another. The seasons arise from alternating periods where hot and dry or
wet and anaphor Anaximander 28 4065A-
28 cold powers predominate, governed by a temporal process figuratively
portrayed as the judgment of Time. Anaximander drew a map of the world and
explained winds, rain, and lightning by naturalistic hypotheses. He also
described the emergence of life in a way that prefigures the theory of
evolution. Anaximander’s interest in cosmology and cosmogony and his brilliant
conjectures set the major questions for later preSocratics.
anaximenes: of Miletus:
Grecian and pre-Griceian philosopher, a
pre-Socratic who, following in the tradition of the Milesians Thales and
Anaximander, speculated about cosmology and meteorology. The source arche of
the cosmos is air aer, originally mist, which by a process of rarefaction
becomes fire, and by a process of condensation becomes wind, clouds, water,
earth, and stones. Air is divine and causes life. The earth is flat and rides
on a cushion of air, while a heavenly firmament revolves about it like a felt
cap. Anaximenes also explained meteorological phenomena and earthquakes.
Although less innovative than his predecessor Anaximander, he made progress in
naturalistic explanations by appealing to a quantitative process of rarefaction
and condensation rather than to mythical processes involving quasi-personal
agents.
ancestry: Studied by H. P.
Grice. Of a given relation R, the relation also called the transitive closure
of R that relates one given individual to a second if and only if the first can
be “reached” from the second by repeated “applications” of the given relation
R. The “ancestor” relation is the ancestral of the parent relation since one
person is an ancestor of a second if the first is a parent of the second or the
first is a parent of a parent of the second or the first is a parent of a
parent of a parent of the second, and so on. Frege discovered a simple method
of giving a materially adequate and formally correct definition of the
ancestral of a given relation in terms of the relation itself plus logical
concepts. This method is informally illustrated as follows. In order for one
person A to be an ancestor of a second person B it is necessary and sufficient
for A to have every property that belongs to every parent of B and that belongs
to every parent of any person to whom it belongs. This and other similar
methods made possible the reduction of all numerical concepts to those of zero
and successor, which Frege then attempted to reduce to concepts of pure logic.
Frege’s definition of the ancestral has become a paradigm in modern analytic
philosophy as well as a historical benchmark of the watershed between
traditional logic and modern logic. It demonstrates the exactness of modern
logical analysis and, in comparison, the narrowness of traditional logic.
andronicus: Grecian
philosopher, a leading member of the Lyceum who was largely responsible for
establishing the canon of Aristotle’s works still read today. He also edited
the works of Theophrastus. At the time, Aristotle was known primarily for his philosophical
dialogues, only fragments of which now survive; his more methodical treatises
had stopped circulating soon after his death. By producing the first systematic
edition of Aristotle’s corpus, Andronicus revived study of the treatises, and
the resulting critical debates dramatically affected the course of philosophy.
Little is recorded about Andronicus’s labors; but besides editing the texts and
discussing titles, arrangement, and authenticity, he sought to explicate and
assess Aristotle’s thought. In so doing, he and his colleagues initiated the
exegetical tradition of Aristotelian commentaries. Nothing he wrote survives; a
summary account of emotions formerly ascribed to him is spurious.
angst: Grice discusses
this as an ‘implicatural emotion.’ G. term for a special form of anxiety, an
emotion seen by existentialists as both constituting and revealing the human
condition. Angst plays a key role in the writings of Heidegger, whose concept
is closely related to Kierkegaard’s angest and Sartre’s angoisse. The concept
is first treated in this distinctive way in Kierkegaard’s The Concept of
Anxiety 1844, where anxiety is described as “the dizziness of freedom.” Anxiety
here represents freedom’s self-awareness; it is the psychological precondition
for the individual’s attempt to become autonomous, a possibility that is seen
as both alluring and disturbing.
animal: pirotese. Durrell’s
Family Conversations. Durrelly’s family conversation. When H. P. Grice was presented with an ‘overview’ of his
oeuvre for PGRICE (Grandy and Warner, 1986), he soon found out. “There’s something missing.” Indeed, there is a very infamous objection,
Grice thought, which is not mentioned by ‘Richards,’ as he abbreviates Richard
Grandy and Richard Warner’s majestically plural ‘overview,’ which seems to
Grice to be one to which Grice must respond. And he shall! The objection Grice
states as follows. One of the leading strands in Grice’s reductive analysis of
the circumstances or scenario in which an emissor (E) communicates that p is
that the scenario, call it “C,” is not to be regarded exclusively, “or even
primarily,” as a ‘feature’ of an E that is using what philosophers of language (since
Plato’s “Cratylus”) have been calling ‘language’ (glossa, la lingua latina, la
lingua italiana, la langue française, the English tongue, de nederlands taal,
die Deutsche Sprache, etc.). The emissum (e) may be an ‘utterance’ which is not
‘linguistic.’ Grice finds the issue crucial after discussing the topic with his
colleague at Berkeley, Davidson. For Davidson reminds Grice: “[t]here is no such
thing as a language, not if a language is anything like what many philosophers […]
have supposed” (Davidson, 1986: 174). “I’m happy you say ‘many,’ Davidson,”
Grice commented. Grice continues formulating what he
obviously found to be an insidious, fastidious, objection. There are many
instances of “NOTABLY NON-‘linguistic’” vehicles or devices of communication,
within a communication-system, even a one-off system, which fulfil this or that
communication-function. I am using ‘communication-function’ alla Grice (1961:138,
repr. 1989:235).
These vehicles or devices are mostly
syntactically un-structured or amorphous – Grice’s favourite example being a
‘sort of hand-wave’ meaning that it is not the case that the emissor knows the
route or that the emissor is about to leave his addressee (1967:VI, repr. 1989:126).
Sometimes,
a device may exhibit at least “some rudimentary syntactic” structure – as Grice
puts it, giving a nod to Morris’s tripartite semiotics -- in that we may perhaps
distinguish and identify a ‘totum’ or complexum (say, Plato’s ‘logos’) from a
pars or simplex (say, Plato’s ‘onoma’ and ‘rhema’). Grice’s intention-based
reductive analysis of a communicatum, based on Aristotle, Locke, and Peirce, is
designed, indeed its very raison d'être being, to allow for the possibility that a non-“linguistic,” and,
further, indeed a non-“conventional” 'utterance,’ perhaps unrepeatable token,
not even manifesting any degree of syntactic structure, but a block of an
amorphous signal, be within the ‘repertoire’ of ‘procedures,’ perhaps
unrepeatable ones, of this or that organism, or creature, or agent, even if not
relying on any apparatus for communication of the kind that that we may label
‘linguistic’ or otherwise ‘conventional,’ will count as an emissor E ‘doing’
this or that ‘thing,’ thereby ‘communicating’ that p. To provide for this
conceptual scenario, it is plainly necessary, Grice grants, that the key
ingredient in any representation or conceptualization, or reductive analysis of
‘communicating,’ viz. intending that p, for Grice, should be a ‘state’ of the
emissor’s “soul” (Grice is translating Grecian ψυχή the capacity for which does not require what we may label
the ‘possession’ of, shall we say, ‘faculty,’ of what philosophers since
Cratylus have been calling ‘γλῶσσα Ἑλληνίδα,’
‘lingua latina,’ ‘lingua italiana,’ ‘langue française,’ ‘English tongue,’
‘Nederlands taal,’ ‘die Deutsche Sprache.’ (Grice
always congratulated Kant for never distinguishing between ‘die Deutsche
Sprache’ and ‘Sprache’ as ‘eine Fakultät.’). Now
a philosopher, relying on this or that neo-Prichardian reductive analysis of
‘intending that p,’ (Oxonian Grice will quote Oxonian if he can) may not be
willing to allow the possibility of such, shall we grant, pre-linguistic
intending that p, or non-linguistic intending that p. Surely, if the emissor E
realizes that his addressee or recipient R does not ‘share’ say, what the
Germans call ‘die Deutsche Sprache,” E may still communicate, by doing
so-and-so, that such-and-such, viz. p. E may make this sort of hand wave
communicating that E knows the route or that E is about to leave R. Against
that objection, Grice surely wins the day. There’s nothing in Prichard account
of ‘willing that p,’ itself a borrowing from William James (“I will that the
distant table slides over the floor toward me. It does not.”) which is about
‘die Deutsche Sprache.’
But Grice hastens to declare that
winning ‘the’ day may not be winning ‘all’ day. And
that is because of Oxonian philosophy being what it is. Because, as far as
Grice’s Oxonian explorations on communication go, in a succession of
increasingly elaborate moves – ending with a a clause which closes the succession
o-- designed to thwart this or that scenario, later deemed illegitimate,
involving two rational agents where the emissor E relies on an
‘inference-element’ that it is not the case that E intends his recipient R will
recogise – Grice is led to narrow the ‘intending’ the reductive analysis of ‘Emissor
E communicates that p’ to C-intending. Grice expects that whatever may be the case in general with
regard to ‘intending,’ C-intending seems for some reason to Grice to be
unsophisticatedly, viz. plainly, too sophisticated a ‘state’ of a soul (or ψυχή) to be found in an organism, ‘pirot,’ creature, that we may
not want to deem ‘rational,’ or as the Germans would say, a creature that is plainly
destitute of “Die Deutsche Sprache.” We seem to be needing a pirot to be “very
intelligent, indeed rational.” (Who other than Grice would genially combine
Locke with Carnap?). Some may regret, Grice admits, that his unavoidable rear-guard
action just undermines the raison d'etre of his campaign. However, Grice goes on to provide an admittedly brief reply
which will have to suffice under the circumstances. There is SOME limit for
Oxonian debate! A full treatment that would satisfy Grice requires delving deep
into crucial problems about the boundary between vicious and virtuous conceptual
circularity.
Which is promising. It is not something
UNATTAINABLE a priori – and there is nothing wrong with leaving it for the
morrow. It reduces to the philosopher trying to show himself virtuously
circular, if not, like Lear, spherical. But why need the circle be virtuous.
Well, as August would put it, unless a ‘circulus’ is not ‘virtuosus,’ one would
hardly deem it a ‘circulus’ in the first place. A circle is virtuous if it is not a
bad circle. One may even say, with The Carpenter, that, like a cabbage or a
king, if a circle is not virtuous is not even a circle! (Grice 2001:35). In
this case, to borrow from former Oxonian student S. R. Schiffer, we need the
‘virtuous circle’ because we are dealing with ‘a loop’ (Schiffer, 1988:v) -- a
‘conceptual loop,’ that is. Schiffer is not interested in ‘communicating;’ only
‘meaning,’ but his point can be easily transliterated. Schiffer is saying that
‘U,’ or utterer, our ‘E,’ means that p’ surely relies on ‘U intends that p,’
but mind the loop: ‘U intends that p’ may rely on ‘U means that p.’In Grice’s
most generic, third-person terms, we have a creature, call it a pirot, P1,
that, by doing thing D1, communicates that p. We are talking of Grice qua
ethologist, who OBSERVES the scenario. As it happens, Grice’s favourite pirot
is the parrot, and call Grice a snob, but his favourite parrot was Prince
Maurice’s Parrot. Prince Maurice’s Parrot. Grice reads Locke, and adapts it
slightly. “Since I think I may be confident, that, whoever should see a
CREATURE of his own shape or make, though it had no more reason all its life
than a PARROT, would call him still A MAN; or whoever should hear a parrot discourse,
reason, and philosophise, would call or think it nothing but a PARROT; and say,
the one was A DULL IRRATIONAL MAN, and the other A VERY INTELLIGENT RATIONAL
PARROT. “A relation we have in an author of great note, is sufficient to
countenance the supposition of A RATIONAL PARROT. “The author’s words are as
follows.”““I had a mind to know, from Prince Maurice's own mouth, the account
of a common, but much credited story, that I had heard so often from many
others, of a parrot he has, that speaks, and asks, and answers common questions,
like A REASONABLE CREATURE.””““So that those of his train there generally
conclude it to be witchery or possession; and one of his chaplains, would never
from that time endure A PARROT, but says all PARROTS have a devil in them.””““I
had heard many particulars of this story, and as severed by people hard to be
discredited, which made me ask Prince Maurice what there is of it.””““Prince
Maurice says, with his usual plainness and dryness in talk, there is something
true, but a great deal false of what is reported.””““I desired to know of him
what there was of the first. Prince Maurice tells me short and coldly, that he
had HEARD of such A PARROT; and though he believes nothing of it, and it was a
good way off, yet he had so much curiosity as to send for the parrot: that it
was a very great parrot; and when the parrot comes first into the room where
Prince Maurice is, with a great many men about him, the parrot says presently, ‘What
a nice company is here.’”” ““ One of the men asks the parrot, ‘What thinkest
thou that man is?,’ ostending his finger, and pointing to Prince Maurice.”“The
parrot answers, ‘Some general -- or other.’ When the man brings the parrot
close to Prince Maurice, Prince Maurice asks the parrot, ‘D'ou venez-vous?’”““The
parrot answers, ‘De Marinnan.’ Then Prince Maurice goes on, and poses a second
question to the parrot.””““‘A qui estes-vous?’ The Parrot answers: ‘A un
Portugais.’”““Prince Maurice then asks a third question: ‘Que fais-tu la?’““The
parrot answers: “Je garde les poulles.’ Prince Maurice smiles, which pleases
the Parrot.”““Prince Maurice, violating a Griceian maxim, and being just
informed that p, asks whether p. This is incidentally the Prince’s fourth
question to the parrot – the first idiotic one. ‘Vous gardez les poulles?’”” ““The Parrot answers, ‘Oui, moi; et je scai bien faire.’
Then the parrott appeals to Peirce’s iconic system and makes the chuck four or
five times that a man uses to make to chickens when a man calls them. I set
down the words of this worthy dialogue in French, just as Prince Maurice said
them to me. I ask Prince Maurice in what ‘tongue’ the parrot speaks.””““Prince
Maurice says that the parrot speaks in the Brazilian tongue.””““ I ask Prince
William whether he understands the Brazilian tongue.”” ““Prince Maurice says:
No, but he has taken care to have TWO interpreters by him, the one a Dutchman
that spoke the Brazilian tongue, and the other a Brazilian that spoke the Dutch
tongue; that Prince Maurice asked them separately and privately, and both of
them AGREED in telling Prince Maurice just the same thing that the parrot had
said.””““I could not but tell this ODD story, because it is so much out of the
way, and from the first hand, and what may pass for a good one; for I dare say
Prince Maurice at least believed himself in all he told me, having ever passed
for a very honest and pious man.””““I leave it to naturalists to reason, and to
other men to believe, as they please upon it. However, it is not, perhaps,
amiss to relieve or enliven a busy scene sometimes with such digressions,
whether to the purpose or no.””Locke takes care “that the reader should have
the story at large in the author's own words, because he seems to me not to
have thought it incredible.”“For it cannot be imagined that so able a man as
he, who had sufficiency enough to warrant all the testimonies he gives of
himself, should take so much pains, in a place where it had nothing to do, to
pin so close, not only on a man whom he mentions as his friend, but on a prince
in whom he acknowledges very great honesty and piety, a story which, if he
himself thought incredible, he could not but also think RIDICULOUS.”“Prince
Maurice, it is plain, who vouches this story, and our author, who relates it
from him, both of them call this talker A PARROT.”Locke asks “any one else who
thinks such a story fit to be told, whether, if this PARROT, and all of its
kind, had always talked, as we have a prince's word for it this one did,-
whether, I say, they would not have passed for a race of RATIONAL ANIMALS; but
yet, whether, for all that, they would have been allowed to be MEN, and not
PARROTS?”“For I presume it is not the idea of A THINKING OR RATIONAL BEING
alone that makes the idea of A MAN in most people's sense: but of A BODY, so
and so shaped, joined to it: and if that be the idea of a MAN, the same
successive body not shifted all at once, must, as well as THE SAME IMMATERIAL
SPIRIT, go to the making of the same MAN.”So
back to Grice’s pirotology, or Pirotologia. But first a precis Grice needs a
dossier with a précis, so that he can insert the parrot’s conversational implicatura
– and Prince Maurice’s. PARROT: What a nice company is here.MAN (pointing to Prince
Maurice): What thinkest thou that man is?PARROT: Some general -- or other. Grice’s
gloss: The he parrot displays what Grice calls ‘up-take.’ The parrot recognizes
the man’s c-intention. So far is ability to display uptake.PRINCE MAURICE: D'ou
venez-vous?PARROT: De Marinnan.PRINCE MAURICE: A qui estes-vous?PARROT: A un
Portugais.PRINCE MAURICE: Que fais-tu la?PARROT: Je garde les poulles.PRINCE
MAURICE SMILES and flouts a Griceian maxim: Vous gardez les poulles?PARROT
(losing patience, and grasping the Prince’s implicaturum that he doubts it): Oui,
moi. Et je scai bien faire.Grice’s gloss: The Parrott appeals to Peirce’s
iconic system and makes the chuck five times that a man uses to make to chickens
when a man calls them.According to his “most recent speculations” about
communication, Grice goes on in his ‘Reply to Richards,’ one should
distinguish, as he engages in a bit of legalese, between two sides of the scenario
under conceptual reduction, E communicates that p. One side is the ‘de facto’
side, a side which, as in name implies, in fact contains any
communication-relevant feature which obtains or is present in the
circumstances. But then there is a ‘de jure’ side to the scenario, viz. the
nested C-intending which is only deemed to be present, as a vicious circle with
good intentions may become a virtuous one. By the ‘nesting,’ Grice means the
three sub-intentions, involved in a scenario where Emissor E communicates that
(psi*) p, reducible to the Emissor E c-intending that A recognises that E psi-s
that p.First, there is the ‘exhibitive’ intention, C1. Emissor E intends A to
recognise that A psi-s that p.Second, there is the ‘reflexive’ intention, C2.Emissor
intends that A recognise C1 by A recognising C2Third, there is the ‘openness’
intention, C3. There is no inference-element which is C-constitutive such that
Emissor relies on it and yet does not intend A to recognise.The “de jure” side
to the state of affairs involves self-reference But since this self-referential
circle, a mere ‘loop,’ is meant to BLOCK an utterly vicious circle of a
regressus ad infinitum (or ‘ho eis apeiron ekballon,’ if you must), the
self-referential circle may well be deemed virtuous. The ‘de jure’ side to the
scenario is trying to save state of affairs which in, in Grice’s words,
“infinitely complex,” and such that no reasonable philosopher should expect to
be realised ‘de facto.’ “In which case,” Grice remarks, “it seems to serve
little, if any, purpose” to assume that this very INCONCEIVABLE ‘de facto’
instantiation of a ‘de jure’ ascription of an emissor communicating that p
would only be detectable, as it isn’t, by appeal to something like ‘die
Deutsche Sprache’!“At its most meagre,” to use Grice’s idiom, the ‘de facto’
side should consist, merely, in any pre-rational ‘counterpart’ to the state of
affairs describable by having an Emissor E communicating that p,This might
amount to no more than making a certain sort of utterance – our doing D1 -- in
order thereby to get some recipient creature R, our second pirot, P2, to think
or want some particular thing, our p. This meagre condition hardly involves
reference to anything like ‘die Deutsche Sprache.’Let’s reformulate the
condition.It’s just a pirot, at a ‘pre-rational’ level. The pirot does a thing
T IN ORDER THEREBY to get some other pirot to think or do some particular
thing. To echo Hare,Die Tur ist geschlossen, ja.Die Tur ist geschlossen,
bitte.Grice continues as a corollary: “Maybe in a less straightforward instance
of “Emissor E communicates that p” there is actually present the C-intention
whose feasibility as an ‘intention’ suggests some ability to use ‘die Deutsche
Sprache.’And if it does, Grice adds, it looks like anything like ‘die Deutsche
Sprache’ ends up being an aid to the conceptualizing about communication, not
communication itself! ReferencesDavidson, Donald
1986. A nice derangement of epitaphs, in Grandy and Warner, pp. 157-74.Durrell,
My family and other animals. Grandy, R. E. and R. O. Warner. 1986.
Philosophical grounds of rationality: intentions, categories, ends. Oxford, at
the Clarendon Press. Grice, H. P. 1986. Reply to Richards, in Grandy and
Warner, pp. 45-106Grice, H. P. 1989. Studies in the Way of Words. London and
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Grice, H. P. 2001. Aspects of
reason. Oxford, at the Clarendon Press. Locke, J. 1690. An essay concerning
humane [sic] understanding. Oxford: The Bodleian. Schiffer, S. R. 1988.
Meaning. Oxford, at the Clarendon Press.
animatum: Grice thinks of
communication as what he calls ‘soul-to-soul transfer.’ Very Aristotelian. Grice was interested in what he called the
‘rational soul’ (psyche logike). In an act of communication, Emissor
communicates that p, there is a psi involved, therefore a soul, therefore what
the Romans called an ‘anima,’ and the Greeks called the ‘psyche.’ For surely
there can be no psi-transmission without a psi. Grice loved to abbreviate this
as the psi, since Lady Asquith, who was a soul, would not have desired any less
from Grice. Grice, like Plato and Aristotle, holds a tripartite theory of the
soul. Where, ‘part’ (Aristotelian ‘meros’) is taken very seriously. Anything
thought. From ‘psyche,’ anima. Grice uses the symbol of the letter psi here
which he renders as ‘animatum.’ Why Grice prefers ‘soul’ to mind. The
immortality of a the chicken soul. By Shropshire. Shropshire claims that the immortality of the soul is proved by
the fact that, if you cut off a chicken's head, the chicken will run round the
yard for a quarter of an hour before dropping. Grice has an an 'expansion' of Shropshire's
ingenious argument.If the soul is not dependent on the body, it is immortal. If
the soul is dependent on the body, it is dependent on that part of the body in
which it is located. If the soul is located in the body, it is located in the
head. If the chicken's soul were located in its head, the chicken's soul would
be destroyed if the head were rendered inoperative by removal from the body.
The chicken runs round the yard after head-removal. It could do this only if
animated, and controlled by its soul. So the chicken's soul is not located in,
and not dependent on, the chicken's head. So the chicken's soul is not
dependent on the chicken's body. So the chicken's soul is immortal. end p.11 If
the chicken's soul is immortal, a fortiori the human soul is immortal. So the
soul is immortal. The question I now ask myself is this: why is it that I
should be quite prepared to believe that the Harvard students ascribed their
expansion of Botvinnik's proof, or at least some part of it, to Botvinnik (as
what he had in mind), whereas I have no inclination at all to ascribe any part
of my expansion to Shropshire? Considerations which at once strike me as being
likely to be relevant are: (1) that Botvinnik's proof without doubt contained
more steps than Shropshire's claim; (2) that the expansion of Botvinnik's proof
probably imported, as extra premisses, only propositions which are true, and
indeed certain; whereas my expansion imports premisses which are false or
dubious; (3) that Botvinnik was highly intelligent and an accomplished
logician; whereas Shropshire was neither very intelligent nor very accomplished
as a philosopher. No doubt these considerations are relevant, though one
wonders whether one would be much readier to accord Shropshire's production the
title of 'reasoning' if it had contained some further striking 'deductions',
such as that since the soul is immortal moral principles have absolute
validity; and one might also ask whether the effect of (3) does not nullify
that of (2), since, if Shropshire was stupid, why should not one ascribe to him
a reconstructed argument containing plainly unacceptable premisses? But,
mainly, I would like some further light on the following question: if such
considerations as those which I have just mentioned are relevant, why are they
relevant? I should say a word about avowals. The following contention might be
advanced. If you want to know whether someone R, who has produced what may be
an incomplete piece of reasoning, has a particular completion in mind, the direct
way to find out is to ask him. That would settle the matter. If, however, you
are unable to ask him, then indirect methods will have to be used, which may
well be indecisive. Indeterminacy springs merely from having to rely on
indirect methods. I have two comments to make. First: it end p.12 is far from
clear to what extent avowals do settle the matter. Anyone who has taught
philosophy is familiar with the situation in which, under pressure to expand an
argument they have advanced, students, particularly beginners, make statements
which, one is inclined to say, misrepresent their position. This phenomenon is
perhaps accounted for by my much more important second point: that avowals in
this kind of context generally do not have the character which one might without
reflection suppose them to have; they are not so much reportive as
constructive. If I ask someone if he thinks that so-and-so is a consequence of
such-and-such, what I shall receive will be primarily a defence of this
supposition, not a report on what, historically, he had in mind in making it.
We are in general much more interested in whether an inferential step is a good
one to make than we are in what a particular person had in mind at the actual
moment at which he made the step. One might perhaps see an analogy between
avowals in this area and the specification of plans. If someone has propounded
a plan for achieving a certain objective, and I ask him what he proposes to do
in such-and-such a contingency, I expect him to do the best he can to specify
for me a way of meeting that contingency, rather than to give a historically
correct account of what thoughts he had been entertaining. This feature of what
I might call inferential avowals is one for which we shall have to account.Let
us take stock. The thesis which we proposed for examination has needed
emendation twice, once in the face of the possibility of bad reasoning, and
once to allow for informal and incomplete reasoning. The reformulation needed
to accommodate the latter is proving difficult to reach. Let us take s and s′
to be sequences consisting of a set of premisses and a conclusion (or, perhaps
it would be better to say, a set of propositions and a further proposition), or
a sequence (sorites) of such sequences. (This is not fully accurate, but will
serve.) Let us suppose that x has produced s (in speech or in thought). Let
"formally cogent" mean "having true premisses, and being such
that steps from premisses to conclusions are formally valid". (1) We
cannot define "s is a piece of reasoning by x" as "x thinks s to
be formally cogent", because if s is an incomplete piece of reasoning s is
not, and could not reasonably be thought by x to be, formally cogent. end p.13
(2) We cannot define "s is a piece of reasoning by x" as "(∃s′) (s′ is an expansion
of s and s′ is formally cogent)" because (a) it does not get in the idea
that x thinks s′ formally cogent and (b) it would exclude bad reasoning. (3) We
cannot define "s is a piece of reasoning by x" as "x thinks that
(∃s′)
(s′ is an expansion of s and s′ is formally cogent)", for this is too
weak, and would allow as reasoning any case in which x believed (for whatever
reason, or lack of reason) that an informal sequence had some formally cogent
expansion or other. (Compare perhaps Shropshire.).” In Latin indeed, ‘animus’
and ‘anima’ make a world of a difference, as Shropshire well knows. Psyche
transliterates as ‘anima’ only; ‘animus’ the Greeks never felt the need for. Of
course a chicken is an animal, as in man. “Homo animalis rationalis.” Grice
prefers ‘human,’ but sometimes he uses ‘animal,’ as opposed to ‘vegetal,
sometimes, when considering stages of freedom. A stone (mineral) displays a
‘free’ fall, which is metabolical. And then, a vegetable is less free than an
animal, which can move, and a non-human animal (that Grice calls ‘a beast’) is
less free than man, who is a rational animal. Grice notes that back in the day,
when the prince came from a hunt, “I brought some animals,” since these were
‘deer,’ ‘deer’ was taken as meaning ‘animal,’ when the implicaturum was very
much cancellable. The Anglo-Saxons soon dropped the ‘deer’ and adopted the
Latinate ‘animal.’ They narrowed the use of ‘deer’ for the ‘cervus cervus.’ But
not across the North Sea where the zoo is still called a ‘deer-garden.’ When
Aelfric studied philosophy he once thought man was a rational deer.
annullatum
-- annullability: a synonym for ‘cancellability,’ used in “Causal.” Perhaps
clear than ‘cancel.’ The etymology seems clear, because it involves the negative
– “Cancel” seems like a soft sophisticated way of annulling, render something
nix. Short and Lewis has ‘nullus’ as ne-ullus, not any, none, no. which is indeed a diminutive
for ‘unus,’ [for unulus, dim. of unus], any, any one (usu.
in neg. sentences; corresp. with aliquis in affirmations).
anniceris: Grecian and
pre-Griceian philosopher, vide. H. P. Grice, “Pleasure.” A pupil of Antipater,
he established a separate branch of the Cyrenaic school known as the
Anniceraioi. He subscribed to typical Cyrenaic hedonism, arguing that the end
of each action should be one’s own pleasure, since we can know nothing of
others’ experiences. He tempered the implications of hedonism with the claim
that a wise man attaches weight to respect for parents, patriotism, gratitude,
and friendship, perhaps influencing Epicurus in this regard. Anniceris also
played down the Cyrenaic stress on the intellect’s role in hedonistic practical
rationality, taking the Aristotelian view that cultivation of the right habits
is indispensable.
anscombe:
H. P. Grice, “Reply to G. E. M. Anscombe.” Anscombe: Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret,
Irish philosopher who has held positions at Oxford and Cambridge, best known
for her work in the philosophy of mind and for her editions and translations of
Vitters’s later writings. Anscombe studied philosophy with Vitters and became
closely associated with him, writing An Introduction to Vitters’s Tractatus 9.
She is married to Peter Geach. Anscombe’s first major work was Intention 7. She
argues that the concept of intention is central to our understanding of
ourselves as rational agents. The basic case is that of the intentions with
which we act. These are identified by the reasons we give in answer to
why-questions concerning our actions. Such reasons usually form a hierarchy
that constitutes a practical syllogism of which action itself is the
conclusion. Hence our intentions are a form of active practical knowledge that
normally leads to action. Anscombe compares the direction of fit of this kind
of knowledge with a shopping list’s relation to one’s purchases, and contrasts
it with the direction of fit characteristic of a list of these purchases drawn
up by an observer of the shopper. She maintains that the deep mistake of modern
i.e., post-medieval philosophy has been to think that all knowledge is of this
latter, observational, type. This conception of active knowledge expressed
through an agent’s intentions conflicts with the passive conception of
rationality characteristic of Hume and his followers, and Anscombe develops
this challenge in papers critical of the isought distinction of Hume and his
modern successors. In a famous paper, “Modern Moral Philosophy” 8, she also
argues that ought-statements make sense only in the context of a moral theology
that grounds morality in divine commands. Since our culture rejects this
theology, it is no surprise that “modern moral philosophers” cannot find much
sense in them. We should therefore abandon them and return to the older
conceptions of practical rationality and virtue. These conceptions, and the
associated conception of natural law, provide the background to an
uncompromising defense of traditional Catholic morality concerning sexuality,
war, and the importance of the distinction between intention and foresight. Anscombe
has never been afraid of unpopular positions
philosophical and ethical. Her three volumes of Collected Papers 1
include a defense of singular causation, an attack on the very idea of a
subject of thought, and a critique of pacifism. She is one of the most original
and distinctive English philosophers of her generation.
anselmus: “I would call him ‘Canterbury,’ only he was an
Italian!” – H. P. Grice. Saint, called Anselm of Canterbury, philosopher
theologian. A Benedictine monk and the second Norman archbishop of Canterbury,
he is best known for his distinctive method
fides quaerens intellectum; his “ontological” argument for the existence
of God in his treatise Proslogion; and his classic formulation of the
satisfaction theory of the Atonement in the Cur Deus homo. Like Augustine
before him, Anselm is a Christian Platonist in metaphysics. He argues that the
most accessible proofs of the existence of God are through value theory: in his
treatise Monologion, he deploys a cosmological argument, showing the existence
of a source of all goods, which is the Good per se and hence supremely good;
that same thing exists per se and is the Supreme Being. In the Proslogion,
Anselm begins with his conception of a being a greater than which cannot be
conceived, and mounts his ontological argument that a being a greater than
which cannot be conceived exists in the intellect, because even the fool
understands the phrase when he hears it; but if it existed in the intellect
alone, a greater could be conceived that existed in reality. This supremely
valuable object is essentially whatever it is
other things being equal that is
better to be than not to be, and hence living, wise, powerful, true, just,
blessed, immaterial, immutable, and eternal per se; even the paradigm of
sensory goods Beauty, Harmony,
Sweetness, and Pleasant Texture, in its own ineffable manner. Nevertheless, God
is supremely simple, not compounded of a plurality of excellences, but “omne et
unum, totum et solum bonum,” a being a more delectable than which cannot be
conceived. Everything other than God has its being and its well-being through
God as efficient cause. Moreover, God is the paradigm of all created natures,
the latter ranking as better to the extent that they more perfectly resemble God.
Thus, it is better to be human than to be horse, to be horse than to be wood,
even though in comparison with God everything else is “almost nothing.” For
every created nature, there is a that-for-which-it-ismade ad quod factum est.
On the one hand, Anselm thinks of such teleology as part of the internal
structure of the natures themselves: a creature of type F is a true F only
insofar as it is/does/exemplifies that for which F’s were made; a defective F,
to the extent that it does not. On the other hand, for Anselm, the telos of a
created nature is that-for-which-God-made-it. Because God is personal and acts
through reason and will, Anselm infers that prior in the order of explanation
to creation, there was, in the reason of the maker, an exemplar, form, likeness,
or rule of what he was going to make. In De veritate Anselm maintains that such
teleology gives rise to obligation: since creatures owe their being and
well-being to God as their cause, so they owe their being and well-being to God
in the sense of having an obligation to praise him by being the best beings
they can. Since every creature is of some nature or other, each can be its best
by being that-for-which-God-made-it. Abstracting from impediments, non-rational
natures fulfill this obligation and “act rightly” by natural necessity;
rational creatures, when they exercise their powers of reason and will to
fulfill God’s purpose in creating them. Thus, the goodness of a creature how
good a being it is is a function of twin factors: its natural telos i.e., what
sort of imitation of divine nature it aims for, and its rightness in exercising
its natural powers to fulfill its telos. By contrast, God as absolutely
independent owes no one anything and so has no obligations to creatures. In De
casu diaboli, Anselm underlines the optimism of his ontology, reasoning that
since the Supreme Good and the Supreme Being are identical, every being is good
and every good a being. Two further conclusions follow. First, evil is a
privation of being, the absence of good in something that properly ought to
have it e.g., blindness in normally sighted animals, injustice in humans or
angels. Second, since all genuine powers are given to enable a being to fulfill
its natural telos and so to be the best being it can, all genuine
metaphysically basic powers are optimific and essentially aim at goods, so that
evils are merely incidental side effects of their operation, involving some
lack of coordination among powers or between their exercise and the surrounding
context. Thus, divine omnipotence does not, properly speaking, include
corruptibility, passibility, or the ability to lie, because the latter are
defects and/or powers in other things whose exercise obstructs the flourishing
of the corruptible, passible, or potential liar. Anselm’s distinctive action
theory begins teleologically with the observation that humans and angels were
made for a happy immortality enjoying God, and to that end were given the
powers of reason to make accurate value assessments and will to love accordingly.
Anselm regards freedom and imputability of choice as essential and permanent
features of all rational beings. But freedom cannot be defined as a power for
opposites the power to sin and the power not to sin, both because neither God
nor the good angels have any power to sin, and because sin is an evil at which
no metaphysically basic power can aim. Rather, freedom is the power to preserve
justice for its own sake. Choices and actions are imputable to an agent only if
they are spontaneous, from the agent itself. Creatures cannot act spontaneously
by the necessity of their natures, because they do not have their natures from
themselves but receive them from God. To give them the opportunity to become
just of themselves, God furnishes them with two motivaAnselm Anselm 31 31 tional drives toward the good: an
affection for the advantageous affectio commodi or a tendency to will things
for the sake of their benefit to the agent itself; and an affection for justice
affectio justitiae or a tendency to will things because of their own intrinsic
value. Creatures are able to align these drives by letting the latter temper
the former or not. The good angels, who preserved justice by not willing some
advantage possible for them but forbidden by God for that time, can no longer
will more advantage than God wills for them, because he wills their maximum as
a reward. By contrast, creatures, who sin by refusing to delay gratification in
accordance with God’s will, lose both uprightness of will and their affection
for justice, and hence the ability to temper their pursuit of advantage or to
will the best goods. Justice will never be restored to angels who desert it.
But if animality makes human nature weaker, it also opens the possibility of
redemption. Anselm’s argument for the necessity of the Incarnation plays out
the dialectic of justice and mercy so characteristic of his prayers. He begins
with the demands of justice: humans owe it to God to make all of their choices
and actions conform to his will; failure to render what was owed insults God’s
honor and makes the offender liable to make satisfaction; because it is worse
to dishonor God than for countless worlds to be destroyed, the satisfaction
owed for any small sin is incommensurate with any created good; it would be
maximally indecent for God to overlook such a great offense. Such calculations
threaten certain ruin for the sinner, because God alone can do/be immeasurably
deserving, and depriving the creature of its honor through the eternal
frustration of its telos seems the only way to balance the scales. Yet, justice
also forbids that God’s purposes be thwarted through created resistance, and it
was divine mercy that made humans for a beatific immortality with him.
Likewise, humans come in families by virtue of their biological nature which
angels do not share, and justice allows an offense by one family member to be
compensated by another. Assuming that all actual humans are descended from
common first parents, Anselm claims that the human race can make satisfaction
for sin, if God becomes human and renders to God what Adam’s family owes. When
Anselm insists that humans were made for beatific intimacy with God and
therefore are obliged to strive into God with all of their powers, he
emphatically includes reason or intellect along with emotion and will. God, the
controlling subject matter, is in part permanently inaccessible to us because
of the ontological incommensuration between God and creatures and our progress
is further hampered by the consequences of sin. Our powers will function best,
and hence we have a duty to follow right order in their use: by submitting
first to the holistic discipline of faith, which will focus our souls and point
us in the right direction. Yet it is also a duty not to remain passive in our
appreciation of authority, but rather for faith to seek to understand what it
has believed. Anselm’s works display a dialectical structure, full of
questions, objections, and contrasting opinions, designed to stir up the mind.
His quartet of teaching dialogues De
grammatico, De veritate, De libertate arbitrii, and De casu diaboli as well as
his last philosophical treatise, De concordia, anticipate the genre of the
Scholastic question quaestio so dominant in the thirteenth and fourteenth
centuries. His discussions are likewise remarkable for their attention to
modalities and proper-versus-improper linguistic usage.
antilogismus: Grice: “Not to be
confused with the mere implicatural ‘para-logism.’ -- an inconsistent triad of
propositions, two of which are the premises of a valid categorical syllogism
and the third of which is the contradictory of the conclusion of this valid
categorical syllogism. An antilogism is a special form of antilogy or
self-contradiction.
antinomianism: as a Kantian,
Grice overused the idea of a nomos or law, and then there’s antinominaism, the
view that one is not bound by moral law; specifically, the view that Christians
are by grace set free from the need to observe moral laws. During the
Reformation, antinomianism was believed by some but not Martin Luther to follow
from the Lutheran doctrine of justification by faith alone.
antiochus: Grecian
philosopher and the last prominent member of the New Academy. He played the
major role in ending its two centuries of Skepticism and helped revive interest
in doctrines from the Old Academy, as he called Plato, Aristotle, and their
associates. The impulse for this decisive shift came in epistemology, where the
Skeptical Academy had long agreed with Stoicism that knowledge requires an
infallible “criterion of truth” but disputed the Stoic claim to find this
criterion in “cognitive perception.” Antiochus’s teacher, Philo of Larissa,
broke with this tradition and proposed that perception need not be cognitive to
qualify as knowledge. Rejecting this concession, Antiochus offered new
arguments for the Stoic claim that some perception is cognitive, and hence
knowledge. He also proposed a similar accommodation in ethics, where he agreed
with the Stoics that virtue alone is sufficient for happiness but insisted with
Aristotle that virtue is not the only good. These and similar attempts to
mediate fundamental disputes have led some to label Antiochus an eclectic or
syncretist; but some of his proposals, especially his appeal to the Old Academy,
set the stage for Middle Platonism, which also sought to reconcile Plato and
Aristotle. No works by Antiochus survive, but his students included many
eminent Romans, most notably Cicero, who summarizes Antiochus’s epistemology in
the Academica, his critique of Stoic ethics in De finibus IV, and his
purportedly Aristotelian ethics in De finibus V.
anti-realism: If Grice was a
realist, he hated anti-realism, the rejection, in one or another form or area
of inquiry, of realism, the view that there are knowable mind-independent
facts, objects, or properties. Metaphysical realists make the general claim
that there is a world of mind-independent objects. Realists in particular areas
make more specific or limited claims. Thus moral realists hold that there are mind-independent
moral properties, mathematical realists that there are mind-independent
mathematical facts, scientific realists that scientific inquiry reveals the
existence of previously unknown and unobservable mind-independent entities and
properties. Antirealists deny either that facts of the relevant sort are
mind-independent or that knowledge of such facts is possible. Berkeley’s
subjective idealism, which claims that the world consists only of minds and
their contents, is a metaphysical anti-realism. Constructivist anti-realists,
on the other hand, deny that the world consists only of mental phenomena, but
claim that it is constituted by, or constructed from, our evidence or beliefs.
Many philosophers find constructivism implausible or even incoherent as a
metaphysical doctrine, but much more plausible when restricted to a particular
domain, such as ethics or mathematics. Debates between realists and
anti-realists have been particularly intense in philosophy of science.
Scientific realism has been rejected both by constructivists such as Kuhn, who
hold that scientific facts are constructed by the scientific community, and by
empiricists who hold that knowledge is limited to what can be observed. A
sophisticated version of the latter doctrine is Bas van Fraassen’s constructive
empiricism, which allows scientists free rein in constructing scientific
models, but claims that evidence for such models confirms only their observable
implications.
apagoge:
distinguished by Grice from both ‘epagoge,’ and his favoured ‘diagoge.’ A shifting of the
basis of argument: hence of argument based on a probable or agreed assumption,
Arist.APr.69a20, cf. Anon.in SE65.35; reduction, “ἡ εἰς τὸ ἀδύνατον ἀ.”
reductio per impossibile, APr. 29b6; “ἡ ἀ. μετάβασίς ἐστιν ἀπ᾽ ἄλλου
προβλήματος ἢ θεωρήματος ἐπ᾽ ἄλλο, οὗ γνωσθέντος ἢ πορισθέντος καὶ τὸ
προκείμενον ἔσται καταφανές” Procl. in Euc.p.212F.; τῶν ἀπορουμένων
διαγραμμάτων τὴν ἀ. ποιήσασθαι ib. p.213F. b. reduction of a disputant (cf. ἀπάγω
v. 1c), “ἡ ἐπὶ τὸ ἄδηλον ἀ.” S.E.P.2.234.
apocatastasis: a branch of
Grice’s eschatology -- from Grecian, ‘reestablishment’, the restoration of all
souls, including Satan’s and his minions’, in the kingdom of God. God’s
goodness will triumph over evil, and through a process of spiritual education
souls will be brought to repentance and made fit for divine life. The theory
originates with Origen but was also held by Gregory of Nyssa. In modern times
F. D. Maurice 180572 and Karl Barth 6 8 held this position.
aporia: cf. aporetic, cognate
with porosity. No porosity, and you get an impasse. While aware of Baker’s and
Deutsch’s treatment of the ‘aporia’ in Aristotle’s account of ‘philos,’ Grice
explores ‘aporia’ in Plato in the Thrasymachus on ‘legal justice’ prior to
‘moral justice’ in Republic. in Dialectic, question for discussion, difficulty,
puzzle, “ἀπορίᾳ σχόμενος” Pl.Prt.321c; ἀ. ἣν ἀπορεῖς ib.324d; “ἡ ἀ. ἰσότης ἐναντίων
λογισμῶν” Arist. Top.145b1, al.; “ἔχει ἀπορίαν περί τινος” Id.Pol.1285b28; “αἱ
μὲν οὖν ἀ. τοιαῦταί τινες συμβαίνουσιν” Id.EN1146b6; “οὐδεμίαν ποιήσει ἀ.”
Id.Metaph.1085a27; ἀ. λύειν, διαλύειν, Id.MM 1201b1, Metaph.1062b31; “ἀπορίᾳ ἀπορίαν
λύειν” D.S.1.37.Discussion with the
Sophist Thrasymachus can
only lead to aporia.
And the more I trust you, the more I sink into an aporia of
sorts. —Aha! roared Thrasymachus to everyone's surprise. There it is!
Socratic aporia is
back! Charge! neither Socrates' company nor Socrates himself gives any
convincing answer. So, he says, finding himself in a real aporia, he
visits Thrasymachus as
well, and ... I argue that a combination of these means in form
that I call “provocative-aporetic” better accounts for the means that Plato
uses to exert a protreptic effect on readers. Aporia is a simultaneously
intellectual and affective experience, and the way that readers choose to
respond to aporia has a greater protreptic effect than either affective or
intellectual means alone. When Socrates says he can 'transfer' the use of
"just" to things related to the 'soul,' what kind of conversational
game is that? Grice took Socrates's manoeuvre very
seriously.Socrates relies on the tripartite theory of the soul. Plato, actually -- since Socrates is a drammatis persona! In "Philosophical Eschatology, Metaphysics, and Plato's
Republic," H. P. Grice's purpose is to carry out a provocative-aporetic
reading Book I Grice argues that it is a dispute between two ways of
understanding 'just' which causes the aporia when Socrates tries to analyse
'just.' Although Socrates will not argue for the complexity and
tripartition of the soul until Bk. IV, we can at least note the contrast with
Thrasymachus' “idealize user” theory.For Socrates, agents are complex, and
justice coordinates the parts of the agent.For Thrasymachus, agents are simple
“users,” and justice is a tool for use. (2 - 3) Justice makes its possessor
happy; the function (telos, metier) argument. To make the argument that
justice is an excellence (virtus, arete) of soul (psyche) that makes its
possessor happy, Socrates relies on a method for discovering the function
(ἔργον, ergon, 352e1, cf. telos, metier, causa finalis) of any object
whatsoever. Socrates begins by differentiating between an exclusive
functions and an optimal function, so that we may discover the functions in
different types of objects, i.e., natural and artificial objects. We can
say an object performs some function (ergon) if one of the following conditions
holds.If the object is the only one that can do the work in
question, or If it is the object that does that work best.Socrates
then provides examples from different part-whole complexes to make his
point. The eye's exclusive function is to see, because no other organ is
specialized so as to perform just that function. A horse's work is to
carry riders into battle. Even though this might not be a horse's
EXCLUSIVE function, it may be its “optimal” function in that the horse is best
suited or designed by God to the task. Finally, the pruning knife is best
for tending to vines, not because it cannot cut anything else, but because it
is optimally suited for that task. Socrates' use of the pruning knife of
as an example of a thing's function resembles a return to the technē model,
since a craftsman must make the knife for a gardener to Socrates asks,
“Would you define this as the function of a horse and of anything else, as that
which someone does either through that thing alone, or best?” (...τοῦτο ἄν
θείης καὶ ἵππου καὶ ἄλλου ὁτουοῦν ἔργον, ὅ ἄν ἤ μόνῳ ἐκείνῳ ποιῇ τις ἤ ἄριστα;
352e1-2) Thrasymachus agrees to this definition of function. 91 use.But his use
of the eye — a bodily organ — should dissuade us from this view. One may
use these examples to argue that Socrates is in fact offering a new method to
investigate the nature of justice: 1) Find out what the functions of such
objects are2) determine (by observation, experiment, or even thought experiment)
cases where objects of such a kind perform their functions well and cases where
they perform them poorly; and 3) finally find out the qualities that
enable them to perform such functions well (and in the absence of which they
perform poorly), and these are their virtues.A crucial difference between this
method and technē model of justice lies in the interpretation that each assigns
to the realm of human artifacts. Polemarchus and Thrasymachus both assume
that the technē is unique as a form of knowledge for the power and control that
it offers users. In Polemarchus' case, the technē of justice, “helping
friends and harming enemies,” may be interpreted as a description of a method
for gaining political power within a traditional framework of communal life,
which assumes the oikos as the basic unit of power. Those families that
help their friends and harm their enemies thrive. Thrasymachus, on the
other hand, emphasizes the ways that technai grant users the power to exploit
nature to further their own, distinctively individual ends. Thus, the
shepherd exploits the sheep to make a livelihood for himself. Socrates'
approach differs from these by re-casting “mastery” over nature as submission
to norms that structure the natural world. For example, many factors contribute
to making This points to a distinction Socrates draws in Book X between
producers and users of artifacts. He uses the example of the blacksmith
who makes a bridle and the horseman who uses the bridle to argue that
production and use correspond to two gradations of knowledge (601c). The
ultimate purpose of the example is to provide a metaphor — using the craft
analogy — for identifying gradations of knowledge on a copy-original paradigm
of the form-participant relation. the pruning knife the optimal tool for
cutting vines: the shape of the human hand, the thickness and shape of the
vines, and the metal of the blade. Likewise, in order for horses to
optimally perform their “work,” they must be "healthy" and
strong. The conditions that bring about their "health" and
strength are not up to us, however."Control” only comes about through the
recognition of natural norms. Thus technē is a type of knowledge that
coordinates structures in nature.It is not an unlimited source of power. Socrates'
inclusion of the human soul (psyche) among those things that have a function is
the more controversial aspect of function argument.Socrates says that the
functions (erga) of the soul (psyche) are “to engage in care-taking,
ruling, and deliberation” and, later, simply that the ergon (or
function) of the soul (or psyche) is “to live” (τὸ ζῆν, "to zen,"
353d6). But the difficulty seems to be this: the functions of pruning
knives, horses, and bodily organs are determined with respect to a limited and
fairly unambiguous context that is already defined for them. But what is
this context with respect to the soul (psyche) of a human individual? One
answer might be that the social world — politics — provides the context that
defines the soul's function, just as the needs of the human organism define the
context in which the eye can perform a function. But here a challenger
might reply that in aristocracies, oligarchies, and democracies, “care-taking,
ruling, and deliberation” are utilized for different ends.In these contexts,
individual souls might have different functions, according to the “needs” that
these different regimes have. Alternatively, one might deny altogether
that the human soul has a function: the distinctive feature of human beings
might be their position “outside” of nature. Thus, even if Socrates'
description of the soul's function is accurate, it is too general to be really
informative.Socrates must offer more details for the function argument to be
convincing. Nonetheless, the idea that justice is a condition that lets
the soul perform its functions is a significant departure from the technē
model of justice, and one that will remain throughout the argument of the
Republic. […] τὸ ἐπιμελεῖσθαι καὶ ἄρχειν καὶ βουλεύεσθαι (353d3). As
far as Bk. I is concerned, “justice” functions as a place-holder for that
condition of the soul which permits the soul to perform its functions
well. What that condition is, however, remains unknown.For this reason,
Plato has Socrates concludes Bk. I by likening himself to a “glutton” (ὥσπερ οἱ
λίχνοι, 354b1), who takes another dish before “moderately enjoying the
previous” serving (πρὶν τοῦ προτέρου μετρίως ἀπολαύσαι, 354b2-3). For
Socrates wants to know what effects the optimal condition of soul brings about
before knowing what the condition itself is. Thus Bk. I concludes in
"aporia," but not in a way that betrays the dialogue's lack of
unity.The “separatist” thesis concerning Bk. I goes back to Hermann in
"Geschichte und System der Platonischen Philosophie." One can
argue on behalf of the “separatist” view as well. One can argue against
the separatist thesis, even granting some evidence in favour of the separatist
thesis. To the contrary, the "aporia" clearly foreshadows the
argument that Socrates makes about the soul in Bk. IV, viz. that the soul
(psyche) is a complex whole of parts -- an implicaturum in the “justice is
stronger” argument -- and that 'just' is the condition that allows this complex
whole be integrated to an optimal degree. Thus, Bk. I does not conclude
negatively, but rather provides the resources for going beyond the
"technē" model of justice, which is the primary cause of
Polemarchus's and Thrasymachus's encounter with "aporia" in Bk.
I. Throughout conversation of "The Republic," Socrates does not
really alter the argument he gives for justice in Bk. I, but rather states the
same argument in a different way. My gratitude to P. N.
Moore. Refs: Wise guys and smart alecks in Republic 1 and 2; Proleptic
composition in the Republic, or why Bk. 1 was never a separate dialogue, The
Classical Quarterly; "Socrates: ironist and moral philosopher."
Strictly an ‘aporia’ in Griceian, is a ‘puzzle’, ‘question for discussion’,
‘state of perplexity’. The aporetic method
the raising of puzzles without offering solutions is typical of the elenchus in the early
Socratic dialogues of Plato. These consist in the testing of definitions and
often end with an aporia, e.g., that piety is both what is and what is not
loved by the gods. Compare the paradoxes of Zeno, e.g., that motion is both
possible and impossible. In Aristotle’s dialectic, the resolution of aporiai
discovered in the views on a subject is an important source of philosophical
understanding. The beliefs that one should love oneself most of all and that
self-love is shameful, e.g., can be resolved with the right understanding of
‘self’. The possibility of argument for two inconsistent positions was an
important factor in the development of Skepticism. In modern philosophy, the
antinomies that Kant claimed reason would arrive at in attempting to prove the
existence of objects corresponding to transcendental ideas may be seen as
aporiai.
applicatum.
While Bennett uses the rather ‘abusive’ “nominalist” to refer to Grice, Grice
isn’t. It’s all about the ‘applied.’ Grice thinks a rational creature – not a
parrot, but a rational intelligent pirot – can have an abstract idea. So there
is this “Communication Device,” with capital C and capital D. The emissor
APPLIES it to a given occasion. Cf. complete and incomplete. What’s the antonym
of applied? Plato’s idea! applied
– grice used ‘applied’ for ‘meaning’ – but ‘applied’ can be used in other
contxts too. In ethics, the domain of ethics that includes professional ethics,
such as business ethics, engineering ethics, and medical ethics, as well as
practical ethics such as environmental ethics, which is applied, and thus
practical as opposed to theoretical, but not focused on any one discipline. One
of the major disputes among those who work in applied ethics is whether or not
there is a general and universal account of morality applicable both to the
ethical issues in the professions and to various practical problems. Some
philosophers believe that each of the professions or each field of activity
develops an ethical code for itself and that there need be no apellatio applied
ethics 34 34 close relationship between
e.g. business ethics, medical ethics, and environmental ethics. Others hold
that the same moral system applies to all professions and fields. They claim
that the appearance of different moral systems is simply due to certain
problems being more salient for some professions and fields than for others.
The former position accepts the consequence that the ethical codes of different
professions might conflict with one another, so that a physician in business
might find that business ethics would require one action but medical ethics
another. Engineers who have been promoted to management positions sometimes
express concern over the tension between what they perceive to be their responsibility
as engineers and their responsibility as managers in a business. Many lawyers
seem to hold that there is similar tension between what common morality
requires and what they must do as lawyers. Those who accept a universal
morality hold that these tensions are all resolvable because there is only one
common morality. Underlying both positions is the pervasive but false view of
common morality as providing a unique right answer to every moral problem.
Those who hold that each profession or field has its own moral code do not
realize that common morality allows for conflicts of duties. Most of those who
put forward moral theories, e.g., utilitarians, Kantians, and contractarians,
attempt to generate a universal moral system that solves all moral problems.
This creates a situation that leads many in applied ethics to dismiss
theoretical ethics as irrelevant to their concerns. An alternative view of a
moral theory is to think of it on the model of a scientific theory, primarily
concerned to describe common morality rather than generate a new improved
version. On this model, it is clear that although morality rules out many
alternatives as unacceptable, it does not provide unique right answers to every
controversial moral question. On this model, different fields and different
professions may interpret the common moral system in somewhat different ways.
For example, although deception is always immoral if not justified, what counts
as deception is not the same in all professions. Not informing a patient of an
alternative treatment counts as deceptive for a physician, but not telling a
customer of an alternative to what she is about to buy does not count as
deceptive for a salesperson. The professions also have considerable input into
what special duties are incurred by becoming a member of their profession.
Applied ethics is thus not the mechanical application of a common morality to a
particular profession or field, but an independent discipline that clarifies
and analyzes the practices in a field or profession so that common morality can
be applied.
a priori: Obviously
contrasted to ‘a posteriori,’ but not necessarily in termporal terms -- Grice
was fascinated by the apriori, both analytic but more so the synthetic. He
would question his children’s playmates with things like, “Can a sweater be
green and red all over? No striped allowed.” a priori, prior to or independent
of experience; contrasted with ‘a posteriori’ empirical. These two terms are
primarily used to mark a distinction between 1 two modes of epistemic
justification, together with derivative distinctions between 2 kinds of
propositions, 3 kinds of knowledge, and 4 kinds of argument. They are also used
to indicate a distinction between 5 two ways in which a concept or idea may be
acquired. 1 A belief or claim is said to be justified a priori if its epistemic
justification, the reason or warrant for thinking it to be true, does not
depend at all on sensory or introspective or other sorts of experience; whereas
if its justification does depend at least in part on such experience, it is
said to be justified a posteriori or empirically. This specific distinction has
to do only with the justification of the belief, and not at all with how the
constituent concepts are acquired; thus it is no objection to a claim of a
priori justificatory status for a particular belief that experience is required
for the acquisition of some of the constituent concepts. It is clear that the
relevant notion of experience includes sensory and introspective experience, as
well as such things as kinesthetic experience. Equally clearly, to construe
experience in the broadest possible sense of, roughly, a conscious undergoing
of any sort would be to destroy the point of the distinction, since even a
priori justification presumably involves some sort of conscious process of
awareness. The construal that is perhaps most faithful to the traditional usage
is that which construes experience as any sort of cognitive input that derives,
presumably causally, from features of the actual world that may not hold in
other possible worlds. Thus, e.g., such things as clairvoyance or telepathy, if
they were to exist, would count as forms of experience and any knowledge
resulting therefrom as a posteriori; but the intuitive apprehension of properties
or numbers or other sorts of abstract entities that are the same in all
possible worlds, would not. Understood in this way, the concept of a priori
justification is an essentially negative concept, specifying as it does what
the justification of the belief does not depend on, but saying nothing a priori
a priori 35 35 about what it does
depend on. Historically, the main positive conception was that offered by
proponents of rationalism such as Plato, Descartes, Spinoza, and Leibniz,
according to which a priori justification derives from the intuitive
apprehension of necessary facts pertaining to universals and other abstract
entities. Although Kant is often regarded as a rationalist, his restriction of
substantive a priori knowledge to the world of appearances represents a major
departure from the main rationalist tradition. In contrast, proponents of
traditional empiricism, if they do not repudiate the concept of a priori
justification altogether as does Quine, typically attempt to account for such justification
by appeal to linguistic or conceptual conventions. The most standard
formulation of this empiricist view a development of the view of Hume that all
a priori knowledge pertains to “relations of ideas” is the claim typical of
logical positivism that all a priori knowable claims or propositions are
analytic. A rationalist would claim in opposition that at least some a priori
claims or propositions are synthetic. 2 A proposition that is the content of an
a priori justified belief is often referred to as an a priori proposition or an
a priori truth. This usage is also often extended to include any proposition
that is capable of being the content of such a belief, whether it actually has
this status or not. 3 If, in addition to being justified a priori or a
posteriori, a belief is also true and satisfies whatever further conditions may
be required for it to constitute knowledge, that knowledge is derivatively
characterized as a priori or a posteriori empirical, respectively. Though a
priori justification is often regarded as by itself guaranteeing truth, this
should be regarded as a further substantive thesis, not as part of the very
concept of a priori justification. Examples of knowledge that have been
classically regarded as a priori in this sense are mathematical knowledge,
knowledge of logical truths, and knowledge of necessary entailments and
exclusions of commonsense concepts ‘Nothing can be red and green all over at
the same time’, ‘If A is later than B and B is later than C, then A is later than
C’; but many claims of metaphysics, ethics, and even theology have also been
claimed to have this status. 4 A deductively valid argument that also satisfies
the further condition that each of the premises or sometimes one or more
particularly central premises are justified a priori is referred to as an a
priori argument. This label is also sometimes applied to arguments that are
claimed to have this status, even if the correctness of this claim is in
question. 5 In addition to the uses just catalogued that derive from the
distinction between modes of justification, the terms ‘a priori’ and ‘a
posteriori’ are also employed to distinguish two ways in which a concept or
idea might be acquired by an individual person. An a posteriori or empirical
concept or idea is one that is derived from experience, via a process of
abstraction or ostensive definition. In contrast, an a priori concept or idea
is one that is not derived from experience in this way and thus presumably does
not require any particular experience to be realized though the explicit
realization of such a concept might still require experience as a “trigger”.
The main historical account of such concepts, again held mainly by
rationalists, construes them as innate, either implanted in the mind by God or,
in the more contemporary version of the claim held by Chomsky, Fodor, and
others, resulting from evolutionary development. Concepts typically regarded as
having this sort of status include the concepts of substance, causation, God,
necessity, infinity, and many others. Empiricists, in contrast, typically hold
that all concepts are derived from experience. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “The
synthetic a priori.”
aquinas: --a strange
genitive for “Aquino,” the little village where the saint was born. while
Grice, being C. of E., would avoid Aquinas like the rats, he was aware of
Aquinas’s clever ‘intention-based semantics’ in his commentary of Aristotle’s
De Interpretatione. Saint Thomas 122574,
philosopher-theologian, the most influential thinker of the medieval period.
He produced a powerful philosophical synthesis that combined Aristotelian and
Neoplatonic elements within a Christian context in an original and ingenious
way. Life and works. Thomas was born at Aquino castle in Roccasecca, Italy, and
took early schooling at the Benedictine Abbey of Monte Cassino. He then studied
liberal arts and philosophy at the of
Naples 123944 and joined the Dominican order. While going to Paris for further
studies as a Dominican, he was detained by his family for about a year. Upon
being released, he studied with the Dominicans at Paris, perhaps privately,
until 1248, when he journeyed to a priori argument Aquinas, Saint Thomas
36 36 Cologne to work under Albertus
Magnus. Thomas’s own report reportatio of Albertus’s lectures on the Divine
Names of Dionysius and his notes on Albertus’s lectures on Aristotle’s Ethics
date from this period. In 1252 Thomas returned to Paris to lecture there as a
bachelor in theology. His resulting commentary on the Sentences of Peter
Lombard dates from this period, as do two philosophical treatises, On Being and
Essence De ente et essentia and On the Principles of Nature De principiis
naturae. In 1256 he began lecturing as master of theology at Paris. From this
period 125659 date a series of scriptural commentaries, the disputations On
Truth De veritate, Quodlibetal Questions VIIXI, and earlier parts of the Summa
against the Gentiles Summa contra gentiles; hereafter SCG. At different
locations in Italy from 1259 to 1269, Thomas continued to write prodigiously,
including, among other works, the completion of the SCG; a commentary on the
Divine Names; disputations On the Power of God De potentia Dei and On Evil De
malo; and Summa of Theology Summa theologiae; hereafter ST, Part I. In January
1269, he resumed teaching in Paris as regent master and wrote extensively until
returning to Italy in 1272. From this second Parisian regency date the
disputations On the Soul De anima and On Virtues De virtutibus; continuation of
ST; Quodlibets IVI and XII; On the Unity of the Intellect against the
Averroists De unitate intellectus contra Averroistas; most if not all of his
commentaries on Aristotle; a commentary on the Book of Causes Liber de causis;
and On the Eternity of the World De aeternitate mundi. In 1272 Thomas returned
to Italy where he lectured on theology at Naples and continued to write until
December 6, 1273, when his scholarly work ceased. He died three months later en
route to the Second Council of Lyons. Doctrine. Aquinas was both a philosopher
and a theologian. The greater part of his writings are theological, but there
are many strictly philosophical works within his corpus, such as On Being and
Essence, On the Principles of Nature, On the Eternity of the World, and the
commentaries on Aristotle and on the Book of Causes. Also important are large
sections of strictly philosophical writing incorporated into theological works
such as the SCG, ST, and various disputations. Aquinas clearly distinguishes
between strictly philosophical investigation and theological investigation. If
philosophy is based on the light of natural reason, theology sacra doctrina
presupposes faith in divine revelation. While the natural light of reason is
insufficient to discover things that can be made known to human beings only through
revelation, e.g., belief in the Trinity, Thomas holds that it is impossible for
those things revealed to us by God through faith to be opposed to those we can
discover by using human reason. For then one or the other would have to be
false; and since both come to us from God, God himself would be the author of
falsity, something Thomas rejects as abhorrent. Hence it is appropriate for the
theologian to use philosophical reasoning in theologizing. Aquinas also
distinguishes between the orders to be followed by the theologian and by the
philosopher. In theology one reasons from belief in God and his revelation to
the implications of this for created reality. In philosophy one begins with an
investigation of created reality insofar as this can be understood by human
reason and then seeks to arrive at some knowledge of divine reality viewed as
the cause of created reality and the end or goal of one’s philosophical inquiry
SCG II, c. 4. This means that the order Aquinas follows in his theological
Summae SCG and ST is not the same as that which he prescribes for the
philosopher cf. Prooemium to Commentary on the Metaphysics. Also underlying
much of Aquinas’s thought is his acceptance of the difference between
theoretical or speculative philosophy including natural philosophy,
mathematics, and metaphysics and practical philosophy. Being and analogy. For
Aquinas the highest part of philosophy is metaphysics, the science of being as
being. The subject of this science is not God, but being, viewed without
restriction to any given kind of being, or simply as being Prooemium to
Commentary on Metaphysics; In de trinitate, qu. 5, a. 4. The metaphysician does
not enjoy a direct vision of God in this life, but can reason to knowledge of
him by moving from created effects to awareness of him as their uncreated
cause. God is therefore not the subject of metaphysics, nor is he included in
its subject. God can be studied by the metaphysician only indirectly, as the
cause of the finite beings that fall under being as being, the subject of the
science. In order to account for the human intellect’s discovery of being as
being, in contrast with being as mobile studied by natural philosophy or being
as quantified studied by mathematics, Thomas appeals to a special kind of
intellectual operation, a negative judgment, technically named by him
“separation.” Through this operation one discovers that being, in order to be
realized as such, need not be material and changAquinas, Saint Thomas Aquinas,
Saint Thomas 37 37 ing. Only as a result
of this judgment is one justified in studying being as being. Following
Aristotle and Averroes, Thomas is convinced that the term ‘being’ is used in
various ways and with different meanings. Yet these different usages are not
unrelated and do enjoy an underlying unity sufficient for being as being to be
the subject of a single science. On the level of finite being Thomas adopts and
adapts Aristotle’s theory of unity by reference to a first order of being. For
Thomas as for Aristotle this unity is guaranteed by the primary referent in our
predication of being substance. Other
things are named being only because they are in some way ordered to and
dependent on substance, the primary instance of being. Hence being is
analogous. Since Thomas’s application of analogy to the divine names
presupposes the existence of God, we shall first examine his discussion of that
issue. The existence of God and the “five ways.” Thomas holds that unaided
human reason, i.e., philosophical reason, can demonstrate that God exists, that
he is one, etc., by reasoning from effect to cause De trinitate, qu. 2, a. 3;
SCG I, c. 4. Best-known among his many presentations of argumentation for God’s
existence are the “five ways.” Perhaps even more interesting for today’s
student of his metaphysics is a brief argument developed in one of his first
writings, On Being and Essence c.4. There he wishes to determine how essence is
realized in what he terms “separate substances,” i.e., the soul, intelligences
angels of the Christian tradition, and the first cause God. After criticizing
the view that created separate substances are composed of matter and form,
Aquinas counters that they are not entirely free from composition. They are
composed of a form or essence and an act of existing esse. He immediately
develops a complex argument: 1 We can think of an essence or quiddity without
knowing whether or not it actually exists. Therefore in such entities essence
and act of existing differ unless 2 there is a thing whose quiddity and act of
existing are identical. At best there can be only one such being, he continues,
by eliminating multiplication of such an entity either through the addition of
some difference or through the reception of its form in different instances of
matter. Hence, any such being can only be separate and unreceived esse, whereas
esse in all else is received in something else, i.e., essence. 3 Since esse in
all other entities is therefore distinct from essence or quiddity, existence is
communicated to such beings by something else, i.e., they are caused. Since
that which exists through something else must be traced back to that which
exists of itself, there must be some thing that causes the existence of
everything else and that is identical with its act of existing. Otherwise one would
regress to infinity in caused causes of existence, which Thomas here dismisses
as unacceptable. In qu. 2, a. 1 of ST I Thomas rejects the claim that God’s
existence is self-evident to us in this life, and in a. 2 maintains that God’s
existence can be demonstrated by reasoning from knowledge of an existing effect
to knowledge of God as the cause required for that effect to exist. The first
way or argument art. 3 rests upon the fact that various things in our world of
sense experience are moved. But whatever is moved is moved by something else.
To justify this, Thomas reasons that to be moved is to be reduced from
potentiality to actuality, and that nothing can reduce itself from potency to
act; for it would then have to be in potency if it is to be moved and in act at
the same time and in the same respect. This does not mean that a mover must
formally possess the act it is to communicate to something else if it is to
move the latter; it must at least possess it virtually, i.e., have the power to
communicate it. Whatever is moved, therefore, must be moved by something else.
One cannot regress to infinity with moved movers, for then there would be no
first mover and, consequently, no other mover; for second movers do not move
unless they are moved by a first mover. One must, therefore, conclude to the
existence of a first mover which is moved by nothing else, and this “everyone
understands to be God.” The second way takes as its point of departure an
ordering of efficient causes as indicated to us by our investigation of
sensible things. By this Thomas means that we perceive in the world of sensible
things that certain efficient causes cannot exercise their causal activity
unless they are also caused by something else. But nothing can be the efficient
cause of itself, since it would then have to be prior to itself. One cannot
regress to infinity in ordered efficient causes. In ordered efficient causes,
the first is the cause of the intermediary, and the intermediary is the cause
of the last whether the intermediary is one or many. Hence if there were no
first efficient cause, there would be no intermediary and no last cause. Thomas
concludes from this that one must acknowledge the existence of a first
efficient cause, “which everyone names God.” The third way consists of two
major parts. Some Aquinas, Saint Thomas Aquinas, Saint Thomas 38 38 textual variants have complicated the
proper interpretation of the first part. In brief, Aquinas appeals to the fact
that certain things are subject to generation and corruption to show that they
are “possible,” i.e., capable of existing and not existing. Not all things can
be of this kind revised text, for that which has the possibility of not
existing at some time does not exist. If, therefore, all things are capable of
not existing, at some time there was nothing whatsoever. If that were so, even
now there would be nothing, since what does not exist can only begin to exist
through something else that exists. Therefore not all beings are capable of
existing and not existing. There must be some necessary being. Since such a
necessary, i.e., incorruptible, being might still be caused by something else,
Thomas adds a second part to the argument. Every necessary being either depends
on something else for its necessity or it does not. One cannot regress to
infinity in necessary beings that depend on something else for their necessity.
Therefore there must be some being that is necessary of itself and that does
not depend on another cause for its necessity, i.e., God. The statement in the
first part to the effect that what has the possibility of not existing at some
point does not exist has been subject to considerable dispute among
commentators. Moreover, even if one grants this and supposes that every
individual being is a “possible” and therefore has not existed at some point in
the past, it does not easily follow from this that the totality of existing
things will also have been nonexistent at some point in the past. Given this,
some interpreters prefer to substitute for the third way the more satisfactory
versions found in SCG I ch. 15 and SCG II ch. 15. Thomas’s fourth way is based
on the varying degrees of perfection we discover among the beings we
experience. Some are more or less good, more or less true, more or less noble, etc.,
than others. But the more and less are said of different things insofar as they
approach in varying degrees something that is such to a maximum degree.
Therefore there is something that is truest and best and noblest and hence that
is also being to the maximum degree. To support this Thomas comments that those
things that are true to the maximum degree also enjoy being to the maximum
degree; in other words he appeals to the convertibility between being and truth
of being. In the second part of this argument Thomas argues that what is
supremely such in a given genus is the cause of all other things in that genus.
Therefore there is something that is the cause of being, goodness, etc., for
all other beings, and this we call God. Much discussion has centered on
Thomas’s claim that the more and less are said of different things insofar as
they approach something that is such to the maximum degree. Some find this
insufficient to justify the conclusion that a maximum must exist, and would
here insert an appeal to efficient causality and his theory of participation.
If certan entities share or participate in such a perfection only to a limited
degree, they must receive that perfection from something else. While more
satisfactory from a philosophical perspective, such an insertion seems to
change the argument of the fourth way significantly. The fifth way is based on
the way things in the universe are governed. Thomas observes that certain
things that lack the ability to know, i.e., natural bodies, act for an end.
This follows from the fact that they always or at least usually act in the same
way to attain that which is best. For Thomas this indicates that they reach
their ends by “intention” and not merely from chance. And this in turn implies
that they are directed to their ends by some knowing and intelligent being.
Hence some intelligent being exists that orders natural things to their ends.
This argument rests on final causality and should not be confused with any
based on order and design. Aquinas’s frequently repeated denial that in this
life we can know what God is should here be recalled. If we can know that God
exists and what he is not, we cannot know what he is see, e.g., SCG I, c. 30.
Even when we apply the names of pure perfections to God, we first discover such
perfections in limited fashion in creatures. What the names of such perfections
are intended to signify may indeed be free from all imperfection, but every
such name carries with it some deficiency in the way in which it signifies.
When a name such as ‘goodness’, for instance, is signified abstractly e.g.,
‘God is goodness’, this abstract way of signifying suggests that goodness does
not subsist in itself. When such a name is signified concretely e.g., ‘God is
good’, this concrete way of signifying implies some kind of composition between
God and his goodness. Hence while such names are to be affirmed of God as
regards that which they signify, the way in which they signify is to be denied
of him. This final point sets the stage for Thomas to apply his theory of
analogy to the divine names. Names of pure perfections such as ‘good’, ‘true’,
‘being’, etc., cannot be applied to God with Aquinas, Saint Thomas Aquinas,
Saint Thomas 39 39 exactly the same
meaning they have when affirmed of creatures univocally, nor with entirely
different meanings equivocally. Hence they are affirmed of God and of creatures
by an analogy based on the relationship that obtains between a creature viewed
as an effect and God its uncaused cause. Because some minimum degree of
similarity must obtain between any effect and its cause, Thomas is convinced
that in some way a caused perfection imitates and participates in God, its
uncaused and unparticipated source. Because no caused effect can ever be equal
to its uncreated cause, every perfection that we affirm of God is realized in
him in a way different from the way we discover it in creatures. This
dissimilarity is so great that we can never have quidditative knowledge of God
in this life know what God is. But the similarity is sufficient for us to
conclude that what we understand by a perfection such as goodness in creatures
is present in God in unrestricted fashion. Even though Thomas’s identification
of the kind of analogy to be used in predicating divine names underwent some
development, in mature works such as On the Power of God qu. 7, a. 7, SCG I
c.34, and ST I qu. 13, a. 5, he identifies this as the analogy of “one to
another,” rather than as the analogy of “many to one.” In none of these works
does he propose using the analogy of “proportionality” that he had previously
defended in On Truth qu. 2, a. 11. Theological virtues. While Aquinas is
convinced that human reason can arrive at knowledge that God exists and at
meaningful predication of the divine names, he does not think the majority of
human beings will actually succeed in such an effort SCG I, c. 4; ST IIIIae,
qu. 2, a. 4. Hence he concludes that it was fitting for God to reveal such
truths to mankind along with others that purely philosophical inquiry could
never discover even in principle. Acceptance of the truth of divine revelation
presupposes the gift of the theological virtue of faith in the believer. Faith
is an infused virtue by reason of which we accept on God’s authority what he
has revealed to us. To believe is an act of the intellect that assents to
divine truth as a result of a command on the part of the human will, a will
that itself is moved by God through grace ST II IIae, qu. 2, a. 9. For Thomas
the theological virtues, having God the ultimate end as their object, are prior
to all other virtues whether natural or infused. Because the ultimate end must
be present in the intellect before it is present to the will, and because the
ultimate end is present in the will by reason of hope and charity the other two
theological virtues, in this respect faith is prior to hope and charity. Hope
is the theological virtue through which we trust that with divine assistance we
will attain the infinite good eternal
enjoyment of God ST IIIIae, qu. 17, aa. 12. In the order of generation, hope is
prior to charity; but in the order of perfection charity is prior both to hope
and faith. While neither faith nor hope will remain in those who reach the
eternal vision of God in the life to come, charity will endure in the blessed.
It is a virtue or habitual form that is infused into the soul by God and that
inclines us to love him for his own sake. If charity is more excellent than
faith or hope ST II IIae, qu. 23, a. 6, through charity the acts of all other
virtues are ordered to God, their ultimate end qu. 23, a. 8.
ars: techne Grecian, ‘art’, ‘craft’, a human skill based
on general principles and capable of being taught. In this sense, a manual
craft such as carpentry is a techne, but so are sciences such as medicine and
arithmetic. According to Plato Gorgias 501a, a genuine techne understands its
subject matter and can give a rational account of its activity. Aristotle
Metaphysics I.1 distinguishes technefrom experience on the grounds that techne
involves knowledge of universals and causes, and can be taught. Sometimes
‘techne’ is restricted to the productive as opposed to theoretical and
practical arts, as at Nicomachean Ethics VI.4. Techne and its products are
often contrasted with physis, nature Physics II.1.
arbitrium: arminius, Jacobus
15601609, Dutch theologian who, as a Dutch Reformed pastor and later professor
at the of Leiden, challenged Calvinist
orthodoxy on predestination and free will. After his death, followers codified
Arminius’s views in a document asserting that God’s grace is necessary for
salvation, but not irresistible: the divine decree depends on human free
choice. This became the basis for Arminianism, which was condemned by the Dutch
ReAristotle, commentaries on Arminius, Jacobus 51 51 formed synod but vigorously debated for
centuries among Protestant theologians of different denominations. The term
‘Arminian’ is still occasionally applied to theologians who defend a free human
response to divine grace against predestinationism.
arcesilaus: Grecian,
pre-Griceian, sceptic philosopher, founder of the Middle Academy. Influenced by
Socratic elenchus, he claimed that, unlike Socrates, he was not even certain
that he was certain of nothing. He shows the influence of Pyrrho in attacking
the Stoic doctrine that the subjective certainty of the wise is the criterion
of truth. At the theoretical level he advocated epoche, suspension of rational
judgment; at the practical, he argued that eulogon, probability, can justify
action an early version of coherentism.
His ethical views were not extreme; he held, e.g., that one should attend to
one’s own life rather than external objects. Though he wrote nothing except
verse, he led the Academy into two hundred years of Skepticism.
archytas: Grecian,
pre-Griceian, Pythagorean philosopher from Tarentum in southern Italy. He was
elected general seven times and sent a ship to rescue Plato from Dionysius II
of Syracuse in 361. He is famous for solutions to specific mathematical
problems, such as the doubling of the cube, but little is known about his
general philosophical principles. His proof that the numbers in a
superparticular ratio have no mean proportional has relevance to music theory,
as does his work with the arithmetic, geometric, and harmonic means. He gave
mathematical accounts of the diatonic, enharmonic, and chromatic scales and
developed a theory of acoustics. Fragments 1 and 2 and perhaps 3 are authentic,
but most material preserved in his name is spurious.
aretaic: sometimes
used by Grice for ‘virtuosum’. arete, ancient Grecian term meaning ‘virtue’ or
‘excellence’. In philosophical contexts, the term was used mainly of virtues of
human character; in broader contexts, arete was applicable to many different
sorts of excellence. The cardinal virtues in the classical period were courage,
wisdom, temperance sophrosune, piety, and justice. Sophists such as Protagoras
claimed to teach such virtues, and Socrates challenged their credentials for
doing so. Several early Platonic dialogues show Socrates asking after definitions
of virtues, and Socrates investigates arete in other dialogues as well.
Conventional views allowed that a person can have one virtue such as courage
but lack another such as wisdom, but Plato’s Protagoras shows Socrates
defending his thesis of the unity of arete, which implies that a person who has
one arete has them all. Platonic accounts of the cardinal virtues with the
exception of piety are given in Book IV of the Republic. Substantial parts of
the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle are given over to discussions of arete,
which he divides into virtues of character and virtues of intellect. This
discussion is the ancestor of most modern theories of virtue ethics.
argumentum:
cited
by Grice in “Aspects of reason.” Grice was Strawson’s tutor for the Logic
Paper, and he had to go with him over the ‘boring theory of the syllogism –
Barbara, Celarent, and the reset of them!” -- syllogism, in Aristotle’s words,
“a discourse in which, a certain thing being stated, something other than what
is stated follows of necessity from being so” Prior Analytics, 24b 18. Three
types of syllogism were usually distinguished: categorical, hypothetical, and
disjunctive. Each will be treated in that order. The categorical syllogism.
This is an argument consisting of three categorical propositions, two serving
as premises and one serving as conclusion. E.g., ‘Some students are happy; all students are high school graduates;
therefore, some high school graduates are happy’. If a syllogism is valid, the
premises must be so related to the conclusion that it is impossible for both
premises to be true and the conclusion false. There are four types of
categorical propositions: universal affirmative or A-propositions ‘All S are P’, or ‘SaP’; universal negative
or E-propositions ‘No S are P’, or
‘SeP’; particular affirmative or I-propositions
‘Some S are P’, or ‘SiP’; and particular negative or O-propositions:
‘Some S are not P’, or ‘SoP’. The mediate basic components of categorical
syllogism are terms serving as subjects or predicates in the premises and the
conclusion. There must be three and only three terms in any categorical
syllogism, the major term, the minor term, and the middle term. Violation of
this basic rule of structure is called the fallacy of four terms quaternio
terminorum; e.g., ‘Whatever is right is useful; only one of my hands is right;
therefore only one of my hands is useful’. Here ‘right’ does not have the same
meaning in its two occurrences; we therefore have more than three terms and
hence no genuine categorical syllogism. The syllogistic terms are identifiable
and definable with reference to the position they have in a given syllogism.
The predicate of the conclusion is the major term; the subject of the
conclusion is the minor term; the term that appears once in each premise but
not in the conclusion is the middle term. As it is used in various types of
categorical propositions, a term is either distributed stands for each and
every member of its extension or undistributed. There is a simple rule regarding
the distribution: universal propositions SaP and SeP distribute their subject
terms; negative propositions SeP and SoP distribute their predicate terms. No
terms are distributed in an I-proposition. Various sets of rules governing
validity of categorical syllogisms have been offered. The following is a
“traditional” set from the popular Port-Royal Logic 1662. R1: The middle term
must be distributed at least once. Violation: ‘All cats are animals; some
animals do not eat liver; therefore some cats do not eat liver’. The middle
term ‘animals’ is not distributed either in the first or minor premise, being
the predicate of an affirmative proposition, nor in the second or major
premise, being the subject of a particular proposition; hence, the fallacy of
undistributed middle. R2: A term cannot be distributed in the conclusion if it
is undistributed in the premises. Violation: ‘All dogs are carnivorous; no
flowers are dogs; therefore, no flowers are carnivorous’. Here the major,
‘carnivorous’, is distributed in the conclusion, being the predicate of a
negative proposition, but not in the premise, serving there as predicate of an
affirmative proposition; hence, the fallacy of illicit major term. Another
violation of R2: ‘All students are happy individuals; no criminals are
students; therefore, no happy individuals are criminals’. Here the minor,
‘happy individuals’, is distributed in the conclusion, but not distributed in
the minor premise; hence the fallacy of illicit minor term. R3: No conclusion
may be drawn from two negative premises. Violation: ‘No dogs are cats; some
dogs do not like liver; therefore, some cats do not like liver’. Here R1 is
satisfied, since the middle term ‘dogs’ is distributed in the minor premise; R2
is satisfied, since both the minor term ‘cats’ as well as the major term
‘things that like liver’ are distributed in the premises and thus no violation
of distribution of terms occurs. It is only by virtue of R3 that we can
proclaim this syllogism to be invalid. R4: A negative conclusion cannot be
drawn where both premises are affirmative. Violation: ‘All educated people take
good care of their children; all syllogism syllogism 894 894 who take good care of their children are
poor; therefore, some poor people are not educated’. Here, it is only by virtue
of the rule of quality, R4, that we can proclaim this syllogism invalid. R5:
The conclusion must follow the weaker premise; i.e., if one of the premises is
negative, the conclusion must be negative, and if one of them is particular,
the conclusion must be particular. R6: From two particular premises nothing
follows. Let us offer an indirect proof for this rule. If both particular
premises are affirmative, no term is distributed and therefore the fallacy of
undistributed middle is inevitable. To avoid it, we have to make one of the
premises negative, which will result in a distributed predicate as middle term.
But by R5, the conclusion must then be negative; thus, the major term will be
distributed in the conclusion. To avoid violating R2, we must distribute that
term in the major premise. It could not be in the position of subject term,
since only universal propositions distribute their subject term and, by
hypothesis, both premises are particular. But we could not use the same
negative premise used to distribute the middle term; we must make the other
particular premise negative. But then we violate R3. Thus, any attempt to make
a syllogism with two particular premises valid will violate one or more basic
rules of syllogism. This set of rules assumes that A- and Epropositions have
existential import and hence that an I- or an O-proposition may legitimately be
drawn from a set of exclusively universal premises. Categorical syllogisms are
classified according to figure and mood. The figure of a categorical syllogism
refers to the schema determined by the possible position of the middle term in
relation to the major and minor terms. In “modern logic,” four syllogistic
figures are recognized. Using ‘M’ for middle term, ‘P’ for major term, and ‘S’
for minor term, they can be depicted as follows: Aristotle recognized only
three syllogistic figures. He seems to have taken into account just the two
premises and the extension of the three terms occurring in them, and then asked
what conclusion, if any, can be derived from those premises. It turns out,
then, that his procedure leaves room for three figures only: one in which the M
term is the subject of one and predicate of the other premise; another in which
the M term is predicated in both premises; and a third one in which the M term
is the subject in both premises. Medievals followed him, although all
considered the so-called inverted first i.e., moods of the first figure with
their conclusion converted either simply or per accidens to be legitimate also.
Some medievals e.g., Albalag and most moderns since Leibniz recognize a fourth
figure as a distinct figure, considering syllogistic terms on the basis not of
their extension but of their position in the conclusion, the S term of the
conclusion being defined as the minor term and the P term being defined as the
major term. The mood of a categorical syllogism refers to the configuration of
types of categorical propositions determined on the basis of the quality and
quantity of the propositions serving as premises and conclusion of any given
syllogism; e.g., ‘No animals are plants; all cats are animals; therefore no
cats are plants’, ‘MeP, SaM /, SeP’, is a syllogism in the mood EAE in the
first figure. ‘All metals conduct electricity; no stones conduct electricity;
therefore no stones are metals’, ‘PaM, SeM /, SeP’, is the mood AEE in the
second figure. In the four syllogistic figures there are 256 possible moods,
but only 24 are valid only 19 in modern logic, on the ground of a
non-existential treatment of A- and E-propositions. As a mnemonic device and to
facilitate reference, names have been assigned to the valid moods, with each
vowel representing the type of categorical proposition. William Sherwood and
Peter of Spain offered the famous list designed to help students to remember
which moods in any given figure are valid and how the “inevident” moods in the
second and third figures are provable by reduction to those in the first
figure: barbara, celarent, darii, ferio direct Fig. 1; baralipton, celantes,
dabitis, fapesmo, frisesomorum indirect Fig. 1; cesare, camestres, festino,
baroco Fig. 2; darapti, felapton, disamis, datisi, bocardo, ferison Fig. 3. The
hypothetical syllogism. The pure hypothetical syllogism is an argument in which
both the premises and the conclusion are hypothetical, i.e. conditional,
propositions; e.g., ‘If the sun is shining, it is warm; if it is warm, the
plants will grow; therefore if the sun is shining, the plants will grow’.
Symbolically, this argument form can be represented by ‘A P B, B P C /, A P C’.
It was not recognized as such by Aristotle, but Aristotle’s pupil Theophrastus
foreshadowed it, even syllogism syllogism 895
895 though it is not clear from his example of it ‘If man is, animal is; if animal is, then
substance is; if therefore man is, substance is’ whether this was seen to be a principle of
term logic or a principle of propositional logic. It was the MegaricStoic
philosophers and Boethius who fully recognized hypothetical propositions and
syllogisms as principles of the most general theory of deduction. Mixed
hypothetical syllogisms are arguments consisting of a hypothetical premise and
a categorical premise, and inferring a categorical proposition; e.g., ‘If the
sun is shining, the plants will grow; the sun is shining; therefore the plants
will grow’. Symbolically, this is represented by ‘P P Q, P /, Q’. This argument
form was explicitly formulated in ancient times by the Stoics as one of the
“indemonstrables” and is now known as modus ponens. Another equally basic form
of mixed hypothetical syllogism is ‘P P Q, -Q /, ~P’, known as modus tollens.
The disjunctive syllogism. This is an argument in which the leading premise is
a disjunction, the other premise being a denial of one of the alternatives,
concluding to the remaining alternative; e.g., ‘It is raining or I will go for
a walk; but it is not raining; therefore I will go for a walk’. It is not
always clear whether the ‘or’ of the disjunctive premise is inclusive or
exclusive. Symbolic logic removes the ambiguity by using two different symbols
and thus clearly distinguishes between inclusive or weak disjunction, ‘P 7 Q’,
which is true provided not both alternatives are false, and exclusive or strong
disjunction, ‘P W Q’, which is true provided exactly one alternative is true
and exactly one false. The definition of ‘disjunctive syllogism’ presupposes
that the lead premise is an inclusive or weak disjunction, on the basis of
which two forms are valid: ‘P 7 Q, -P /, Q’ and ‘P 7 Q, -Q /, P’. If the
disjunctive premise is exclusive, we have four valid argument forms, and we should speak here of an exclusive disjunctive
syllogism. This is defined as an argument in which either from an exclusive
disjunction and the denial of one of its disjuncts we infer the remaining
disjunct ’P W Q, -P /,Q’, and ‘P W Q, -Q
/, P’ modus tollendo ponens; or else, from an exclusive disjunction and one of
its disjuncts we infer the denial of the remaining disjunct ’P W Q, P /, -Q’, and ‘P W Q, Q /,-P’ modus
ponendo tollens. “Strictly, ‘argumetum’ is ‘what is argued,’
the passive perfect participle – arguens is the present active participle,
‘argumentatio’ the feminine abstract noun, and ‘argumentarus,’ and
‘argumentarum’ the neuter active future participle. – there is the
argumenttaturum, too.”“I thought I saw an argument, it turned to be some soap”
(Dodgson). Term that Grice borrows from (but “never returned” to) Boethius, the
Roman philosopher. Strictly, Grice is interested in the ‘arguer.’ Say Blackburn
goes to Grice and, not knowing Grice speaks English, writes a skull. Blackburn
intends Grice to think that there is danger, somewhere, even deadly danger. So
there is arguing on Blackburn’s part. And there is INTENDED arguing on
Blackburn’s recipient, Grice, as it happens. For Grice, the truth-value of
“Blackburn communicates (to Grice) that there is danger” does not REQUIRE the
uptake.” “Why, one must just as well require that Jones GETS his job to deem
Smith having GIVEN it to him if that’s what he’s promised. The arguer is
invoked in a self-psi-transmission. For he must think P, and he must think C,
and he must think that P yields C. And this thought that C must be CAUSED by
the fact that he thinks that P yields C. -- f. argŭo , ŭi, ūtum (ŭĭtum, hence
arguiturus, Sall. Fragm. ap. Prisc. p. 882 P.), 3, v. a. cf. ἀργής, white; ἀργός,
bright; Sanscr. árgunas, bright; ragatas, white; and rag, to shine (v. argentum
and argilla); after the same analogy we have clarus, bright; and claro, to make
bright, to make evident; and the Engl. clear, adj., and to clear = to make
clear; v. Georg Curtius p. 171. I. A.. In gen., to make clear, to show,
prove, make known, declare, assert, μηνύειν: “arguo Eam me vidisse intus,”
Plaut. Mil. 2, 3, 66: “non ex auditu arguo,” id. Bacch. 3, 3, 65: “M. Valerius
Laevinus ... speculatores, non legatos, venisse arguebat,” Liv. 30, 23:
“degeneres animos timor arguit,” Verg. A. 4, 13: “amantem et languor et
silentium Arguit,” Hor. Epod. 11, 9; id. C. 1, 13, 7.—Pass., in a mid. signif.:
“apparet virtus arguiturque malis,” makes itself known, Ov. Tr. 4, 3, 80:
“laudibus arguitur vini vinosus Homerus,” betrays himself, Hor. Ep. 1, 19, 6.—
B. Esp. a. With aliquem, to attempt to show something, in one's case, against
him, to accuse, reprove, censure, charge with: Indicāsse est detulisse;
“arguisse accusāsse et convicisse,” Dig. 50, 16, 197 (cf. Fest. p. 22: Argutum
iri in discrimen vocari): tu delinquis, ego arguar pro malefactis? Enn. (as
transl. of Eurip. Iphig. Aul. 384: Εἶτ̓ ἐγὼ δίκην δῶ σῶν κακῶν ὁ μὴ σφαλείς)
ap. Rufin. § “37: servos ipsos neque accuso neque arguo neque purgo,” Cic.
Rosc. Am. 41, 120: “Pergin, sceleste, intendere hanc arguere?” Plaut. Mil. 2,
4, 27; 2, 2, 32: “hae tabellae te arguunt,” id. Bacch. 4, 6, 10: “an hunc porro
tactum sapor arguet oris?” Lucr. 4, 487: “quod adjeci, non ut arguerem, sed ne
arguerer,” Vell. 2, 53, 4: “coram aliquem arguere,” Liv. 43, 5: “apud
praefectum,” Tac. A. 14, 41: “(Deus) arguit te heri,” Vulg. Gen. 31, 42; ib.
Lev. 19, 17; ib. 2 Tim. 4, 2; ib. Apoc. 3, 19 al.— b. With the cause of complaint
in the gen.; abl. with or without de; with in with abl.; with acc.; with a
clause as object; or with ut (cf. Ramsh. p. 326; Zumpt, § 446). (α). With gen.:
“malorum facinorum,” Plaut. Ps. 2, 4, 56 (cf. infra, argutus, B. 2.): “aliquem
probri, Stupri, dedecoris,” id. Am. 3, 2, 2: “viros mortuos summi sceleris,”
Cic. Rab. Perd. 9, 26: “aliquem tanti facinoris,” id. Cael. 1: “criminis,” Tac.
H. 1, 48: “furti me arguent,” Vulg. Gen. 30, 33; ib. Eccl. 11, 8:
“repetundarum,” Tac. A. 3, 33: “occupandae rei publicae,” id. ib. 6, 10:
“neglegentiae,” Suet. Caes. 53: “noxae,” id. Aug. 67: “veneni in se comparati,”
id. Tib. 49: “socordiae,” id. Claud. 3: “mendacii,” id. Oth. 10: “timoris,”
Verg. A. 11, 384: “sceleris arguemur,” Vulg. 4 Reg. 7, 9; ib. Act. 19, 40 al.—
(β). With abl.: “te hoc crimine non arguo,” Cic. Verr. 2, 5, 18; Nep. Paus. 3
fin.— (γ). With de: “de eo crimine, quo de arguatur,” Cic. Inv 2, 11, 37: “de
quibus quoniam verbo arguit, etc.,” id. Rosc. Am. 29 fin.: “Quis arguet me de
peccato?” Vulg. Joan. 8, 46; 16, 8.— (δ). With in with abl. (eccl. Lat.): “non
in sacrificiis tuis arguam te,” Vulg. Psa. 49, 8.—(ε) With acc.: quid
undas Arguit et liquidam molem camposque natantīs? of what does he impeach the
waves? etc., quid being here equivalent to cujus or de quo, Lucr. 6, 405
Munro.—(ζ)
With an inf.-clause as object: “quae (mulier) me arguit Hanc domo ab se
subripuisse,” Plaut. Men. 5, 2, 62; id. Mil. 2, 4, 36: “occidisse patrem Sex.
Roscius arguitur,” Cic. Rosc. Am. 13, 37: “auctor illius injuriae fuisse
arguebatur?” Cic. Verr. 2, 1, 33: “qui sibimet vim ferro intulisse arguebatur,”
Suet. Claud. 16; id. Ner. 33; id. Galb. 7: “me Arguit incepto rerum accessisse
labori,” Ov. M. 13, 297; 15, 504.—(η) With ut, as in
Gr. ὡς (post-Aug. and rare), Suet. Ner. 7: “hunc ut dominum et tyrannum, illum
ut proditorem arguentes,” as being master and tyrant, Just. 22, 3.— II. Transf.
to the thing. 1. To accuse, censure, blame: “ea culpa, quam arguo,” Liv. 1, 28:
“peccata coram omnibus argue,” Vulg. 1 Tim. 5, 20: “tribuni plebis dum arguunt
in C. Caesare regni voluntatem,” Vell. 2, 68; Suet. Tit. 5 fin.:
“taciturnitatem pudoremque quorumdam pro tristitiā et malignitate arguens,” id.
Ner. 23; id. Caes. 75: “arguebat et perperam editos census,” he accused of
giving a false statement of property, census, id. Calig. 38: “primusque
animalia mensis Arguit imponi,” censured, taught that it was wrong, Ov. M. 15,
73: “ut non arguantur opera ejus,” Vulg. Joan. 3, 20.— 2. Trop., to denounce as
false: “quod et ipsum Fenestella arguit,” Suet. Vit. Ter. p. 292 Roth.—With
reference to the person, to refute, confute: “aliquem,” Suet. Calig. 8.—Hence,
argūtus , a, um, P. a. A. Of physical objects, clear. 1. To the sight, bright,
glancing, lively: “manus autem minus arguta, digitis subsequens verba, non
exprimens,” not too much in motion, Cic. de Or. 3, 59, 220 (cf. id. Or. 18, 59:
nullae argutiae digitorum, and Quint. 11, 3, 119-123): “manus inter agendum
argutae admodum et gestuosae,” Gell. 1, 5, 2: “et oculi nimis arguti, quem ad
modum animo affecti sumus, loquuntur,” Cic. Leg. 1, 9, 27: “ocelli,” Ov. Am. 3,
3, 9; 3, 2, 83: “argutum caput,” a head graceful in motion, Verg. G. 3, 80
(breve, Servius, but this idea is too prosaic): aures breves et argutae, ears
that move quickly (not stiff, rigid), Pall. 4, 13, 2: “argutā in soleā,” in the
neat sandal, Cat. 68, 72.— 2. a.. To the hearing, clear, penetrating, piercing,
both of pleasant and disagreeable sounds, clear-sounding, sharp, noisy,
rustling, whizzing, rattling, clashing, etc. (mostly poet.): linguae, Naev. ap.
Non. p. 9, 24: “aves,” Prop. 1, 18, 30: “hirundo,” chirping, Verg. G. 1, 377:
“olores,” tuneful, id. E. 9, 36: ilex, murmuring, rustling (as moved by the
wind), id. ib. 7, 1: “nemus,” id. ib. 8, 22 al.—Hence, a poet. epithet of the
musician and poet, clear-sounding, melodious: “Neaera,” Hor. C. 3, 14, 21:
“poëtae,” id. Ep. 2, 2, 90: “fama est arguti Nemesis formosa Tibullus,” Mart.
8, 73, 7: forum, full of bustle or din, noisy, Ov. A.A. 1, 80: “serra,”
grating, Verg. G. 1, 143: “pecten,” rattling, id. ib. 1, 294; id. A. 7, 14 (cf.
in Gr. κερκὶς ἀοιδός, Aristoph. Ranae, v. 1316) al.—Hence, of rattling,
prating, verbose discourse: “sine virtute argutum civem mihi habeam pro
preaeficā, etc.,” Plaut. Truc. 2, 6, 14: “[Neque mendaciloquom neque adeo
argutum magis],” id. Trin. 1, 2, 163 Ritschl.— b. Trop., of written
communications, rattling, wordy, verbose: “obviam mihi litteras quam
argutissimas de omnibus rebus crebro mittas,” Cic. Att. 6, 5: vereor, ne tibi
nimium arguta haec sedulitas videatur, Cael. ap. Cic. Fam. 8, 1. —Transf. to
omens, clear, distinct, conclusive, clearly indicative, etc.: “sunt qui vel
argutissima haec exta esse dicant,” Cic. Div. 2, 12 fin.: “non tibi candidus
argutum sternuit omen Amor?” Prop. 2, 3, 24.— 3. To the smell; sharp, pungent:
“odor argutior,” Plin. 15, 3, 4, § 18.— 4. To the taste; sharp, keen, pungent:
“sapor,” Pall. 3, 25, 4; 4, 10, 26.— B. Of mental qualities. 1. In a good
sense, bright, acute, sagacious, witty: “quis illo (sc. Catone) acerbior in
vituperando? in sententiis argutior?” Cic. Brut. 17, 65: “orator,” id. ib. 70,
247: “poëma facit ita festivum, ita concinnum, ita elegans, nihil ut fieri
possit argutius,” id. Pis. 29; so, “dicta argutissima,” id. de Or. 2, 61, 250:
“sententiae,” id. Opt. Gen. 2: “acumen,” Hor. A. P. 364: “arguto ficta dolore
queri,” dexterously-feigned pain, Prop. 1, 18, 26 al.— 2. In a bad sense, sly,
artful, cunning: “meretrix,” Hor. S. 1, 10, 40: calo. id. Ep. 1, 14, 42:
“milites,” Veg. Mil. 3, 6.—As a pun: ecquid argutus est? is he cunning? Ch.
Malorum facinorum saepissime (i.e. has been accused of), Plaut. Ps. 2, 4, 56
(v. supra, I. B. a.).—Hence, adv.: argūtē (only in the signif. of B.). a.
Subtly, acutely: “respondere,” Cic. Cael. 8: “conicere,” id. Brut. 14, 53: “dicere,”
id. Or. 28, 98.—Comp.: “dicere,” Cic. Brut. 11, 42.— Sup.: “de re argutissime
disputare,” Cic. de Or. 2, 4, 18.— b. Craftily: “obrepere,” Plaut. Trin. 4, 2,
132; Arn. 5, p. 181. For Grice, an argumentum is a sequence of statements such
that some of them the premises purport to give reason to accept another of
them, the conclusion. Since we speak of bad arguments and weak arguments, the
premises of an argument need not really support the conclusion, but they must
give some appearance of doing so or the term ‘argument’ is misapplied. Logic is
mainly concerned with the question of validity: whether if the premises are
true we would have reason to accept the conclusion. A valid argument with true
premises is called sound. A valid deductive argument is one such that if we
accept the premises we are logically bound to accept the conclusion and if we
reject the conclusion we are logically bound to reject one or more of the
premises. Alternatively, the premises logically entail the conclusion. A good
inductive argument some would reserve
‘valid’ for deductive arguments is one
such that if we accept the premises we are logically bound to regard the
conclusion as probable, and, in addition, as more probable than it would be if
the premises should be false. A few arguments have only one premise and/or more
than one conclusion.
arbor griceiana: When Kant
introduces the categoric imperative in terms of the ‘maxim’ he does not specify which. He just goes,
irritatingly, “Make the maxim of your conduct a law of nature.” This gave free
rein to Grice to multiply maxims as much as he wished. If he was an occamist
about senses, he certainly was an anti-occamist about maxims. The expression
Strawson and Wiggins use (p. 520) is “ramification.”So Grice needs just ONE principle
– indeed the idea of principles, in plural, is self-contradictory. For whch
‘first’ is ‘first’? Eventually, he sticks with the principle of conversational
co-operation. And the principle of conversational co-operation, being
Ariskantian, and categoric, even if not ‘moral,’ “ramifies into” the maxims.
This is important. While an ‘ought’ cannot be derived from an ‘is,’ an ‘ought’
can yield a sub-ought. So whatever obligation the principle brings, the maxim
inherit. The maxim is also stated categoric. But it isn’t. It is a ‘counsel of
prudence,’ and hypothetical in nature – So, Grice is just ‘playing Kant,’ but
not ‘being’ Kant. The principle states the GOAL (not happiness, unless we call
it ‘conversational eudaemonia’). In any case, as Hare would agree, there is
‘deontic derivability.’ So if the principle ramifies into the maxims, the
maxims are ‘deductible’ from the principle. This deductibility is obvious in
terms of from generic to specific. The principle merely enjoins to make the
conversational move as is appropriate. Then, playing with Kant, Grice chooses
FOUR dimensions. Two correspond to the material: the quale and the quantum. The
quale relates to affirmation and negation, and Grice uses ‘false,’ which while
hardly conceptually linked to ‘negation,’ it relates in common parlance. So you
have things like a prohibition to say the ‘false’ (But “it is raining” can be
false, and it’s affirmative). The quantum relates to what Grice calls
‘informative CONTENT.’ He grants that the verb ‘inform’ already ENTAILS the
candour that quality brings. So ‘fortitude’ seems a better way to qualify this
dimension. Make the strongest conversational move. The clash with the quality
is obvious – “provided it’s not false.” The third dimension relates two two
materials. Notably the one by the previous conversationalist and your own. If A
said, “She is an old bag.” B says, “The weather’s been delightful.” By NOT
relating the ‘proposition’ “The weather has been delightful” to “She is an old
bag.” He ‘exploits’ the maxim. This is not a concept in Kant. It mocks Kant.
But yet, ‘relate!’ does follow from the principle of cooperation. So, there is
an UNDERLYING relation, as Hobbes noted, when he discussed a very distantly
related proposition concerning the history of Rome, and expecting the recipient
to “only connect.” So the ‘exploitation’ is ‘superficial,’ and applies to the
explicatum. Yet, the emissor does communicate that the weather has been
delightful. Only there is no point in informing the recipient about it, unless
he is communicating that the co-conversationalist has made a gaffe. Finally,
the category of ‘modus’ Grice restricts to the ‘forma,’ not the ‘materia.’ “Be
perspicuous” is denotically entailed by “Make your move appropriate.” This is
the desideratum of clarity. The point must be ‘explicit.’ This is Strawson and Wiggins way of putting
this. It’s a difficult issue. What the connection is between Grice’s principle
of conversational helpfulness and the attending conversational maxims. Strawson
and Wiggins state that Grice should not feel the burden to make the maxims
‘necessarily independent.’
The
image of the ramification is a good one – Grice called it ‘arbor griceiana.’
ariskant: Two of Grice’s
main tutees were respectively Aristotelian and Kantian scholars: Ackrill and
Strawson. Grice, of course, read Ariskant in the vernacular. Critique of Pure Reason. Translated by Francis Haywood. William Pickering.
1838. critick of pure reason. (first English
translation) Critique
of Pure Reason. Translated by J. M. D. Meiklejohn. 1855 – via Project Gutenberg.Critique of Pure Reason.
Translated by Thomas Kingsmill Abbott. 1873.Critique of Pure Reason. Translated by Friedrich Max Müller. The Macmillan Company.
1881. (Introduction by Ludwig Noiré)Critique of Pure Reason. Translated by Norman Kemp Smith. Palgrave Macmillan.
1929. ISBN 1-4039-1194-0. Archived from the
original on 2009-04-27.Critique
of Pure Reason. Translated by Wolfgang Schwartz. Scientia Verlag
und Antiquariat. 1982. ISBN 978-3-5110-9260-3.Critique of Pure Reason. Translated by Werner S.
Pluhar. Hackett Publishing. 1996. ISBN 978-0-87220-257-3.Critique of Pure Reason, Abridged. Translated by Werner S.
Pluhar. Hackett Publishing. 1999. ISBN 978-1-6246-6605-6.Critique of Pure Reason.
Translated and edited by Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood. Cambridge University
Press. 1999. ISBN 978-0-5216-5729-7.Critique of Pure Reason.
Translated by Marcus Weigelt. Penguin Books. 2007. ISBN 978-0-1404-4747-7. Grice’s
favourite philosopher is Ariskant. One way to approach Grice’s meta-philosophy
is by combining teleology with deontology. Eventually, Grice embraces a
hedonistic eudaimonism, if rationally approved. Grice knows how to tutor in
philosophy: he tutor on Kant as if he is tutoring on Aristotle, and vice versa.
His tutees would say, Here come [sic] Kantotle. Grice is obsessed with
Kantotle. He would teach one or the other as an ethics requirement. Back at
Oxford, the emphasis is of course Aristotle, but he is aware of some trends to
introduce Kant in the Lit.Hum. curriculum, not with much success. Strawson does
his share with the pure reason in Kant in The bounds of sense, but White
professors of moral philosophy are usually not too keen on the critique by Kant
of practical reason. Grice is fascinated that an Irishman, back in 1873, cares
to translate (“for me”) all that Kant has to say about the eudaimonism and
hedonism of Aristotle. An Oxonian philosopher is expected to be a utilitarian,
as Hare is, or a Hegelian, and that is why Grice prefers, heterodoxical as he
is, to be a Kantian rationalist instead. But Grice cannot help being
Aristotelian, Hardie having instilled the “Eth. Nich.” on him at Corpus. While
he can’t read Kant in German, Grice uses Abbott’s Irish vernacular. Note
the archaic metaphysic sic in singular. More Kant. Since Baker can
read the vernacular even less than Grice, it may be good to review the
editions. It all starts when Abbott thinks that his fellow Irishmen are unable
to tackle Kant in the vernacular. Abbott’s thing comes out in 1873: Kant’s
critique of practical reason and other works on the theory of tthics, with
Grice quipping. Oddly, I prefer his other work! Grice collaborates with Baker
mainly on work on meta-ethics seen as an offspring, alla Kant, of philosophical
psychology. Akrasia or egkrateia is one such topic. Baker contributes to
PGRICE, a festschrift for Grice, with an essay on the purity, and alleged lack
thereof, of this or that morally evaluable motive – rhetorically put: do ones
motives have to be pure? For Grice morality cashes out in self-love,
self-interest, and desire. Baker also contributes to a volume on Grice’s honour
published by Palgrave, Meaning and analysis: essays on Grice. Baker
organises of a symposium on the thought of Grice for the APA, the proceedings
of which published in The Journal of Philosophy, with Bennett as chair, contributions
by Baker and Grandy, commented by Stalnaker andWarner. Grice explores with
Baker problems of egcrateia and the reduction of duty to self-love and
interest. Aristotle: preeminent Grecian
philosopher born in Stagira, hence sometimes called the Stagirite. Aristotle
came to Athens as a teenager and remained for two decades in Plato’s Academy.
Following Plato’s death in 347, Aristotle traveled to Assos and to Lesbos,
where he associated with Theophrastus and collected a wealth of biological
data, and later to Macedonia, where he tutored Alexander the Great. In 335 he
returned to Athens and founded his own philosophical school in the Lyceum. The
site’s colonnaded walk peripatos conferred on Aristotle and his group the name
‘the Peripatetics’. Alexander’s death in 323 unleashed antiMacedonian forces in
Athens. Charged with impiety, and mindful of the fate of Socrates, Aristotle
withdrew to Chalcis, where he died. Chiefly influenced by his association with
Plato, Aristotle also makes wide use of the preSocratics. A number of works
begin by criticizing and, ultimately, building on their views. The direction of
Plato’s influence is debated. Some scholars see Aristotle’s career as a
measured retreat from his teacher’s doctrines. For others he began as a confirmed
anti-Platonist but returned to the fold as he matured. More likely, Aristotle
early on developed a keenly independent voice that expressed enduring
puzzlement over such Platonic doctrines as the separate existence of Ideas and
the construction of physical reality from two-dimensional triangles. Such
unease was no doubt heightened by Aristotle’s appreciation for the evidential
value of observation as well as by his conviction that long-received and
well-entrenched opinion is likely to contain at least part of the truth.
Aristotle reportedly wrote a few popular works for publication, some of which
are dialogues. Of these we have only fragments and reports. Notably lost are
also his lectures on the good and on the Ideas. Ancient cataloguers also list
under Aristotle’s name some 158 constitutions of Grecian states. Of these, only
the Constitution of Athens has survived, on a papyrus discovered in 0. What
remains is an enormous body of writing on virtually every topic of
philosophical significance. Much of it consists of detailed lecture notes,
working drafts, and accounts of his lectures written by others. Although
efforts may have been under way in Aristotle’s lifetime, Andronicus of Rhodes,
in the first century B.C., is credited with giving the Aristotelian corpus its
present organization. Virtually no extant manuscripts predate the ninth century
A.D., so the corpus has been transmitted by a complex history of manuscript
transcription. In 1831 the Berlin Academy published the first critical edition
of Aristotle’s work. Scholars still cite Aristotle by , column, and line of
this edition. Logic and language. The writings on logic and language are
concentrated in six early works: Categories, On Interpretation, Prior
Analytics, Posterior Analytics, Topics, and Sophistical Refutations. Known
since late antiquity as the Organon, these works share a concern with what is
now called semantics. The Categories focuses on the relation between uncombined
terms, such as ‘white’ or ‘man’, and the items they signify; On Interpretation
offers an account of how terms combine to yield simple statements; Prior
Analytics provides a systematic account of how three terms must be distributed
in two categorical statements so as to yield logically a third such statement;
Posterior Analytics specifies the conditions that categorical statements must
meet to play a role in scientific explanation. The Topics, sometimes said to
include Sophistical Refutations, is a handbook of “topics” and techniques for
dialectical arguments concerning, principally, the four predicables: accident
what may or may not belong to a subject, as sitting belongs to Socrates;
definition what signifies a subject’s essence, as rational animal is the
essence of man; proprium what is not in the essence of a subject but is unique
to or counterpredicable of it, as all and only persons are risible; and genus
what is in the essence of subjects differing in species, as animal is in the
essence of both men and oxen. Categories treats the basic kinds of things that
exist and their interrelations. Every uncombined term, says Aristotle,
signifies essentially something in one of ten categories a substance, a quantity, a quality, a
relative, a place, a time, a position, a having, a doing, or a being affected.
This doctrine underlies Aristotle’s admonition that there are as many proper or
per se senses of ‘being’ as there are categories. In order to isolate the
things that exist primarily, namely, primary substances, from all other things
and to give an account of their nature, two asymmetric relations of ontological
dependence are employed. First, substance ousia is distinguished from the
accidental categories by the fact that every accident is present in a substance
and, therefore, cannot exist without a substance in which to inhere. Second,
the category of substance itself is divided into ordinary individuals or
primary substances, such as Socrates, and secondary substances, such as the
species man and the genus animal. Secondary substances are said of primary
substances and indicate what kind of thing the subject is. A mark of this is
that both the name and the definition of the secondary substance can be
predicated of the primary substance, as both man and rational animal can be
predicated of Socrates. Universals in non-substance categories are also said of
subjects, as color is said of white. Therefore, directly or indirectly,
everything else is either present in or said of primary substances and without
them nothing would exist. And because they are neither present in a subject nor
said of a subject, primary substances depend on nothing else for their
existence. So, in the Categories, the ordinary individual is ontologically
basic. On Interpretation offers an account of those meaningful expressions that
are true or false, namely, statements or assertions. Following Plato’s Sophist,
a simple statement is composed of the semantically heterogeneous parts, name
onoma and verb rhema. In ‘Socrates runs’ the name has the strictly referential
function of signifying the subject of attribution. The verb, on the other hand,
is essentially predicative, signifying something holding of the subject. Verbs
also indicate when something is asserted to hold and so make precise the
statement’s truth conditions. Simple statements also include general categorical
statements. Since medieval times it has become customary to refer to the basic
categoricals by letters: A Every man is white, E No man is white, I Some man is
white, and O Not every man is white. On Interpretation outlines their logical
relations in what is now called the square of opposition: A & E are
contraries, A & O and E & I are contradictories, and A & I and E
& O are superimplications. That A implies I reflects the no longer current
view that Aristotle Aristotle 45 45 all
affirmative statements carry existential import. One ambition of On
Interpretation is a theory of the truth conditions for all statements that
affirm or deny one thing or another. However, statements involving future
contingencies pose a special problem. Consider Aristotle’s notorious sea
battle. Either it will or it will not happen tomorrow. If the first, then the
statement ‘There will be a sea battle tomorrow’ is now true. Hence, it is now
fixed that the sea battle occur tomorrow. If the second, then it is now fixed
that the sea battle not occur tomorrow. Either way there can be no future
contingencies. Although some hold that Aristotle would embrace the determinism
they find implicit in this consequence, most argue either that he suspends the
law of excluded middle for future contingencies or that he denies the principle
of bivalence for future contingent statements. On the first option Aristotle
gives up the claim that either the sea battle will happen tomorrow or not. On
the second he keeps the claim but allows that future contingent statements are
neither true nor false. Aristotle’s evident attachment to the law of excluded
middle, perhaps, favors the second option. Prior Analytics marks the invention
of logic as a formal discipline in that the work contains the first virtually
complete system of logical inference, sometimes called syllogistic. The fact
that the first chapter of the Prior Analytics reports that there is a syllogism
whenever, certain things being stated, something else follows of necessity,
might suggest that Aristotle intended to capture a general notion of logical
consequence. However, the syllogisms that constitute the system of the Prior
Analytics are restricted to the basic categorical statements introduced in On
Interpretation. A syllogism consists of three different categorical statements:
two premises and a conclusion. The Prior Analytics tells us which pairs of
categoricals logically yield a third. The fourteen basic valid forms are
divided into three figures and, within each figure, into moods. The system is
foundational because second- and third-figure syllogisms are reducible to
first-figure syllogisms, whose validity is self-evident. Although syllogisms
are conveniently written as conditional sentences, the syllogistic proper is,
perhaps, best seen as a system of valid deductive inferences rather than as a
system of valid conditional sentences or sentence forms. Posterior Analytics
extends syllogistic to science and scientific explanation. A science is a
deductively ordered body of knowledge about a definite genus or domain of
nature. Scientific knowledge episteme consists not in knowing that, e.g., there
is thunder in the clouds, but rather in knowing why there is thunder. So the
theory of scientific knowledge is a theory of explanation and the vehicle of
explanation is the first-figure syllogism Barbara: If 1 P belongs to all M and
2 M belongs to all S, then 3 P belongs to all S. To explain, e.g., why there is
thunder, i.e., why there is noise in the clouds, we say: 3H Noise P belongs to
the clouds S because 2H Quenching of fire M belongs to the clouds S and 1H
Noise P belongs to quenching of fire M. Because what is explained in science is
invariant and holds of necessity, the premises of a scientific or demonstrative
syllogism must be necessary. In requiring that the premises be prior to and
more knowable than the conclusion, Aristotle embraces the view that explanation
is asymmetrical: knowledge of the conclusion depends on knowledge of each
premise, but each premise can be known independently of the conclusion. The
premises must also give the causes of the conclusion. To inquire why P belongs
to S is, in effect, to seek the middle term that gives the cause. Finally, the
premises must be immediate and non-demonstrable. A premise is immediate just in
case there is no middle term connecting its subject and predicate terms. Were P
to belong to M because of a new middle, M1, then there would be a new, more
basic premise, that is essential to the full explanation. Ultimately,
explanation of a received fact will consist in a chain of syllogisms
terminating in primary premises that are immediate. These serve as axioms that
define the science in question because they reflect the essential nature of the
fact to be explained as in 1H the
essence of thunder lies in the quenching of fire. Because they are immediate,
primary premises are not capable of syllogistic demonstration, yet they must be
known if syllogisms containing them are to constitute knowledge of the
conclusion. Moreover, were it necessary to know the primary premises
syllogistically, demonstration would proceed infinitely or in a circle. The
first alternative defeats the very possibility of explanation and the second
undermines its asymmetric character. Thus, the primary premises must be known
by the direct grasp of the mind noûs. This just signals the appropriate way for
the highest principles of a science to be known
even demonstrable propositions can be known directly, but they are
explained only when located within the structure of the relevant science, i.e.,
only when demonstrated syllogistically. Although all sciences exhibit the same
formal structure and use Aristotle Aristotle 46 46 certain common principles, different
sciences have different primary premises and, hence, different subject matters.
This “one genus to one science” rule legislates that each science and its
explanations be autonomous. Aristotle recognizes three kinds of intellectual
discipline. Productive disciplines, such as house building, concern the making
of something external to the agent. Practical disciplines, such as ethics,
concern the doing of something not separate from the agent, namely, action and
choice. Theoretical disciplines are concerned with truth for its own sake. As
such, they alone are sciences in the special sense of the Posterior Analytics.
The three main kinds of special science are individuated by their objects natural science by objects that are separate
but not changeless, mathematics by objects that are changeless but not
separate, and theology by separate and changeless objects. The mathematician
studies the same objects as the natural scientist but in a quite different way.
He takes an actual object, e.g. a chalk figure used in demonstration, and
abstracts from or “thinks away” those of its properties, such as definiteness
of size and imperfection of shape, that are irrelevant to its standing as a
perfect exemplar of the purely mathematical properties under investigation.
Mathematicians simply treat this abstracted circle, which is not separate from
matter, as if it were separate. In this way the theorems they prove about the
object can be taken as universal and necessary. Physics. As the science of
nature physis, physics studies those things whose principles and causes of
change and rest are internal. Aristotle’s central treatise on nature, the
Physics, analyzes the most general features of natural phenomena: cause,
change, time, place, infinity, and continuity. The doctrine of the four causes
is especially important in Aristotle’s work. A cause aitia is something like an
explanatory factor. The material cause of a house, for instance, is the matter
hyle from which it is built; the moving or efficient cause is the builder, more
exactly, the form in the builder’s soul; the formal cause is its plan or form
eidos; and the final cause is its purpose or end telos: provision of shelter.
The complete explanation of the coming to be of a house will factor in all of
these causes. In natural phenomena efficient, formal, and final causes often
coincide. The form transmitted by the father is both the efficient cause and
the form of the child, and the latter is glossed in terms of the child’s end or
complete development. This explains why Aristotle often simply contrasts matter
and form. Although its objects are compounds of both, physics gives priority to
the study of natural form. This accords with the Posterior Analytics’
insistence that explanation proceed through causes that give the essence and
reflects Aristotle’s commitment to teleology. A natural process counts
essentially as the development of, say, an oak or a man because its very
identity depends on the complete form realized at its end. As with all things
natural, the end is an internal governing principle of the process rather than
an external goal. All natural things are subject to change kinesis. Defined as
the actualization of the potential qua potential, a change is not an
ontologically basic item. There is no category for changes. Rather, they are
reductively explained in terms of more basic things substances, properties, and potentialities. A
pale man, e.g., has the potentiality to be or become tanned. If this
potentiality is utterly unactualized, no change will ensue; if completely
actualized, the change will have ended. So the potentiality must be actualized
but not, so to speak, exhausted; i.e., it must be actualized qua potentiality.
Designed for the ongoing operations of the natural world, the Physics’
definition of change does not cover the generation and corruption of
substantial items themselves. This sort of change, which involves matter and
elemental change, receives extensive treatment in On Generation and Corruption.
Aristotle rejects the atomists’ contention that the world consists of an
infinite totality of indivisible atoms in various arrangements. Rather, his
basic stuff is uniform elemental matter, any part of which is divisible into
smaller such parts. Because nothing that is actually infinite can exist, it is
only in principle that matter is always further dividable. So while countenancing
the potential infinite, Aristotle squarely denies the actual infinite. This
holds for the motions of the sublunary elemental bodies earth, air, fire, and
water as well as for the circular motions of the heavenly bodies composed of a
fifth element, aether, whose natural motion is circular. These are discussed in
On the Heavens. The four sublunary elements are further discussed in
Meteorology, the fourth book of which might be described as an early treatise
on chemical combination. Psychology. Because the soul psyche is officially
defined as the form of a body with the potentiality for life, psychology is a
subfield of natural science. In effect, Aristotle applies the Aristotle
Aristotle 47 47 apparatus of form and
matter to the traditional Grecian view of the soul as the principle and cause
of life. Although even the nutritive and reproductive powers of plants are
effects of the soul, most of his attention is focused on topics that are
psychological in the modern sense. On the Soul gives a general account of the
nature and number of the soul’s principal cognitive faculties. Subsequent
works, chiefly those collected as the Parva naturalia, apply the general theory
to a broad range of psychological phenomena from memory and recollection to
dreaming, sleeping, and waking. The soul is a complex of faculties. Faculties,
at least those distinctive of persons, are capacities for cognitively grasping
objects. Sight grasps colors, smell odors, hearing sounds, and the mind grasps
universals. An organism’s form is the particular organization of its material
parts that enable it to exercise these characteristic functions. Because an
infant, e.g., has the capacity to do geometry, Aristotle distinguishes two
varieties of capacity or potentiality dynamis and actuality entelecheia. The
infant is a geometer only in potentiality. This first potentiality comes to him
simply by belonging to the appropriate species, i.e., by coming into the world
endowed with the potential to develop into a competent geometer. By actualizing,
through experience and training, this first potentiality, he acquires a first
actualization. This actualization is also a second potentiality, since it
renders him a competent geometer able to exercise his knowledge at will. The
exercise itself is a second actualization and amounts to active contemplation
of a particular item of knowledge, e.g. the Pythagorean theorem. So the soul is
further defined as the first actualization of a complex natural body.
Faculties, like sciences, are individuated by their objects. Objects of
perception aisthesis fall into three general kinds. Special proper sensibles,
such as colors and sounds, are directly perceived by one and only one sense and
are immune to error. They demarcate the five special senses: sight, hearing, smell,
taste, and touch. Common sensibles, such as movement and shape, are directly
perceived by more than one special sense. Both special and common sensibles are
proper objects of perception because they have a direct causal effect on the
perceptual system. By contrast, the son of Diares is an incidental sensible
because he is perceived not directly but as a consequence of directly
perceiving something else that happens to be the son of Diares e.g., a white thing. Aristotle calls the mind
noûs the place of forms because it is able to grasp objects apart from matter.
These objects are nothing like Plato’s separately existing Forms. As
Aristotelian universals, their existence is entailed by and depends on their
having instances. Thus, On the Soul’s remark that universals are “somehow in
the soul” only reflects their role in assuring the autonomy of thought. The
mind has no organ because it is not the form or first actualization of any
physical structure. So, unlike perceptual faculties, it is not strongly dependent
on the body. However, the mind thinks its objects by way of images, which are
something like internal representations, and these are physically based.
Insofar as it thus depends on imagination phantasia, the mind is weakly
dependent on the body. This would be sufficient to establish the naturalized
nature of Aristotle’s mind were it not for what some consider an incurably
dualist intrusion. In distinguishing something in the mind that makes all
things from something that becomes all things, Aristotle introduces the
notorious distinction between the active and passive intellects and may even
suggest that the first is separable from the body. Opinion on the nature of the
active intellect diverges widely, some even discounting it as an irrelevant
insertion. But unlike perception, which depends on external objects, thinking
is up to us. Therefore, it cannot simply be a matter of the mind’s being
affected. So Aristotle needs a mechanism that enables us to produce thoughts
autonomously. In light of this functional role, the question of active
intellect’s ontological status is less pressing. Biology. Aristotle’s
biological writings, which constitute about a quarter of the corpus, bring
biological phenomena under the general framework of natural science: the four
causes, form and matter, actuality and potentiality, and especially the
teleological character of natural processes. If the Physics proceeds in an a
priori style, the History of Animals, Parts of Animals, and Generation of
Animals achieve an extraordinary synthesis of observation, theory, and general
scientific principle. History of Animals is a comparative study of generic
features of animals, including analogous parts, activities, and dispositions.
Although its morphological and physiological descriptions show surprisingly
little interest in teleology, Parts of Animals is squarely teleological. Animal
parts, especially organs, are ultimately differentiated by function rather than
morphology. The composition of, e.g., teeth and flesh is determined by their
role in the overall functioning of the organism and, hence, requires Aristotle
Aristotle 48 48 teleology. Generation
of Animals applies the formmatter and actualitypotentiality distinctions to
animal reproduction, inheritance, and the development of accidental
characteristics. The species form governs the development of an organism and
determines what the organism is essentially. Although in the Metaphysics and
elsewhere accidental characteristics, including inherited ones, are excluded
from science, in the biological writings form has an expanded role and explains
the inheritance of non-essential characteristics, such as eye color. The more
fully the father’s form is imposed on the minimally formed matter of the
mother, the more completely the father’s traits are passed on to the offspring.
The extent to which matter resists imposition of form determines the extent to
which traits of the mother emerge, or even those of more distant ancestors.
Aristotle shared the Platonists’ interest in animal classification. Recent
scholarship suggests that this is less an interest in elaborating a
Linnean-style taxonomy of the animal kingdom than an interest in establishing
the complex differentiae and genera central to definitions of living things.
The biological works argue, moreover, that no single differentia could give the
whole essence of a species and that the differentiae that do give the essence
will fall into more than one division. If the second point rejects the method
of dichotomous division favored by Plato and the Academy, the first counters
Aristotle’s own standard view that essence can be reduced to a single final
differentia. The biological sciences are not, then, automatically accommodated
by the Posterior Analytics model of explanation, where the essence or
explanatory middle is conceived as a single causal property. A number of themes
discussed in this section are brought together in a relatively late work,
Motion of Animals. Its psychophysical account of the mechanisms of animal
movement stands at the juncture of physics, psychology, and biology.
Metaphysics. In Andronicus’s edition, the fourteen books now known as the
Metaphysics were placed after the Physics, whence comes the word ‘metaphysics’,
whose literal meaning is ‘what comes after the physics’. Aristotle himself
prefers ‘first philosophy’ or ‘wisdom’ sophia. The subject is defined as the
theoretical science of the causes and principles of what is most knowable. This
makes metaphysics a limiting case of Aristotle’s broadly used distinction between
what is better known to us and what is better known by nature. The genus
animal, e.g., is better known by nature than the species man because it is
further removed from the senses and because it can be known independently of
the species. The first condition suggests that the most knowable objects would
be the separately existing and thoroughly non-sensible objects of theology and,
hence, that metaphysics is a special science. The second condition suggests
that the most knowable objects are simply the most general notions that apply
to things in general. This favors identifying metaphysics as the general
science of being qua being. Special sciences study restricted modes of being.
Physics, for instance, studies being qua having an internal principle of change
and rest. A general science of being studies the principles and causes of
things that are, simply insofar as they are. A good deal of the Metaphysics
supports this conception of metaphysics. For example, Book IV, on the principle
of non-contradiction, and Book X, on unity, similarity, and difference, treat
notions that apply to anything whatever. So, too, for the discussion of form
and actuality in the central books VII, VIII, and IX. Book XII, on the other
hand, appears to regard metaphysics as the special science of theology.
Aristotle himself attempts to reconcile these two conceptions of metaphysics.
Because it studies immovable substance, theology counts as first philosophy.
However, it is also general precisely because it is first, and so it will include
the study of being qua being. Scholars have found this solution as perplexing
as the problem. Although Book XII proves the causal necessity for motion of an
eternal substance that is an unmoved mover, this establishes no conceptual
connection between the forms of sensible compounds and the pure form that is
the unmoved mover. Yet such a connection is required, if a single science is to
encompass both. Problems of reconciliation aside, Aristotle had to face a prior
difficulty concerning the very possibility of a general science of being. For
the Posterior Analytics requires the existence of a genus for each science but
the Metaphysics twice argues that being is not a genus. The latter claim, which
Aristotle never relinquishes, is implicit in the Categories, where being falls
directly into kinds, namely, the categories. Because these highest genera do
not result from differentiation of a single genus, no univocal sense of being
covers them. Although being is, therefore, ambiguous in as many ways as there are
categories, a thread connects them. The ontological priority accorded primary
substance in the Categories is made part of the very definition of
non-substantial entities Aristotle Aristotle 49 49 in the Metaphysics: to be an accident is
by definition to be an accident of some substance. Thus, the different senses
of being all refer to the primary kind of being, substance, in the way that
exercise, diet, medicine, and climate are healthy by standing in some relation
to the single thing health. The discovery of focal meaning, as this is
sometimes called, introduces a new way of providing a subject matter with the
internal unity required for science. Accordingly, the Metaphysics modifies the
strict “one genus to one science” rule of the Posterior Analytics. A single
science may also include objects whose definitions are different so long as
these definitions are related focally to one thing. So focal meaning makes
possible the science of being qua being. Focal meaning also makes substance the
central object of investigation. The principles and causes of being in general
can be illuminated by studying the principles and causes of the primary
instance of being. Although the Categories distinguishes primary substances
from other things that are and indicates their salient characteristics e.g.,
their ability to remain one and the same while taking contrary properties, it
does not explain why it is that primary substances have such characteristics.
The difficult central books of the Metaphysics
VII, VIII, and IX investigate
precisely this. In effect, they ask what, primarily, about the Categories’
primary substances explains their nature. Their target, in short, is the
substance of the primary substances of the Categories. As concrete empirical
particulars, the latter are compounds of form and matter the distinction is not
explicit in the Categories and so their substance must be sought among these
internal structural features. Thus, Metaphysics VII considers form, matter, and
the compound of form and matter, and quickly turns to form as the best
candidate. In developing a conception of form that can play the required
explanatory role, the notion of essence to ti en einai assumes center stage.
The essence of a man, e.g., is the cause of certain matter constituting a man,
namely, the soul. So form in the sense of essence is the primary substance of
the Metaphysics. This is obviously not the primary substance of the Categories
and, although the same word eidos is used, neither is this form the species of
the Categories. The latter is treated in the Metaphysics as a kind of universal
compound abstracted from particular compounds and appears to be denied
substantial status. While there is broad, though not universal, agreement that
in the Metaphysics form is primary substance, there is equally broad
disagreement over whether this is particular form, the form belonging to a
single individual, or species form, the form common to all individuals in the
species. There is also lively discussion concerning the relation of the Metaphysics
doctrine of primary substance to the earlier doctrine of the Categories.
Although a few scholars see an outright contradiction here, most take the
divergence as evidence of the development of Aristotle’s views on substance.
Finally, the role of the central books in the Metaphysics as a whole continues
to be debated. Some see them as an entirely selfcontained analysis of form,
others as preparatory to Book XII’s discussion of non-sensible form and the
role of the unmoved mover as the final cause of motion. Practical philosophy.
Two of Aristotle’s most heralded works, the Nicomachean Ethics and the
Politics, are treatises in practical philosophy. Their aim is effective action
in matters of conduct. So they deal with what is up to us and can be otherwise
because in this domain lie choice and action. The practical nature of ethics
lies mainly in the development of a certain kind of agent. The Nicomachean
Ethics was written, Aristotle reminds us, “not in order to know what virtue is,
but in order to become good.” One becomes good by becoming a good chooser and
doer. This is not simply a matter of choosing and doing right actions but of
choosing or doing them in the right way. Aristotle assumes that, for the most
part, agents know what ought to be done the evil or vicious person is an
exception. The akratic or morally weak agent desires to do other than what he
knows ought to be done and acts on this desire against his better judgment. The
enkratic or morally strong person shares the akratic agent’s desire but acts in
accordance with his better judgment. In neither kind of choice are desire and
judgment in harmony. In the virtuous, on the other hand, desire and judgment
agree. So their choices and actions will be free of the conflict and pain that
inevitably accompany those of the akratic and enkratic agent. This is because
the part of their soul that governs choice and action is so disposed that
desire and right judgment coincide. Acquiring a stable disposition hexis of
this sort amounts to acquiring moral virtue ethike arete. The disposition is
concerned with choices as would be determined by the person of practical wisdom
phronesis; these will be actions lying between extreme alternatives. They will
lie in a mean popularly called the
“golden mean” relative to the talents
and stores of the agent. Choosing in this way is not easily done. It involves,
for instance, feeling anger or extending Aristotle Aristotle 50 50 generosity at the right time, toward the
right people, in the right way, and for the right reasons. Intellectual
virtues, such as excellence at mathematics, can be acquired by teaching, but
moral virtue cannot. I may know what ought to be done and even perform virtuous
acts without being able to act virtuously. Nonetheless, because moral virtue is
a disposition concerning choice, deliberate performance of virtuous acts can,
ultimately, instill a disposition to choose them in harmony and with pleasure
and, hence, to act virtuously. Aristotle rejected Plato’s transcendental Form
of the Good as irrelevant to the affairs of persons and, in general, had little
sympathy with the notion of an absolute good. The goal of choice and action is
the human good, namely, living well. This, however, is not simply a matter of
possessing the requisite practical disposition. Practical wisdom, which is
necessary for living well, involves skill at calculating the best means to
achieve one’s ends and this is an intellectual virtue. But the ends that are
presupposed by deliberation are established by moral virtue. The end of all
action, the good for man, is happiness eudaimonia. Most things, such as wealth,
are valued only as a means to a worthy end. Honor, pleasure, reason, and
individual virtues, such as courage and generosity, are deemed worthy in their
own right but they can also be sought for the sake of eudaimonia. Eudaimonia
alone can be sought only for its own sake. Eudaimonia is not a static state of
the soul but a kind of activity energeia of the soul something like human flourishing. The happy
person’s life will be selfsufficient and complete in the highest measure. The
good for man, then, is activity in accordance with virtue or the highest
virtue, should there be one. Here ‘virtue’ means something like excellence and
applies to much besides man. The excellence of an ax lies in its cutting, that
of a horse in its equestrian qualities. In short, a thing’s excellence is a
matter of how well it performs its characteristic functions or, we might say,
how well it realizes its nature. The natural functions of persons reside in the
exercise of their natural cognitive faculties, most importantly, the faculty of
reason. So human happiness consists in activity in accordance with reason.
However, persons can exercise reason in practical or in purely theoretical
matters. The first suggests that happiness consists in the practical life of
moral virtue, the second that it consists in the life of theoretical activity.
Most of the Nicomachean Ethics is devoted to the moral virtues but the final
book appears to favor theoretical activity theoria as the highest and most
choiceworthy end. It is man’s closest approach to divine activity. Much recent
scholarship is devoted to the relation between these two conceptions of the
good, particularly, to whether they are of equal value and whether they exclude
or include one another. Ethics and politics are closely connected. Aristotle
conceives of the state as a natural entity arising among persons to serve a
natural function. This is not merely, e.g., provision for the common defense or
promotion of trade. Rather, the state of the Politics also has eudaimonia as
its goal, namely, fostering the complete and selfsufficient lives of its
citizens. Aristotle produced a complex taxonomy of constitutions but reduced
them, in effect, to three kinds: monarchy, aristocracy, and democracy. Which
best serves the natural end of a state was, to some extent, a relative matter
for Aristotle. Although he appears to have favored democracy, in some
circumstances monarchy might be appropriate. The standard ordering of
Aristotle’s works ends with the Rhetoric and the Poetics. The Rhetoric’s
extensive discussion of oratory or the art of persuasion locates it between
politics and literary theory. The relatively short Poetics is devoted chiefly
to the analysis of tragedy. It has had an enormous historical influence on
aesthetic theory in general as well as on the writing of drama. Refs.: The obvious keyword is “Kant,” –
especially in the Series III on the doctrines, in collaboration with Baker.
There are essays on the Grundlegung, too. The keyword for “Kantotle,” and the
keywords for ‘free,’ and ‘freedom,’ and ‘practical reason,’ and ‘autonomy, are
also helpful. Some of this material in “Actions and events,” “The influence of
Kant on Aristotle,” by H. P. Grice, John Locke Scholar (failed), etc., Oxford
(Advisor: J. Dempsey). The H. P. Grice Papers, BANC. Grice’s composite for Kant
and Aristotle -- Grice as an Aristotelian commentator – in “Aristotle on the
multiplicity of being,” – Grice would comment on Aristotle profusely at Oxford.
One of his favourite tutees was J. L. Ackrill – but he regretted that, of all
things Ackrill could do, he decided “to translate Aristotle into the
vernacular!” -- commentaries on Aristotle, the term commonly used for the
Grecian commentaries on Aristotle that take up about 15,000 s in the Berlin
Commentaria in Aristotelem Graeca 29, still the basic edition of them. Only in
the 0s did a project begin, under the editorship of Richard Sorabji, of King’s
, London, to translate at least the most significant portions of them into
English. They had remained the largest corpus of Grecian philosophy not tr.
into any modern language. Most of these works, especially the later,
Neoplatonic ones, are much more than simple commentaries on Aristotle. They are
also a mode of doing philosophy, the favored one at this stage of intellectual
history. They are therefore important not only for the understanding of
Aristotle, but also for both the study of the pre-Socratics and the Hellenistic
philosophers, particularly the Stoics, of whom they preserve many fragments,
and lastly for the study of Neoplatonism itself
and, in the case of John Philoponus, for studying the innovations he
introduces in the process of trying to reconcile Platonism with Christianity.
The commentaries may be divided into three main groups. 1 The first group of
commentaries are those by Peripatetic scholars of the second to fourth
centuries A.D., most notably Alexander of Aphrodisias fl. c.200, but also the
paraphraser Themistius fl. c.360. We must not omit, however, to note
Alexander’s predecessor Aspasius, author of the earliest surviving commentary,
one on the Nicomachean Ethics a work not
commented on again until the late Byzantine period. Commentaries by Alexander
survive on the Prior Analytics, Topics, Metaphysics IV, On the Senses, and
Meteorologics, and his now lost ones on the Categories, On the Soul, and
Physics had enormous influence in later times, particularly on Simplicius. 2 By
far the largest group is that of the Neoplatonists up to the sixth century A.D.
Most important of the earlier commentators is Porphyry 232c.309, of whom only a
short commentary on the Categories survives, together with an introduction
Isagoge to Aristotle’s logical works, which provoked many commentaries itself,
and proved most influential in both the East and through Boethius in the Latin
West. The reconciling of Plato and Aristotle is largely his work. His big
commentary on the Categories was of great importance in later times, and many
fragments are preserved in that of Simplicius. His follower Iamblichus was also
influential, but his commentaries are likewise lost. The Athenian School of
Syrianus c.375437 and Proclus 41085 also commented on Aristotle, but all that
survives is a commentary of Syrianus on Books III, IV, XIII, and XIV of the
Metaphysics. It is the early sixth century, however, that produces the bulk of
our surviving commentaries, originating from the Alexandrian school of
Ammonius, son of Hermeias c.435520, but composed both in Alexandria, by the
Christian John Philoponus c.490575, and in or at least from Athens by
Simplicius writing after 532. Main commentaries of Philoponus are on
Categories, Prior Analytics, Posterior Analytics, On Generation and Corruption,
On the Soul III, and Physics; of Simplicius on Categories, Physics, On the
Heavens, and perhaps On the Soul. The tradition is carried on in Alexandria by
Olympiodorus c.495565 and the Christians Elias fl. c.540 and David an Armenian,
nicknamed the Invincible, fl. c.575, and finally by Stephanus, who was brought
by the emperor to take the chair of philosophy in Constantinople in about 610.
These scholars comment chiefly on the Categories and other introductory
material, but Olympiodorus produced a commentary on the Meteorologics. Characteristic
of the Neoplatonists is a desire to reconcile Aristotle with Platonism arguing,
e.g., that Aristotle was not dismissing the Platonic theory of Forms, and to
systematize his thought, thus reconciling him with himself. They are responding
to a long tradition of criticism, during which difficulties were raised about
incoherences and contradictions in Aristotle’s thought, and they are concerned
to solve these, drawing on their comprehensive knowledge of his writings. Only
Philoponus, as a Christian, dares to criticize him, in particular on the
eternity of the world, but also on the concept of infinity on which he produces
an ingenious argument, picked up, via the Arabs, by Bonaventure in the
thirteenth century. The Categories proves a particularly fruitful battleground,
and much of the later debate between realism and nominalism stems from
arguments about the proper subject matter of that work. The format of these
commentaries is mostly that adopted by scholars ever since, that of taking
command theory of law commentaries on Aristotle 159 159 one passage, or lemma, after another of
the source work and discussing it from every angle, but there are variations.
Sometimes the general subject matter is discussed first, and then details of
the text are examined; alternatively, the lemma is taken in subdivisions
without any such distinction. The commentary can also proceed explicitly by
answering problems, or aporiai, which have been raised by previous authorities.
Some commentaries, such as the short one of Porphyry on the Categories, and
that of Iamblichus’s pupil Dexippus on the same work, have a “catechetical”
form, proceeding by question and answer. In some cases as with Vitters in
modern times the commentaries are simply transcriptions by pupils of the lectures
of a teacher. This is the case, for example, with the surviving “commentaries”
of Ammonius. One may also indulge in simple paraphrase, as does Themistius on
Posterior Analysis, Physics, On the Soul, and On the Heavens, but even here a
good deal of interpretation is involved, and his works remain interesting. An
important offshoot of all this activity in the Latin West is the figure of
Boethius c.480524. It is he who first transmitted a knowledge of Aristotelian
logic to the West, to become an integral part of medieval Scholasticism. He tr.
Porphyry’s Isagoge, and the whole of Aristotle’s logical works. He wrote a
double commentary on the Isagoge, and commentaries on the Categories and On
Interpretation. He is dependent ultimately on Porphyry, but more immediately,
it would seem, on a source in the school of Proclus. 3 The third major group of
commentaries dates from the late Byzantine period, and seems mainly to emanate
from a circle of scholars grouped around the princess Anna Comnena in the
twelfth century. The most important figures here are Eustratius c.10501120 and
Michael of Ephesus originally dated c.1040, but now fixed at c.1130. Michael in
particular seems concerned to comment on areas of Aristotle’s works that had
hitherto escaped commentary. He therefore comments widely, for example, on the
biological works, but also on the Sophistical Refutations. He and Eustratius,
and perhaps others, seem to have cooperated also on a composite commentary on
the Nicomachean Ethics, neglected since Aspasius. There is also evidence of
lost commentaries on the Politics and the Rhetoric. The composite commentary on
the Ethics was tr. into Latin in the next century, in England, by Robert
Grosseteste, but earlier than this translations of the various logical commentaries
had been made by James of Venice fl. c.1130, who may have even made the
acquaintance of Michael of Ephesus in Constantinople. Later in that century
other commentaries were being tr. from Arabic versions by Gerard of Cremona
d.1187. The influence of the Grecian commentary tradition in the West thus
resumed after the long break since Boethius in the sixth century, but only now,
it seems fair to say, is the full significance of this enormous body of work
becoming properly appreciated.
aristotelian society: London – founded,
as it should, in London, by an amateur -- Grice and the Aristotelian Society –
his “Causal Theory of perception” was an invited contribution, a
‘popularisation’ for this Society, which was founded in London back in the day.
The Aristotelian Society’s first president was S. H. Hodgson, of Christ Church,
Oxford. He was succeeded by Bernard Bosanquet.
armstrong: Grice:
“pre-colonial philosopher, from the colonies.” -- d. m. “Meaning and
communication,” on H. P. Grice -- philosopher of mind and metaphysician, and
until his retirement Challis Professor of Philosophy at Sydney, noted for his
allegiance to a physicalist account of consciousness and to a realist view of
properties conceived as universals. A Materialist Theory of the Mind 8 develops
a scientifically motivated version of the view that mental states are identical
with physical states of the central nervous system. Universals and Scientific
Realism 8 and What Is a Law of Nature? argue that a scientifically adequate
ontology must include universals in order to explain the status of natural
laws. Armstrong contends that laws must be construed as expressing relations of
necessitation between universals rather than mere regularities among
particulars. However, he is only prepared to acknowledge the existence of such
universals as are required for the purposes of scientific explanation.
Moreover, he adopts an “immanent” or “Aristotelian” as opposed to a
“transcendent” or “Platonic” realism, refusing to accept the existence of
uninstantiated universals and denying that universals somehow exist “outside”
space and time. More recently, Armstrong has integrated his scientifically
inspired physicalism and property realism within the overall framework of an
ontology of states of affairs, notably in A World of States of Affairs. Here he
advocates the truthmaker principle that every truth must be made true by some
existing state of affairs and contends that states of affairs, rather than the
universals and particulars that he regards as their constituents, are the basic
building blocks of reality. Within this ontology, which in some ways resembles
that of Vitters’s Tractatus, necessity and possibility are accommodated by
appeal to combinatorial principles. As Armstrong explains in A Combinatorial
Theory of Possibility, this approach offers an ontologically economical
alternative to the realist conception of possible worlds defended by David
Lewis.
arnauld: “Have you ever
been to Port Royale? I haven’t!” – Grice. Grice enjoyed the “Logique de Port-Royal.”
Antoine: philosopher, perhaps the most important and best-known intellectual
associated with the Jansenist community at Port-Royal, as well as a staunch and
orthodox champion of Cartesian philosophy. His theological writings defend the
Augustinian doctrine of efficacious grace, according to which salvation is not
earned by one’s own acts, but granted by the irresistible grace of God. He also
argues in favor of a strict contritionism, whereby one’s absolution must be
based on a true, heartfelt repentance, a love of God, rather than a selfish
fear of God’s punishment. These views brought him and Port-Royal to the center
of religious controversy in seventeenth-century France, as Jansenism came to be
perceived as a subversive extension of Protestant reform. Arnauld was also
constantly engaged in philosophical disputation, and was regarded as one of the
sharpest and most philosophically acute thinkers of his time. His influence on
several major philosophers of the period resulted mainly from his penetrating
criticism of their systems. In 1641, Arnauld was asked to comment on
Descartes’s Meditations. The objections he sent
regarding, among other topics, the representational nature of ideas, the
circularity of Descartes’s proofs for the existence of God, and the apparent
irreconcilability of Descartes’s conception of material substance with the
Catholic doctrine of Eucharistic transubstantiation were considered by Descartes to be the most
intelligent and serious of all. Arnauld offered his objections in a
constructive spirit, and soon became an enthusiastic defender of Descartes’s
philosophy, regarding it as beneficial both to the advancement of human
learning and to Christian piety. He insists, for example, that the immortality
of the soul is well grounded in Cartesian mind body dualism. In 1662, Arnauld
composed with Pierre Nicole the Port-Royal Logic, an influential treatise on
language and reasoning. After several decades of theological polemic, during
which he fled France to the Netherlands, Arnauld resumed his public
philosophical activities with the publication in 1683 of On True and False
Ideas and in 1685 of Philosophical and Theological Reflections on the New
System of Nature and Grace. These two works, opening salvos in what would
become a long debate, constitute a detailed attack on Malebranche’s theology
and its philosophical foundations. In the first, mainly philosophical treatise,
Arnauld insists that ideas, or the mental representations that mediate human
knowledge, are nothing but acts of the mind that put us in direct cognitive and
perceptual contact with things in the world. Malebranche, as Arnauld reads him,
argues that ideas are immaterial but nonmental objects in God’s understanding
that we know and perceive instead of physical things. Thus, the debate is often
characterized as between Arnauld’s direct realism and Malebranche’s
representative theory. Such mental acts also have representational content, or
what Arnauld following Descartes calls “objective reality.” This content
explains the act’s intentionality, or directedness toward an object. Arnauld
would later argue with Pierre Bayle, who came to Malebranche’s defense, over
whether all mental phenomena have intentionality, as Arnauld believes, or, as
Bayle asserts, certain events in the soul e.g., pleasures and pains are
non-intentional. This initial critique of Malebranche’s epistemology and
philosophy of mind, however, was intended by Arnauld only as a prolegomenon to
the more important attack on his theology; in particular, on Malebranche’s
claim that God always acts by general volitions and never by particular
volitions. This view, Arnauld argues, undermines the true Catholic system of
divine providence and threatens the efficacy of God’s will by removing God from
direct governance of the world. In 1686, Arnauld also entered into discussions
with Leibniz regarding the latter’s Discourse on Metaphysics. In the ensuing
correspondence, Arnauld focuses his critique on Leibniz’s concept of substance
and on his causal theory, the preestablished harmony. In this exchange, like
the one with Malebranche, Arnauld is concerned to preserve what he takes to be
the proper way to conceive of God’s freedom and providence; although his
remarks on substance in which he objects to Leibniz’s reintroduction of
“substantial forms” is also clearly motivated by his commitment to a strict
Cartesian ontology bodies are nothing
more than extension, devoid of any spiritual element. Most of his philosophical
activity in the latter half of the century, in fact, is a vigorous defense of
Cartesianism, particularly on theological grounds e.g., demonstrating the
consistency between Cartesian metaphysics and the Catholic dogma of real
presence in the Eucharist, as it became the object of condemnation in both
Catholic and Protestant circles.
atomism: the theory,
originated by Leucippus and elaborated by Democritus, that the ultimate
realities are atoms and the void. The theory was later used by Epicurus as the
foundation for a philosophy stressing ethical concerns, Epicureanism.
arrow’s paradox – discussed by
Grice in “Conversational reason.” Also called Arrow’s impossibility theorem, a
major result in social choice theory, named for its discoverer, economist
Kenneth Arrow. It is intuitive to suppose that the preferences of individuals
in a society can be expressed formally, and then aggregated into an expression
of social preferences, a social choice function. Arrow’s paradox is that
individual preferences having certain well-behaved formalizations demonstrably
cannot be aggregated into a similarly well-behaved social choice function
satisfying four plausible formal conditions: 1 collective rationality any set of individual orderings and
alternatives must yield a social ordering; 2 Pareto optimality if all individuals prefer one ordering to
another, the social ordering must also agree; 3 non-dictatorship the social ordering must not be identical to
a particular individual’s ordering; and 4 independence of irrelevant
alternatives the social ordering depends
on no properties of the individual orderings other than the orders themselves,
and for a given set of alternatives it depends only on the orderings of those
particular alternatives. Most attempts to resolve the paradox have focused on
aspects of 1 and 4. Some argue that preferences can be rational even if they
are intransitive. Others argue that cardinal orderings, and hence,
interpersonal comparisons of preference intensity, are relevant.
ascriptum: ascriptivism, the
theory that to call an action voluntary is not to describe it as caused in a
certain way by the agent who did it, but to express a commitment to hold the
agent responsible for the action. Ascriptivism is thus a kind of noncognitivism
as applied to judgments about the voluntariness of acts. Introduced by Hart in
“Ascription of Rights and Responsibilities,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Society 9, ascriptivism was given its name and attacked in Geach’s
“Ascriptivism,” Philosophical Review 0. Hart recanted in the Preface to his Punishment
and Responsibility.
associatum -- associationism:
discussed by Grice as an example of a propositional complexum -- the
psychological doctrine that association is the sole or primary basis of
learning as well as of intelligent thought and behavior. Association occurs
when one type of thought, idea, or behavior follows, or is contingent upon,
another thought, idea, or behavior or external event, and the second somehow
bonds with the first. If the idea of eggs is paired with the idea of ham, then
the two ideas may become associated. Associationists argue that complex states
of mind and mental processes can be analyzed into associated elements. The
complex may be novel, but the elements are products of past associations.
Associationism often is combined with hedonism. Hedonism explains why events
associate or bond: bonds are forged by pleasant experiences. If the
pleasantness of eating eggs is combined with the pleasantness of eating ham,
then ideas of ham and eggs associate. Bonding may also be explained by various
non-hedonistic principles of association, as in Hume’s theory of the
association of ideas. One of these principles is contiguity in place or time.
Associationism contributes to the componential analysis of intelligent,
rational activity into non-intelligent, non-rational, mechanical processes.
People believe as they do, not because of rational connections among beliefs,
but because beliefs associatively bond. Thus one may think of London when
thinking of England, not because one possesses an inner logic of geographic beliefs
from which one infers that London is in England. The two thoughts may co-occur
because of contiguity or other principles. Kinds of associationism occur in
behaviorist models of classical and operant conditioning. Certain
associationist ideas, if not associationism itself, appear in connectionist
models of cognition, especially the principle that contiguities breed bonding.
Several philosophers and psychologists, including Hume, Hartley, and J. S. Mill
among philosophers and E. L. Thorndike 18749 and B. F. Skinner 490 among
psychologists, are associationists.
attenuatum – attenuated cases
of communication -- Borderline – case -- degenerate case, an expression used
more or less loosely to indicate an individual or class that falls outside of a
given background class to which it is otherwise very closely related, often in
virtue of an ordering of a more comprehensive class. A degenerate case of one
class is often a limiting case of a more comprehensive class. Rest zero
velocity is a degenerate case of motion positive velocity while being a
limiting case of velocity. The circle is a degenerate case of an equilateral
and equiangular polygon. In technical or scientific contexts, the conventional
term for the background class is often “stretched” to cover otherwise
degenerate cases. A figure composed of two intersecting lines is a degenerate
case of hyperbola in the sense of synthetic geometry, but it is a limiting case
of hyperbola in the sense of analytic geometry. The null set is a degenerate
case of set in an older sense but a limiting case of set in a modern sense. A
line segment is a degenerate case of rectangle when rectangles are ordered by
ratio of length to width, but it is not a limiting case under these conditions.
attributum: attribution theory,
a theory in social psychology concerned with how and why ordinary people
explain events. People explain by attributing causal powers to certain events
rather than others. The theory attempts to describe and clarify everyday
commonsense explanation, to identify criteria of explanatory success
presupposed by common sense, and to compare and contrast commonsense
explanation with scientific explanation. The heart of attribution theory is the
thesis that people tend to attribute causal power to factors personally
important to them, which they believe covary with alleged effects. For example,
a woman may designate sexual discrimination as the cause of her not being
promoted in a corporation. Being female is important to her and she believes
that promotion and failure covary with gender. Males get promoted; females
don’t. Causal attributions tend to preserve self-esteem, reduce cognitive
dissonance, and diminish the attributor’s personal responsibility for misdeeds.
When attributional styles or habits contribute to emotional ill-being, e.g. to
chronic, inappropriate feelings of depression or guilt, attribution theory
offers the following therapeutic recommendation: change attributions so as to
reduce emotional ill-being and increase well-being. Hence if the woman blames
herself for the failure, and if self-blame is part of her depressive
attributional style, she would be encouraged to look outside herself, perhaps
to sexual discrimination, for the explanation.
augustinus -- ugustinian
semiotics -- Augustine, Saint, known as Augustine of Hippo 354430, Christian
philosopher and church father, one of the chief sources of Christian thought in
the West; his importance for medieval and modern European philosophy is
impossible to describe briefly or ever to circumscribe. Matters are made more
difficult because Augustine wrote voluminously and dialectically as a Christian
theologian, treating philosophical topics for the most part only as they were
helpful to theology or as corrected by
it. Augustine fashioned the narrative of the Confessions 397400 out of the
events of the first half of his life. He thus supplied later biographers with
both a seductive selection of biographical detail and a compelling story of his
successive conversions from adolescent sensuality, to the image-laden religion
of the Manichaeans, to a version of Neoplatonism, and then to Christianity. The
story is an unexcelled introduction to Augustine’s views of philosophy. It
shows, for instance, that Augustine received very little formal education in philosophy.
He was trained as a rhetorician, and the only philosophical work that he
mentions among his early reading is Cicero’s lost Hortensius, an exercise in
persuasion to the study of philosophy. Again, the narrative makes plain that
Augustine finally rejected Manichaeanism because he came to see it as bad
philosophy: a set of sophistical fantasies without rational coherence or
explanatory force. More importantly, Augustine’s final conversion to
Christianity was prepared by his reading in “certain books of the Platonists”
Confessions 7.9.13. These Latin translations, which seem to have been
anthologies or manuals of philosophic teaching, taught Augustine a form of
Neoplatonism that enabled him to conceive of a cosmic hierarchy descending from
an immaterial, eternal, and intelligible God. On Augustine’s judgment,
philosophy could do no more than that; it could not give him the power to order
his own life so as to live happily and in a stable relation with the
now-discovered God. Yet in his first years as a Christian, Augustine took time
to write a number of works in philosophical genres. Best known among them are a
refutation of Academic Skepticism Contra academicos, 386, a theodicy De ordine,
386, and a dialogue on the place of human choice within the providentially
ordered hierarchy created by God De libero arbitrio, 388/39. Within the decade
of his conversion, Augustine was drafted into the priesthood 391 and then
consecrated bishop 395. The thirty-five years of his life after that
consecration were consumed by labors on behalf of the church in northern Africa
and through the Latin-speaking portions of the increasingly fragmented empire.
Most of Augustine’s episcopal writing was polemical both in origin and in form;
he composed against authors or movements he judged heretical, especially the
Donatists and Pelagians. But Augustine’s sense of his authorship also led him
to write works of fundamental theology conceived on a grand scale. The most
famous of these works, beyond the Confessions, are On the Trinity 399412, 420,
On Genesis according to the Letter 40115, and On the City of God 41326. On the
Trinity elaborates in subtle detail the distinguishable “traces” of Father,
Son, and Spirit in the created world and particularly in the human soul’s triad
of memory, intellect, and will. The commentary on Genesis 13, which is meant to
be much more than a “literal” commentary in the modern sense, treats many
topics in philosophical psychology and anthropology. It also teaches such
cosmological doctrines as the “seed-reasons” rationes seminales by which
creatures are given intelligible form. The City of God begins with a critique
of the bankruptcy of pagan civic religion and its attendant philosophies, but
it ends with the depiction of human history as a combat between forces of
self-love, conceived as a diabolic city of earth, and the graced love of God,
which founds that heavenly city within which alone peace is possible.
attributive pluralism Augustine 60 60 A
number of other, discrete doctrines have been attached to Augustine, usually
without the dialectical nuances he would have considered indispensable. One
such doctrine concerns divine “illumination” of the human intellect, i.e., some
active intervention by God in ordinary processes of human understanding. Another
doctrine typically attributed to Augustine is the inability of the human will
to do morally good actions without grace. A more authentically Augustinian
teaching is that introspection or inwardness is the way of discovering the
created hierarchies by which to ascend to God. Another authentic teaching would
be that time, which is a distension of the divine “now,” serves as the medium
or narrative structure for the creation’s return to God. But no list of
doctrines or positions, however authentic or inauthentic, can serve as a
faithful representation of Augustine’s thought, which gives itself only through
the carefully wrought rhetorical forms of his texts.
austinian: J.: discussed by
Grice in his explorations on moral versus legal right. English legal philosopher
known especially for his command theory of law. His career as a lawyer was
unsuccessful but his reputation as a scholar was such that on the founding
of , London, he was offered the chair of
jurisprudence. In 1832 he published the first ten of his lectures, compressed
into six as The Province of Jurisprudence Determined. Although he published a
few papers, and his somewhat fragmentary Lectures on Jurisprudence 1863 was
published posthumously, it is on the Province that his reputation rests. He and
Bentham his friend, London neighbor, and fellow utilitarian were the foremost
English legal philosophers of their time, and their influence on the course of
legal philosophy endures. Austin held that the first task of legal philosophy,
one to which he bends most of his energy, is to make clear what laws are, and
if possible to explain why they are what they are: their rationale. Until those
matters are clear, legislative proposals and legal arguments can never be
clear, since irrelevant considerations will inevitably creep in. The proper
place for moral or theological considerations is in discussion of what the
positive law ought to be, not of what it is. Theological considerations reduce
to moral ones, since God can be assumed to be a good utilitarian. It is
positive laws, “that is to say the laws which are simply and strictly so
called, . . . which form the appropriate matter of general and particular
jurisprudence.” They must also be distinguished from “laws metaphorical or
figurative.” A law in its most general senseis “a rule laid down for the
guidance of an intelligent being by an intelligent being having power over
him.” It is a command, however phrased. It is the commands of men to men, of
political superiors, that form the body of positive law. General or comparative
jurisprudence, the source of the rationale, if any, of particular laws, is
possible because there are commands nearly universal that may be attributed to
God or Nature, but they become positive law only when laid down by a ruler. The
general model of an Austinian analytic jurisprudence built upon a framework of
definitions has been widely followed, but cogent objections, especially by
Hart, have undermined the command theory of law.
austin: Grice: “Never to be confused with David Austin,
of rosarian infame!” -- Grice referred to him as “Austin the younger,” in
opposition to “Austin the elder” – (Austin never enjoyed the joke). j. l. H. P.
Grice, “The Austinian Code.” English philosopher, a leading exponent of postwar
“linguistic” philosophy. Educated primarily as a classicist at Shrewsbury and
Balliol , Oxford, he taught philosophy at Magdalen . During World War II he
served at a high level in military intelligence, which earned him the O.B.E.,
Croix de Guerre, and Legion of Merit. In 2 he became White’s Professor of Moral
Philosophy at Oxford, and in 5 and 8 he held visiting appointments at Harvard
and Berkeley, respectively. In his relatively brief career, Austin published
only a few invited papers; his influence was exerted mainly through discussion
with his colleagues, whom he dominated more by critical intelligence than by
any preconceived view of what philosophy should be. Unlike some others, Austin
did not believe that philosophical problems all arise out of aberrations from
“ordinary language,” nor did he necessarily find solutions there; he dwelt,
rather, on the authority of the vernacular as a source of nice and pregnant
distinctions, and held that it deserves much closer attention than it commonly
receives from philosophers. It is useless, he thought, to pontificate at large
about knowledge, reality, or existence, for example, without first examining in
detail how, and when, the words ‘know’, ‘real’, and ‘exist’ are employed in
daily life. In Sense and Sensibilia 2; compiled from lecture notes, the
sense-datum theory comes under withering fire for its failings in this respect.
Austin also provoked controversy with his well-known distinction between
“performative” and “constative” utterances ‘I promise’ makes a promise, whereas
‘he promised’ merely reports one; he later recast this as a threefold
differentiation of locutionary, illocutionary, and perlocutionary “forces” in
utterance, corresponding roughly to the meaning, intention, and consequences of
saying a thing, in one context or another. Though never very stable or fully
worked out, these ideas have since found a place in the still-evolving study of
speech acts.
austinian code, The: The jocular
way by Grice to refer to ‘The Master,’ whom he saw wobble on more than one
occasion. Grice has mixed feelings (“or fixed meelings, if you prefer”) about
Austin. Unlike Austin, Grice is a Midlands scholarship boy, and ends up in
Corpus. One outcome of this, as he later reminisced is that Austin never cared
to invite him to the Thursday-evenings at All Souls – “which was alright, I
suppose, in that the number was appropriately restricted to seven.” But Grice
confessed that he thought it was because “he had been born on the wrong side of
the tracks.” After the war, Grice would join what Grice, in fun, called “the
Playgroup,” which was anything BUT. Austin played the School Master, and let
the kindergarten relax in the sun! One reason Grice avoided publication was the
idea that Austin would criticise him. Austin never cared to recognise Grice’s
“Personal Identity,” or less so, “Meaning.” He never mentioned his
“Metaphysics” third programme lecture – but Austin never made it to the
programme. Grice socialized very well with who will be Austin’s custodians, in
alphabetical order, Urmson and Warnock – “two charmers.” Unlike Austin, Urmson
and Warnock were the type of person Austin would philosophise with – and he
would spend hours talking about visa with Warnock. Upon Austin’s demise, Grice
kept with the ‘play group’, which really became one! Grice makes immense
references to Austin. Austin fits Grice to a T, because of the ‘mistakes’ he
engages in. So, it is fair to say that Grice’s motivation for the coinage of implicaturum
was Austin (“He would too often ignore the distinction between what a ‘communicator’
communicates and what his expression, if anything, does.”). So Grice attempts
an intention-based account of the communicator’s message. Within this message,
there is ONE aspect that can usually be regarded as being of ‘philosophical
interest.’ The ‘unnecessary implicaturum’ is bound to be taken Austin as part
of the ‘philosophical interesting’ bit when it isn’t. So Grice is criticizing
Austin for providing the wrong analysis for the wrong analysandum. Grice refers
specifically to the essays in “Philosophical Papers,” notably “Other Minds” and
“A Plea for Excuses.” But he makes a passing reference to “Sense and
Sensibilia,” whose tone Grice dislikes, and makes a borrowing or two from the
‘illocution,’ never calling it by that name. At most, Grice would adapt
Austin’s use of ‘act.’ But his rephrase is ‘conversational move.’ So Grice
would say that by making a conversational ‘move,’ the conversationalist may be
communicating TWO things. He spent some type finding a way to conceptualise
this. He later came with the metaphor of the FIRST-FLOOR act, the MEZZANINE
act, and the SECOND-FLOOR act. This applies to Fregeianisms like ‘aber,’ but it
may well apply to Austinian-code type of utterances.
austinianism: Grice felt sorry
for Nowell-Smith, whom he calls the ‘straight-man’ for the comedy double act
with Austin at the Play Groups. “I would say ‘on principle’” – “I would say,
‘no, thanks.” “I don’t understand Donne.” “It’s perfectly clear to me.” By
using Nowell-Sith, Grice is implicating that Austin had little manners in the
‘play group,’ “And I wasn’t surprised when Nowell-Smith left Oxford for good,
almost.” Not quite, of course. After some time in the extremely fashionable
Canterbury, Nowell-Smith returns to Oxford. Vide: nowell-smithianism.
autarkia: Grecian for
‘self-sufficiency,’ from ‘auto-‘, self, and ‘arkhe,’ principium. Autarkia was
widely regarded as a mark of the human good, happiness eudaimonia. A life is
self-sufficient when it is worthy of choice and lacks nothing. What makes a
life self-sufficient and thereby
happy was a matter of controversy.
Stoics maintained that the mere possession of virtue would suffice; Aristotle
and the Peripatetics insisted that virtue must be exercised and even, perhaps,
accompanied by material goods. There was also a debate among later Grecian
thinkers over whether a self-sufficient life is solitary or whether only life
in a community can be self-sufficient.
avenarius, R. philosopher:
an influence on Ayer, who thinks he is following British empiricism! Avenarius
was born in Paris and educated at the of
Leipzig. He became a professor at Leipzig and succeeded Windelband at the of Zürich in 1877. For a time he was editor
of the Zeitschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie. His earliest work was
Über die beiden ersten Phasen des Spinozischen Pantheismus 1868. His major
work, Kritik der reinen Erfahrung Critique of Pure Experience, 2 vols., 890,
was followed by his last study, Der menschliche Weltbegriffe 1. In his
post-Kantian Kritik Avenarius presented a radical positivism that sought to
base philosophy on scientific principles. This “empirio-criticism” emphasized
“pure experience” and descriptive and general definitions of experience.
Metaphysical claims to transcend experience were rejected as mere creations of
the mind. Like Hume, Avenarius denied the ontological validity of substance and
causality. Seeking a scientific empiricism, he endeavored to delineate a
descriptive determination of the form and content of pure experience. He
thought that the subject-object dichotomy, the separation of inner and outer
experiences, falsified reality. If we could avoid “introjecting” feeling,
thought, and will into experience and thereby splitting it into subject and
object, we could attain the original “natural” view of the world. Although
Avenarius, in his Critique of Pure Experience, thought that changes in brain
states parallel states of consciousness, he did not reduce sensations or states
of consciousness to physiological changes in the brain. Because his theory of
pure experience undermined dogmatic materialism, Lenin attacked his philosophy
in Materialism and Empirio-Criticism 2. His epistemology influenced Mach and
his emphasis upon pure experience had considerable influence on James.
awareness: an Anglo-Saxon,
“sort of,” term Grice liked – for Grice, awareness means the doxastic attitude
prefixed to any other state -- consciousness, a central feature of our lives
that is notoriously difficult to characterize. You experience goings-on in the
world, and, turning inward “introspecting”, you experience your experiencing.
Objects of awareness can be external or internal. Pressing your finger on the
edge of a table, you can be aware of the table’s edge, and aware of the feeling
of pressure though perhaps not simultaneously. Philosophers from Locke to Nagel
have insisted that our experiences have distinctive qualities: there is
“something it is like” to have them. It would seem important, then, to
distinguish qualities of objects of which you are aware from qualities of your
awareness. Suppose you are aware of a round, red tomato. The tomato, but not
your awareness, is round and red. What then are the qualities of your
awareness? Here we encounter a deep puzzle that divides theorists into
intransigent camps. Some materialists, like Dennett, insist that awareness
lacks qualities or lacks qualities distinct from its objects: the qualities we
attribute to experiences are really those of experienced objects. This opens
the way to a dismissal of “phenomenal” qualities qualia, qualities that seem to
have no place in the material world. Others T. Nagel, Ned Block regard such
qualities as patently genuine, preferring to dismiss any theory unable to
accommodate them. Convinced that the qualities of awareness are ineliminable
and irreducible to respectable material properties, some philosophers,
following Frank Jackson, contend they are “epiphenomenal”: real but causally
inefficacious. Still others, including Searle, point to what they regard as a
fundamental distinction between the “intrinsically subjective” character of
awareness and the “objective,” “public” character of material objects, but deny
that this yields epiphenomenalism.
axioma – Porphyry
translated this as ‘principium,’ but Grice was not too happy about it! Referred
to by Grice in his portrayal of the formalists in their account of an ‘ideal’
language. He is thinking Peano, Whitehead, and Russell. – the axiomatic method,
originally, a method for reorganizing the accepted propositions and concepts of
an existent science in order to increase certainty in the propositions and
clarity in the concepts. Application of this method was thought to require the
identification of 1 the “universe of discourse” domain, genus of entities
constituting the primary subject matter of the science, 2 the “primitive
concepts” that can be grasped immediately without the use of definition, 3 the
“primitive propositions” or “axioms”, whose truth is knowable immediately,
without the use of deduction, 4 an immediately acceptable “primitive definition”
in terms of primitive concepts for each non-primitive concept, and 5 a
deduction constructed by chaining immediate, logically cogent inferences
ultimately from primitive propositions and definitions for each nonprimitive
accepted proposition. Prominent proponents of more or less modernized versions
of the axiomatic method, e.g. Pascal, Nicod 34, and Tarski, emphasizing the
critical and regulatory function of the axiomatic method, explicitly open the
possibility that axiomatization of an existent, preaxiomatic science may lead
to rejection or modification of propositions, concepts, and argumentations that
had previously been accepted. In many cases attempts to realize the ideal of an
axiomatic science have resulted in discovery of “smuggled premises” and other
previously unnoted presuppositions, leading in turn to recognition of the need
for new axioms. Modern axiomatizations of geometry are much richer in detail
than those produced in ancient Greece. The earliest extant axiomatic text is
based on an axiomatization of geometry due to Euclid fl. 300 B.C., which itself
was based on earlier, nolonger-extant texts. Archimedes 287212 B.C. was one of
the earliest of a succession of postEuclidean geometers, including Hilbert,
Oswald Veblen 00, and Tarski, to propose modifications of axiomatizations of
classical geometry. The traditional axiomatic method, often called the
geometric method, made several presuppositions no longer widely accepted. The
advent of non-Euclidean geometry was particularly important in this connection.
For some workers, the goal of reorganizing an existent science was joined to or
replaced by a new goal: characterizing or giving implicit definition to the
structure of the subject matter of the science. Moreover, subsequent
innovations in logic and foundations of mathematics, especially development of
syntactically precise formalized languages and effective systems of formal
deductions, have substantially increased the degree of rigor attainable. In
particular, critical axiomatic exposition of a body of scientific knowledge is
now not thought to be fully adequate, however successful it may be in realizing
the goals of the original axiomatic method, so long as it does not present the
underlying logic including language, semantics, and deduction system. For these
and other reasons the expression ‘axiomatic method’ has undergone many
“redefinitions,” some of which have only the most tenuous connection with the
original meaning. The term ‘axiom’ has
been associated to different items by philosophers. There’s the axiom of
comprehension, also called axiom of abstraction, the axiom that for every
property, there is a corresponding set of things having that property; i.e., f
DA x x 1 A È f x, where f is a property and A is a set. The axiom was used in Frege’s
formulation of set theory and is the axiom that yields Russell’s paradox,
discovered in 1. If fx is instantiated as x 2 x, then the result that A 1 A È A
2 A is easily obtained, which yields, in classical logic, the explicit
contradiction A 1 A & A 2 A. The paradox can be avoided by modifying the
comprehension axiom and using instead the separation axiom, f DA x x 1 A Èfx
& x 1 B. This yields only the result that A 1 A ÈA 2 A & A 1 B, which
is not a contradiction. The paradox can also be avoided by retaining the
comprehension axiom but restricting the symbolic language, so that ‘x 1 x’ is
not a meaningful formula. Russell’s type theory, presented in Principia Mathematica,
uses this approach. Then there’s the axiom
of consistency, an axiom stating that a given set of sentences is consistent.
Let L be a formal language, D a deductive system for L, S any set of sentences
of L, and C the statement ‘S is consistent’ i.e., ‘No contradiction is
derivable from S via D’. For certain sets S e.g., the theorems of D it is
interesting to ask: Can C be expressed in L? If so, can C be proved in D? If C
can be expressed in L but not proved in D, can C be added consistently to D as
a new axiom? Example from Gödel: Let L and D be adequate for elementary number
theory, and S be the axioms of D; then C can be expressed in L but not proved
in D, but can be added as a new axiom to form a stronger system D’. Sometimes
we can express in L an axiom of consistency in the semantic sense i.e., ‘There
is a universe in which all the sentences in S are true’. Trivial example:
suppose the only non-logical axiom in D is ‘For any two sets B and B’, there
exists the union of B and B’ ’. Then C might be ‘There is a set U such that,
for any sets B and B’ in U, there exists in U the union of B and B’ ’.
ayerianism: Grice: “One of the most memorable pieces of
Ayer’s philosophical depth is his ‘Saturday is in bed.’ It was so popular at
Oxford that Ryle, Ayer’s tutor, felt he could use it without credit!’ -- a. j.
, philosopher of Swiss ancestry, one of the most important of the Oxford
logical positivists. He continued to occupy a dominant place in analytic
philosophy as he gradually modified his adherence to central tenets of the
view. He was educated at Eton and Oxford, and, after a brief period at the of Vienna, became a lecturer in philosophy at
Christ Church in 3. After the war he returned to Oxford as fellow and dean of
Wadham . He was Grote Professor of the Philosophy of Mind and Logic at the of London 659, Wykeham Professor of Logic in
the of Oxford and a fellow of New 978, and a fellow of Wolfson , Oxford 883.
Ayer was knighted in 3 and was a Chevalier de la Légion d’Honneur. His early
work clearly and forcefully developed the implications of the positivists’
doctrines that all cognitive statements are either analytic and a priori, or
synthetic, contingent, and a posteriori, and that empirically meaningful
statements must be verifiable must admit of confirmation or disconfirmation. In
doing so he defended reductionist analyses of the self, the external world, and
other minds. Value statements that fail the empiricist’s criterion of meaning
but defy naturalistic analysis were denied truth-value and assigned emotive
meaning. Throughout his writings he maintained a foundationalist perspective in
epistemology in which sense-data later more neutrally described occupied not
only a privileged epistemic position but constituted the subject matter of the
most basic statements to be used in reductive analyses. Although in later works
he significantly modified many of his early views and abandoned much of their
strict reductionism, he remained faithful to an empiricist’s version of
foundationalism and the basic idea behind the verifiability criterion of
meaning. His books include Language, Truth and Logic; The Foundations of
Empirical Knowledge; The Problems of Knowledge; Philosophical Essays; The
Concept of a Person; The Origins of Pragmatism; Metaphysics and Common Sense;
Russell and Moore: The Analytical Heritage; The Central Questions of Philosophy;
Probability and Evidence; Philosophy in the Twentieth Century; Russell; Hume;
Freedom and Morality, Ludwig Vitters; and Voltaire. Born of Swiss parentage in
London, “Freddie” got an Oxford educated, and though he wanted to be a judge,
he read Lit. Hum (Phil.). He spent three months in Vienna, and when he
returned, Grice called him ‘enfant terrible.’ Ayer would later cite Grice in
the Aristotelian symposium on the Causal Theory of Perception. But the type of
subtlety in conversational implicaturum that Grice is interested goes over
Freddie’s head. (“That,” or he was not interested.” Grice was glad that Oxford
was ready to attack Ayer on philosophical grounds, and he later lists
Positivism as a ‘monster’ on his way to the City of Eternal Truth. “Verificationism”
was anti-Oxonian, in being mainly anti-Bradleyian, who is recognised by every
Oxonian philosopher as “one of the clearest and subtlest prosists in English,
and particularly Oxonian, philosophy.” Ayer later became the logic professor at
Oxford – which is now taught no longer at the Sub-Faculty of Philosophy, but
the Department of Mathematics!
babbage: discussed by
Grice in his functionalist approach to philosophical psychology. English
applied mathematician, inventor, and expert on machinery and manufacturing. His
chief interest was in developing mechanical “engines” to compute tables of
functions. Until the invention of the electronic computer, printed tables of
functions were important aids to calculation. Babbage invented the difference
engine, a machine that consisted of a series of accumulators each of which, in
turn, transmitted its contents to its successor, which added to them to its own
contents. He built only a model, but George and Edvard Scheutz built difference
engines that were actually used. Though tables of squares and cubes could be
calculated by a difference engine, the more commonly used tables of logarithms
and of trigonometric functions could not. To calculate these and other useful
functions, Babbage conceived of the analytical engine, a machine for numerical
analysis. The analytical engine was to have a store memory and a mill
arithmetic unit. The store was to hold decimal numbers on toothed wheels, and
to transmit them to the mill and back by means of wheels and toothed bars. The
mill was to carry out the arithmetic operations of addition, subtraction,
multiplication, and division mechanically, greatly extending the technology of
small calculators. The operations of the mill were to be governed by pegged
drums, derived from the music box. A desired sequence of operations would be
punched on cards, which would be strung together like the cards of a Jacquard
loom and read by the machine. The control mechanisms could branch and execute a
different sequence of cards when a designated quantity changed sign. Numbers
would be entered from punched cards and the answers punched on cards. The
answers might also be imprinted on metal sheets from which the calculated
tables would be printed, thus avoiding the errors of proofreading. Although
Babbage formulated various partial plans for the analytical engine and built a
few pieces of it, the machine was never realized. Given the limitations of
mechanical computing technology, building an analytical engine would probably
not have been an economical way to produce numerical tables. The modern
electronic computer was invented and developed completely independently of
Babbage’s pioneering work. Yet because of it, Babbage’s work has been
publicized and he has become famous.
bachelard: g., philosopher
of applied rationalism, enjoyed by Grice. philosopher of science and literary
analyst. His philosophy of science developed, e.g., in The New Scientific
Spirit, 4, and Rational Materialism, 3 began from reflections on the
relativistic and quantum revolutions in twentieth-century physics. Bachelard
viewed science as developing through a series of discontinuous changes
epistemological breaks. Such breaks overcome epistemological obstacles:
methodological and conceptual features of commonsense or outdated science that
block the path of inquiry. Bachelard’s emphasis on the discontinuity of
scientific change strikingly anticipated Thomas Kuhn’s focus, many years later,
on revolutionary paradigm change. However, unlike Kuhn, Bachelard held to a
strong notion of scientific progress across revolutionary discontinuities.
Although each scientific framework rejects its predecessors as fundamentally
erroneous, earlier frameworks may embody permanent achievements that will be
preserved as special cases within subsequent frameworks. Newton’s laws of
motion, e.g., are special limit-cases of relativity theory. Bachelard based his
philosophy of science on a “non-Cartesian epistemology” that rejects
Descartes’s claim that knowledge must be founded on incorrigible intuitions of
first truths. All knowledge claims are subject to revision in the light of
further evidence. Similarly, he rejected a naive realism that defines reality
in terms of givens of ordinary sense experience and ignores the ontological
constructions of scientific concepts and instrumentation. He maintained,
however, that denying this sort of realism did not entail accepting idealism,
which makes only the mental ultimately real. Instead he argued for an “applied
rationalism,” which recognizes the active role of reason in constituting
objects of knowledge while admitting that any constituting act of reason must
be directed toward an antecedently given object. Although Bachelard denied the
objective reality of the perceptual and imaginative worlds, he emphasized their
subjective and poetic significance. Complementing his writings on science are a
series of books on imagination and poetic imagery e.g., The Psychoanalysis of
Fire, 8; The Poetics of Space, 7 which subtly unpack the meaning of archetypal
in Jung’s sense images. He put forward a “law of the four elements,” according
to which all images can be related to the earth, air, fire, and water posited
by Empedocles as the fundamental forms of matter. Together with Georges
Canguilhem, his successor at the Sorbonne, Bachelard had an immense impact on
several generations of students of
philosophy. He and Canguilhem offered an important alternative to the more
fashionable and widely known phenomenology and existentialism and were major
influences on among others Althusser and Foucault.
baconian – “You can tell
when a contitnental philosopher knows about insular philosopher when they can
tell one bacon from the other.” – H. P. Grice. Francis: English philosopher,
essayist, and scientific methodologist. In politics Bacon rose to the position
of lord chancellor. In 1621 he retired to private life after conviction for
taking bribes in his official capacity as judge. Bacon championed the new
empiricism resulting from the achievements of early modern science. He opposed
alleged knowledge based on appeals to authority, and on the barrenness of
Scholasticism. He thought that what is needed is a new attitude and methodology
based strictly on scientific practices. The goal of acquiring knowledge is the
good of mankind: knowledge is power. The social order that should result from
applied science is portrayed in his New Atlantis1627. The method of induction
to be employed is worked out in detail in his Novum Organum 1620. This new
logic is to replace that of Aristotle’s syllogism, as well as induction by
simple enumeration of instances. Neither of these older logics can produce
knowledge of actual natural laws. Bacon thought that we must intervene in
nature, manipulating it by means of experimental control leading to the invention
of new technology. There are well-known hindrances to acquisition of knowledge
of causal laws. Such hindrances false opinions, prejudices, which “anticipate”
nature rather than explain it, Bacon calls idols idola. Idols of the tribe
idola tribus are natural mental tendencies, among which are the idle search for
purposes in nature, and the impulse to read our own desires and needs into
nature. Idols of the cave idola specus are predispositions of particular
individuals. The individual is inclined to form opinions based on
idiosyncrasies of education, social intercourse, reading, and favored
authorities. Idols of the marketplace idola fori Bacon regards as the most
potentially dangerous of all dispositions, because they arise from common uses
of language that often result in verbal disputes. Many words, though thought to
be meaningful, stand for nonexistent things; others, although they name actual
things, are poorly defined or used in confused ways. Idols of the theater idola
theatri depend upon the influence of received theories. The only authority
possessed by such theories is that they are ingenious verbal constructions. The
aim of acquiring genuine knowledge does not depend on superior skill in the use
of words, but rather on the discovery of natural laws. Once the idols are
eliminated, the mind is free to seek knowledge of natural laws based on
experimentation. Bacon held that nothing exists in nature except bodies
material objects acting in conformity with fixed laws. These laws are “forms.”
For example, Bacon thought that the form or cause of heat is the motion of the
tiny particles making up a body. This form is that on which the existence of
heat depends. What induction seeks to show is that certain laws are perfectly
general, universal in application. In every case of heat, there is a measurable
change in the motion of the particles constituting the moving body. Bacon
thought that scientific induction proceeds as follows. First, we look for those
cases where, given certain changes, certain others invariably follow. In his
example, if certain changes in the form motion of particles take place, heat
always follows. We seek to find all of the “positive instances” of the form
that give rise to the effect of that form. Next, we investigate the “negative
instances,” cases where in the absence of the form, the qualitative change does
not take place. In the operation of these methods it is important to try to
produce experimentally “prerogative instances,” particularly striking or
typical examples of the phenomenon under investigation. Finally, in cases where
the object under study is present to some greater or lesser degree, we must be
able to take into account why these changes occur. In the example, quantitative
changes in degrees of heat will be correlated to quantitative changes in the
speed of the motion of the particles. This method implies that backward
causation Bacon, Francis 68 68 in many
cases we can invent instruments to measure changes in degree. Such inventions
are of course the hoped-for outcome of scientific inquiry, because their
possession improves the lot of human beings. Bacon’s strikingly modern but not
entirely novel empiricist methodology influenced nineteenth-century figures
e.g., Sir John Herschel and J. S. Mill who generalized his results and used
them as the basis for displaying new insights into scientific methodology.
baconian: “You can tell
when a continental philosopher knows the first thing about insular philosophy
when they can tell one bacon from the other” – H. P. Grice. R., English
philosopher who earned the honorific title of Doctor Mirabilis. He was one of
the first medievals in the Latin West to lecture and comment on newly recovered
work by Aristotle in natural philosophy, physics, and metaphysics. Born in
Somerset and educated at both Oxford and
the of Paris, he became by 1273 a master
of arts at Paris, where he taught for about ten years. In 1247 he resigned his
teaching post to devote his energies to investigating and promoting topics he
considered neglected but important insofar as they would lead to knowledge of
God. The English “experimentalist” Grosseteste, the man Peter of Maricourt, who
did pioneering work on magnetism, and the author of the pseudo-Aristotelian
Secretum secretorum influenced Roger’s new perspective. By 1257, however,
partly from fatigue, Roger had put this work aside and entered the Franciscan
order in England. To his dismay, he did not receive within the order the
respect and freedom to write and teach he had expected. During the early 1260s
Roger’s views about reforming the
curriculum reached Cardinal Guy le Gos de Foulques, who, upon becoming
Pope Clement IV in 1265, demanded to see Roger’s writings. In response, Roger
produced the Opus maius 1267 an
encyclopedic work that argues, among other things, that 1 the study of Hebrew
and Grecian is indispensable for understanding the Bible, 2 the study of
mathematics encompassing geometry, astronomy, and astrology is, with
experimentation, the key to all the sciences and instrumental in theology, and
3 philosophy can serve theology by helping in the conversion of non-believers.
Roger believed that although the Bible is the basis for human knowledge, we can
use reason in the service of knowledge. It is not that rational argument can,
on his view, provide fullblown proof of anything, but rather that with the aid
of reason one can formulate hypotheses about nature that can be confirmed by
experience. According to Roger, knowledge arrived at in this way will lead to
knowledge of nature’s creator. All philosophical, scientific, and linguistic
endeavors are valuable ultimately for the service they can render to theology.
Roger summarizes and develops his views on these matters in the Opus minus and
the Opus tertium, produced within a year of the Opus maius. Roger was
altogether serious in advocating curricular change. He took every opportunity
to rail against many of his celebrated contemporaries e.g., Alexander of Hales,
Bonaventure, Albertus Magnus, and Aquinas for not being properly trained in
philosophy and for contributing to the demise of theology by lecturing on Peter
Lombard’s Sentences instead of the Bible. He also wrote both Grecian and Hebrew
grammars, did important work in optics, and argued for calendar reform on the
basis of his admittedly derivative astronomical research. One should not,
however, think that Roger was a good mathematician or natural scientist. He
apparently never produced a single theorem or proof in mathematics, he was not
always a good judge of astronomical competence he preferred al-Bitruji to
Ptolemy, and he held alchemy in high regard, believing that base metals could
be turned into silver and gold. Some have gone so far as to claim that Roger’s
renown in the history of science is vastly overrated, based in part on his
being confusedly linked with the fourteenthcentury Oxford Calculators, who do
deserve credit for paving the way for certain developments in
seventeenth-century science. Roger’s devotion to curricular reform eventually
led to his imprisonment by Jerome of Ascoli the future Pope Nicholas IV,
probably between 1277 and 1279. Roger’s teachings were said to have contained
“suspect novelties.” Judging from the date of his imprisonment, these novelties
may have been any number of propositions condemned by the bishop of Paris,
Étienne Tempier, in 1277. But his imprisonment may also have had something to
do with the anger he undoubtedly provoked by constantly abusing the members of
his order regarding their approach to education, or with his controversial
Joachimite views about the apocalypse and the imminent coming of the
Antichrist. Given Roger’s interest in educational reform and his knack for
systematization, it is not unlikely that he was abreast of and had something to
say about most of the central philosophical issues of the day. If so, his
writings could be an important source of information about thirteenth-century
Scholastic philosophy generally. In this connection, recent investigations have
revealed, e.g., that he may well have played an important role in the development
of logic and philosophy of language during the thirteenth and early fourteenth
centuries. In the course of challenging the views of certain people some of
whom have been tentatively identified as Richard of Cornwall, Lambert of
Auxerre, Siger of Brabant, Henry of Ghent, Boethius of Dacia, William Sherwood,
and the Magister Abstractionum on the nature of signs and how words function as
signs, Roger develops and defends views that appear to be original. The
pertinent texts include the Sumule dialectices c.1250, the De signis part of
Part III of the Opus maius, and the Compendium studii theologiae 1292. E.g., in
connection with the question whether Jesus could be called a man during the
three-day entombment and, thus, in connection with the related question whether
man can be said to be animal when no man exists, and with the sophism ‘This is
a dead man, therefore this is a man’, Roger was not content to distinguish
words from all other signs as had been the tradition. He distinguished between
signs originating from nature and from the soul, and between natural
signification and conventional ad placitum signification which results
expressly or tacitly from the imposition of meaning by one or more individuals.
He maintained that words signify existing and non-existing entities only
equivocally, because words conventionally signify only presently existing
things. On this view, therefore, ‘man’ is not used univocally when applied to
an existing man and to a dead man.
bona fides: vs. mala fides: dishonest
and blameworthy instances of self-deception; 2 inauthentic and self-deceptive
refusal to admit to ourselves and others our full freedom, thereby avoiding
anxiety in making decisions and evading responsibility for actions and
attitudes Sartre, Being and Nothingness, 3; 3 hypocrisy or dishonesty in speech
and conduct, as in making a promise without intending to keep it. One
self-deceiving strategy identified by Sartre is to embrace other people’s views
in order to avoid having to form one’s own; another is to disregard options so
that one’s life appears predetermined to move in a fixed direction.
Occasionally Sartre used a narrower, fourth sense: self-deceptive beliefs held
on the basis of insincere and unreasonable interpretations of evidence, as
contrasted with the dishonesty of “sincerely” acknowledging one truth “I am
disposed to be a thief” in order to deny a deeper truth “I am free to
change”.
bain: a., philosopher
and reformer, biographer of James Mill 2 and J. S. Mill 2 and founder of the
first psychological journal, Mind 1876, to which Grice submitted his “Personal
identity.” In the development of psychology, Bain represents in England
alongside Continental thinkers such as Taine and Lotze the final step toward
the founding of psychology as a science. His significance stems from his wish
to “unite psychology and physiology,” fulfilled in The Senses and the Intellect
1855 and The Emotions and the Will 1859, abridged in one volume, Mental and
Moral Science 1868. Neither Bain’s psychology nor his physiology were
particularly original. His psychology came from English empiricism and
associationism, his physiology from Johannes Muller’s 180158 Elements of
Physiology 1842. Muller was an early advocate of the reflex, or sensorimotor,
conception of the nervous system, holding that neurons conduct sensory
information to the brain or motor commands from the brain, the brain connecting
sensation with appropriate motor response. Like Hartley before him, Bain
grounded the laws of mental association in the laws of neural connection. In
opposition to faculty psychology, Bain rejected the existence of mental powers
located in different parts of the brain On the Study of Character, 1861. By
combining associationism with modern physiology, he virtually completed the
movement of philosophical psychology toward science. In philosophy, his most
important concept was his analysis of belief as “a preparation to act.” By thus
entwining conception and action, he laid the foundation for pragmatism, and for
the focus on adaptive behavior central to modern psychology.
banez: philosopher known
for his disputes with Molina concerning divine grace, or grice. Against Molina
he held physical predetermination, the view that God physically determines the
secondary causes of human action. This renders grace intrinsically efficacious
and independent of human will and merits. He is also known for his
understanding of the centrality of the act of existence esse in Thomistic
metaphysics. Bañez’s most important works are his commentaries on Aquinas’s
Summa theologiae and Aristotle’s On Generation and Corruption.
barthesian: semiotic: r. post-structuralist literary critic and
essayist. Born in Cherbourg, he suffered from numerous ailments as a child and
spent much of his early life as a semiinvalid. After leaving the military, he
took up several positions teaching subjects like classics, grammar, and
philology. His interest in linguistics finally drew him to literature, and by
the mid-0s he had already published what would become a classic in structural
analysis, The Elements of Semiology. Its principal message is that words are
merely one kind of sign whose meaning lies in relations of difference between
them. This concept was later amended to include the reading subject, and the
structuring effect that the subject has on the literary work a concept expressed later in his S/Z and The
Pleasure of the Text. Barthes’s most mature contributions to the
post-structuralist movement were brilliant and witty interpretations of visual,
tactile, and aural sign systems, culminating in the publication of several
books and essays on photography, advertising, film, and cuisine.
bite off more than
you can chew:
To bite is the function of the FRONT teeth (incisors and
canines); the back teeth (molars) CHEW, crush, or grind. So the relation is Russellian. 1916 G. B. Shaw Pygmalion 195 The mistake we describe metaphorically as
‘biting off more than they can chew’. a1960 J.
L. Austin Sense & Sensibilia (1962) i. 1 They [sc. doctrines] all bite off more than they can chew. While the NED would not DARE define this obviousness,
the OED does not. to undertake too
much, to be too ambitious – “irrational” simpliciter for Grice (WoW).
basilides: philosopher, he
improved on Valentinus’s doctrine of emanations, positing 365 the number of
days in a year levels of existence in the Pleroma the fullness of the Godhead,
all descending from the ineffable Father. He taught that the rival God was the
God of the Jews the God of the Old Testament, who created the material world.
Redemption consists in the coming of the first begotten of the Father, Noûs
Mind, in human form in order to release the spiritual element imprisoned within
human bodies. Like other gnostics he taught that we are saved by knowledge, not
faith. He apparently held to the idea of reincarnation before the restoration
of all things to the Pleroma.
basis: basing relation,
also called basis relation, the relation between a belief or item of knowledge
and a second belief or item of knowledge when the latter is the ground basis of
the first. It is clear that some knowledge is indirect, i.e., had or gained on
the basis of some evidence, as opposed to direct knowledge, which assuming
there is any is not so gained, or based. The same holds for justified belief.
In one broad sense of the term, the basing relation is just the one connecting
indirect knowledge or indirectly justified belief to the evidence: to give an
account of either of the latter is to give an account of the basing relation.
There is a narrower view of the basing relation, perhaps implicit in the first.
A person knows some proposition P on the basis of evidence or reasons only if
her belief that P is based on the evidence or reasons, or perhaps on the
possession of the evidence or reasons. The narrow basing relation is indicated
by this question: where a belief that P constitutes indirect knowledge or
justification, what is it for that belief to be based on the evidence or
reasons that support the knowledge or justification? The most widely favored
view is that the relevant belief is based on evidence or reasons only if the
belief is causally related to the belief or reasons. Proponents of this causal
view differ concerning what, beyond this causal relationship, is needed by an
account of the narrow basing relation.
batailleian
communicatum:
g., philosopher and novelist with enormous influence on post-structuralist
thought. By locating value in expenditure as opposed to accumulation, Bataille
inaugurates the era of the death of the subject. He insists that individuals
must transgress the limits imposed by subjectivity to escape isolation and
communicate. Bataille’s prewar philosophical contributions consist mainly of
short essays, the most significant of which have been collected in Visions of
Excess. These essays introduce the central idea that base matter disrupts
rational subjectivity by attesting to the continuity in which individuals lose
themselves. Inner Experience, Bataille’s first lengthy philosophical treatise,
was followed by Guilty 4 and On Nietzsche 5. Together, these three works
constitute Bataille’s Summa Atheologica, which explores the play of the
isolation and the dissolution of beings in terms of the experience of excess
laughter, tears, eroticism, death, sacrifice, poetry. The Accursed Share 9,
which he considered his most important work, is his most systematic account of
the social and economic implications of expenditure. In Erotism 7 and The Tears
of Eros 1, he focuses on the excesses of sex and death. Throughout his life,
Bataille was concerned with the question of value. He located it in the excess
that lacerates individuals and opens channels of communication.
bath: Grice never
referred to William of Occam as “William” (“that would be rude”). Similarlly,
his Adelard of Bath is referred to as “Bath.” (“Sometimes I wish people would
refer to me as “Harborne” but that was the day!”). “Of course, it is amusing to
refer to adelard as “Bath” since he was only there for twelve years! But surely
to call him “Oxford” would be supernumerary!”. Grice found inspiration on
Adelard’s “On the same and the different,” and he was pleased that he had been
educated not far from Bath, at Clifton! Adelard is Benedictine monk notable for
his contributions to the introduction of Arabic science in the West. After
studying at Tours, he taught at Laon, then spent seven years traveling in
Italy, possibly Spain, and Cilicia and Syria, before returning to England. In
his dialogue On the Same and the Different, he remarks, concerning universals,
that the names of individuals, species, and genera are imposed on the same
essence regarded in different respects. He also wrote Seventy-six Questions on
Nature, based on Arabic learning; works on the use of the abacus and the
astrolabe; a work on falconry; and translations of Abu Ma’shar’s Arabic active
euthanasia Adelard of Bath 9 4065A- 9
Shorter Introduction to Astronomy, al-Khwarizmi’s fl. c.830 astronomical tables,
and Euclid’s Elements.
baumgarten: a. g. – Grice
loved his coinage of ‘aesthetics’-- Alexander Gottlieb 171462, G. philosopher.
Born in Berlin, he was educated in Halle and taught at Halle 173840 and
Frankfurt an der Oder 174062. Baumgarten was brought up in the Pietist circle
of A. H. Francke but adopted the anti-Pietist rationalism of Wolff. He wrote
textbooks in metabasic particular Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb 73 73 physics Metaphysica, 1739 and ethics
Ethica Philosophica, 1740; Initia Philosophiae Practicae Prima [“First Elements
of Practical Philosophy”], 1760 on which Kant lectured. For the most part,
Baumgarten did not significantly depart from Wolff, although in metaphysics he
was both further and yet closer to Leibniz than was Wolff: unlike Leibniz, he
argued for real physical influx, but, unlike Wolff, he did not restrict
preestablished harmony to the mindbody relationship alone, but paradoxically
reextended it to include all relations of substances. Baumgarten’s claim to
fame, however, rests on his introduction of the discipline of aesthetics into
G. philosophy, and indeed on his introduction of the term ‘aesthetics’ as well.
Wolff had explained pleasure as the response to the perception of perfection by
means of the senses, in turn understood as clear but confused perception.
Baumgarten subtly but significantly departed from Wolff by redefining our
response to beauty as pleasure in the perfection of sensory perception, i.e.,
in the unique potential of sensory as opposed to merely conceptual
representation. This concept was first introduced in his dissertation
Meditationes Philosophicae de Nonnullis ad Poema Pertinentibus “Philosophical
Meditations on some Matters pertaining to Poetry,” 1735, which defined a poem
as a “perfect sensate discourse,” and then generalized in his twovolume but
still incomplete Aesthetica 1750 58. One might describe Baumgarten’s aesthetics
as cognitivist but no longer rationalist: while in science or logic we must
always prefer discursive clarity, in art we respond with pleasure to the
maximally dense or “confused” intimation of ideas. Baumgarten’s theory had
great influence on Lessing and Mendelssohn, on Kant’s theory of aesthetic
ideas, and even on the aesthetics of Hegel.
bayle: p., Grice on
longitudinal history of philosophy. philosopher who also pioneered in
disinterested, critical history. A Calvinist forced into exile in 1681, Bayle
nevertheless rejected the prevailing use of history as an instrument of
partisan or sectarian interest. He achieved fame and notoriety with his
multivolume Dictionnaire historique et critique 1695. For each subject covered,
Bayle provided a biographical sketch and a dispassionate examination of the
historical record and interpretive controversies. He also repeatedly probed the
troubled and troubling boundary between reason and faith philosophy and
religion. In the article “David,” the seemingly illicit conduct of God’s
purported agent yielded reflections on the morals of the elect and the autonomy
of ethics. In “Pyrrho,” Bayle argued that self-evidence, the most plausible
candidate for the criterion of truth, is discredited by Christianity because
some self-evident principles contradict essential Christian truths and are
therefore false. Finally, provoking Leibniz’s Theodicy, Bayle argued, most
relentlessly in “Manichaeans” and “Paulicians,” that there is no defensible
rational solution to the problem of evil. Bayle portrayed himself as a
Christian skeptic, but others have seen instead an ironic critic of
religion a precursor of the Enlightenment. Bayle’s purely philosophical
reflections support his self-assessment, since he consistently maintains that
philosophy achieves not comprehension and contentment, but paradox and
puzzlement. In making this case he proved to be a superb critic of
philosophical systems. Some examples are “Zeno of Elea” on space, time, and motion; “Rorarius” on mind and body and animal mechanism; and
“Spinoza” on the perils of monism.
Bayle’s skepticism concerning philosophy significantly influenced Berkeley and
Hume. His other important works include Pensées diverses de la comète de 1683
1683; Commentaire philosophique sur ces paroles de Jesus Christ: contrain les
d’entrer 1686; and Réponse aux questions d’un provincial1704; and an early
learned periodical, the Nouvelles de la République des Lettres 1684 87.
beattie, j. Common-sense –
H. P. Grice, “The so-called English common-sense,” Beattie: j. philosopher and
poet who, in criticizing Hume, widened the latter’s audience. A member of the
Scottish school of common sense philosophy along with Oswald and Reid,
Beattie’s major work was An Essay on the Nature and Immutability of Truth 1771,
in which he criticizes Hume for fostering skepticism and infidelity. His
positive view was that the mind possesses a common sense, i.e., a power for
perceiving self-evident truths. Common sense is instinctive, unalterable by
education; truth is what common sense determines the mind to believe. Beattie
cited Hume and then claimed that his views led to moral and religious evils.
When Beattie’s Essay was tr. into G. 1772, Kant could read Hume’s discussions
of personal identity and causation. Since these topics were not covered in
Hume’s Inquiry Concerning Human Understanding, Beattie provided Kant access to
two issues in the Treatises of Human Nature critical to the development of
transcendental idealism.
beccaria, c. philosopher – Referred to by H. P. Grice in
his explorations on moral versus legal right, studied in Parma and Pavia and
taught political economy in Milan. Here, he met Pietro and Alessandro Verri and
other Milanese intellectuals attempting to promote political, economical, and
judiciary reforms. His major work, Dei delitti e delle pene “On Crimes and
Punishments,” 1764, denounces the contemporary methods in the administration of
justice and the treatment of criminals. Beccaria argues that the highest good
is the greatest happiness shared by the greatest number of people; hence,
actions against the state are the most serious crimes. Crimes against
individuals and property are less serious, and crimes endangering public
harmony are the least serious. The purposes of punishment are deterrence and
the protection of society. However, the employment of torture to obtain
confessions is unjust and useless: it results in acquittal of the strong and
the ruthless and conviction of the weak and the innocent. Beccaria also rejects
the death penalty as a war of the state against the individual. He claims that
the duration and certainty of the punishment, not its intensity, most strongly
affect criminals. Beccaria was influenced by Montesquieu, Rousseau, and
Condillac. His major work was tr. into many languages and set guidelines for
revising the criminal and judicial systems of several European countries.
beneke: a Kantian
commentator beloved by Grice (“if only because he could read Kant in the
vernacular!”)-- philosopher who was influenced by Herbart and English
empiricism and criticized rationalistic metaphysics. He taught at Berlin and
published some eighteen books in philosophy. His major work was Lehrbuch der
Psychologie als Naturwissenschaft 1833. He wrote a critical study of Kant’s
Critique of Pure Reason and another on his moral theory; other works included
Psychologie Skizzen 1825, Metaphysik und Religionphilosophie 1840, and Die neue
Psychologie 1845. The “new psychology” developed by Beneke held that the
hypostatization of “faculties” led to a mythical psychology. He proposed a
method that would yield a natural science of the soul or, in effect, an
associationist psychology. Influenced by the British empiricists, he conceived
the elements of mental life as dynamic, active processes or impulses Trieben.
These “elementary faculties,” originally activated by stimuli, generate the
substantial unity of the nature of the psychic by their persistence as traces,
as well as by their reciprocal adjustment in relation to the continuous production
of new forces. In what Beneke called “pragmatic psychology,” the psyche is a
bundle of impulses, forces, and functions. Psychological theory should rest on
inductive analyses of the facts of inner perception. This, in turn, is the
foundation of the philosophical disciplines of logic, ethics, metaphysics, and
philosophy of religion. In this regard, Beneke held a psychologism. He agreed
with Herbart that psychology must be based on inner experience and must eschew
metaphysical speculation, but rejected Hebart’s mathematical reductionism.
Beneke sought to create a “pragmatic philosophy” based on his psychology. In
his last years he contributed to pedagogic theory.
benthamian: -- semiotics --
j. Engish philosopher of ethics and political-legal theory. Born in London, he
entered Queen’s, Oxford, at age 12, and after graduation entered Lincoln’s Inn
to study law. He was admitted to the bar in 1767 but never practiced. He spent
his life writing, advocating changes along utilitarian lines maximal happiness for
everyone affected of the whole legal system, especially the criminal law. He
was a strong influence in changes of the British law of evidence; in abolition
of laws permitting imprisonment for indebtedness; in the belief, basic Bentham,
Jeremy 79 79 reform of Parliamentary
representation; in the formation of a civil service recruited by examination;
and in much else. His major work published during his lifetime was An
Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation 1789. He became head
of a “radical” group including James Mill and J. S. Mill, and founded the
Westminster Review and , London where
his embalmed body still reposes in a closet. He was a friend of Catherine of
Russia and John Quincy Adams, and was made a citizen of France in 1792. Pleasure,
he said, is the only good, and pain the only evil: “else the words good and
evil have no meaning.” He gives a list of examples of what he means by
‘pleasure’: pleasures of taste, smell, or touch; of acquiring property; of
learning that one has the goodwill of others; of power; of a view of the
pleasures of those one cares about. Bentham was also a psychological hedonist:
pleasures and pains determine what we do. Take pain. Your state of mind may be
painful now at the time just prior to action because it includes the
expectation of the pain say of being burned; the present pain or the
expectation of later pain Bentham is
undecided which motivates action to prevent being burned. One of a person’s
pleasures, however, may be sympathetic enjoyment of the well-being of another.
So it seems one can be motivated by the prospect of the happiness of another.
His psychology here is not incompatible with altruistic motivation. Bentham’s
critical utilitarianism lies in his claim that any action, or measure of government,
ought to be taken if and only if it tends to augment the happiness of everyone
affected not at all a novel principle,
historically. When “thus interpreted, the words ought, and right and wrong . .
. have a meaning: when otherwise, they have none.” Bentham evidently did not
mean this statement as a purely linguistic point about the actual meaning of
moral terms. Neither can this principle be proved; it is a first principle from
which all proofs proceed. What kind of reason, then, can he offer in its
support? At one point he says that the principle of utility, at least
unconsciously, governs the judgment of “every thinking man . . . unavoidably.”
But his chief answer is his critique of a widely held principle that a person
properly calls an act wrong if when informed of the facts he disapproves of it.
Bentham cites other language as coming to the same thesis: talk of a “moral
sense,” or common sense, or the understanding, or the law of nature, or right
reason, or the “fitness of things.” He says that this is no principle at all,
since a “principle is something that points out some external consideration, as
a means of warranting and guiding the internal sentiments of approbation. . .
.” The alleged principle also allows for widespread disagreement about what is
moral. So far, Bentham’s proposal has not told us exactly how to determine
whether an action or social measure is right or wrong. Bentham suggests a
hedonic calculus: in comparing two actions under consideration, we count up the
pleasures or pains each will probably produce
how intense, how long-lasting, whether near or remote, including any
derivative later pleasures or pains that may be caused, and sum them up for all
persons who will be affected. Evidently these directions can provide at best
only approximate results. We are in no position to decide whether one pleasure
for one hour is greater than another pleasure for half an hour, even when they
are both pleasures of one person who can compare them. How much more when the
pleasures are of different persons? Still, we can make judgments important for
the theory of punishment: whether a blow in the face with no lasting damage for
one person is more or less painful than fifty lashes for his assailant! Bentham
has been much criticized because he thought that two pleasures are equal in
value, if they are equally intense, enduring, etc. As he said, “Quantity of
pleasure being equal, pushpin is as good as poetry.” It has been thought e.g.,
by J. S. Mill that some pleasures, especially intellectual ones, are higher and
deserve to count more. But it may be replied that the so-called higher
pleasures are more enduring, are less likely to be followed by satiety, and
open up new horizons of enjoyment; and when these facts are taken into account,
it is not clear that there is need to accord higher status to intellectual
pleasures as such. A major goal of Bentham’s was to apply to the criminal law
his principle of maximizing the general utility. Bentham thought there should
be no punishment of an offense if it is not injurious to someone. So how much
punishment should there be? The least amount the effect of which will result in
a greater degree of happiness, overall. The benefit of punishment is primarily
deterrence, by attaching to the thought of a given act the thought of the
painful sanction which will deter both
the past and prospective lawbreakers. The punishment, then, must be severe
enough to outweigh the benefit of the offense to the agent, making allowance,
by addition, for the uncertainty that the punishment will actually occur. There
are some harmful acts, however, that it is Bentham, Jeremy Bentham, Jeremy
80 80 not beneficial to punish. One is
an act needful to produce a greater benefit, or avoid a serious evil, for the
agent. Others are those which a penal prohibition could not deter: when the law
is unpublished or the agent is insane or an infant. In some cases society need
feel no alarm about the future actions of the agent. Thus, an act is criminal
only if intentional, and the agent is excused if he acted on the basis of
beliefs such that, were they true, the act would have caused no harm, unless
these beliefs were culpable in the sense that they would not have been held by
a person of ordinary prudence or benevolence. The propriety of punishing an act
also depends somewhat on its motive, although no motive e.g., sexual desire,
curiosity, wanting money, love of reputation
is bad in itself. Yet the propriety of punishment is affected by the
presence of some motivations that enhance public security because it is
unlikely that they e.g., sympathetic
concern or concern for reputation will
lead to bad intentional acts. When a given motive leads to a bad intention, it
is usually because of the weakness of motives like sympathy, concern for
avoiding punishment, or respect for law. In general, the sanction of moral
criticism should take lines roughly similar to those of the ideal law. But
there are some forms of behavior, e.g., imprudence or fornication, which the
law is hardly suited to punish, that can be sanctioned by morality. The
business of the moral philosopher is censorial: to say what the law, or
morality, ought to be. To say what is the law is a different matter: what it is
is the commands of the sovereign, defined as one whom the public, in general,
habitually obeys. As consisting of commands, it is imperatival. The imperatives
may be addressed to the public, as in “Let no one steal,” or to judges: “Let a
judge sentence anyone who steals to be hanged.” It may be thought that there is
a third part, an explanation, say, of what is a person’s property; but this can
be absorbed in the imperatival part, since the designations of property are
just imperatives about who is to be free to do what. Why should anyone obey the
actual laws? Bentham’s answer is that one should do so if and only if it
promises to maximize the general happiness. He eschews contract theories of
political obligation: individuals now alive never contracted, and so how are
they bound? He also opposes appeal to natural rights. If what are often
mentioned as natural rights were taken seriously, no government could survive:
it could not tax, require military service, etc. Nor does he accept appeal to
“natural law,” as if, once some law is shown to be immoral, it can be said to
be not really law. That would be absurd.
berdyaevian: n., philosopher
studied by H. P. Grice for his ‘ontological Marxism,’ he began as a “Kantian
Marxist” in epistemology, ethical theory, and philosophy of history, but soon
turned away from Marxism although he continued to accept Marx’s critique of
capitalism toward a theistic philosophy of existence stressing the values of
creativity and “meonic” freedom a
freedom allegedly prior to all being, including that of God. In exile after 2,
Berdyaev appears to have been the first to grasp clearly in the early 0s that
the Marxist view of historical time involves a morally unacceptable devaluing
and instrumentalizing of the historical present including living persons for
the sake of the remote future end of a perfected communist society. Berdyaev
rejects the Marxist position on both Christian and Kantian grounds, as a
violation of the intrinsic value of human persons. He sees the historical order
as marked by inescapable tragedy, and welcomes the “end of history” as an
“overcoming” of objective historical time by subjective “existential” time with
its free, unobjectified creativity. For Berdyaev the “world of objects” physical things, laws of nature, social
institutions, and human roles and relationships
is a pervasive threat to “free spiritual creativity.” Yet such
creativity appears to be subject to inevitable frustration, since its outward
embodiments are always “partial and fragmentary” and no “outward action” can
escape ultimate “tragic failure.” Russian Orthodox traditionalists condemned
Berdyaev for claiming that all creation is a “divine-human process” and for
denying God’s omnipotence, but such Western process theologians as Hartshorne
find Berdyaev’s position highly congenial.
bergmann: g. infamous for
calling H. P. Grice “one of them English futilitarians” -- philosopher, the
youngest member of the Vienna Circle. Born in Vienna, he received his doctorate
in mathematics in 8 from the of Vienna.
Originally influenced by logical positivism, he became a phenomenalist who also
posited mental acts irreducible to sense-data see his The Metaphysics of
Logical Positivism, 4. Although he eventually rejected phenomenalism, his
ontology of material objects remained structurally phenomenalistic. Bergmann’s
world is one of momentary bare i.e. natureless particulars exemplifying
phenomenally simple Berdyaev, Nicolas Bergmann, Gustav 81 81 universals, relational as well as
non-relational. Some of these universals are non-mental, such as color
properties and spatial relations, while others, such as the “intentional
characters” in virtue of which some particulars mental acts intend or represent
the facts that are their “objects,” are mental. Bergmann insisted that the
world is independent of both our experience of it and our thought and discourse
about it: he claimed that the connection of exemplification and even the
propositional connectives and quantifiers are mind-independent. See Meaning and
Existence, 9; Logic and Reality, 4; and Realism: A Critique of Brentano and Meinong,
7. Such extreme realism produced many criticisms of his philosophy that are
only finally addressed in Bergmann’s recently, and posthumously, published
book, New Foundations of Ontology 2, in which he concedes that his atomistic
approach to ontology has inevitable limitations and proposes a way of squaring
this insight with his thoroughgoing realism.
bergson: Philosopher of
central European ancestry born in Paris. The surname literally means, ‘the son
of the mountain,’ -- cited by H. P. Grice in “Personal identity,” philosopher,
the most influential of the first half of the twentieth century. Born in Paris
and educated at the prestigious École Normale Supérieure, he began his teaching
career at Clermont-Ferrand in 4 and was called in 0 to the Collège de France,
where his lectures enjoyed unparalleled success until his retirement in 1.
Ideally placed in la belle époque of prewar Paris, his ideas influenced a broad
spectrum of artistic, literary, social, and political movements. In 8 he
received the Légion d’honneur and was admitted into the Academy. From 2 through 5 he participated in
the League of Nations, presiding over the creation of what was later to become
UNESCO. Forced by crippling arthritis into virtual seclusion during his later
years, Bergson was awarded the Nobel Prize for literature in 8. Initially a
disciple of Spencer, Bergson broke with him after a careful examination of
Spencer’s concept of time and mechanistic positivism. Following a deeply
entrenched tradition in Western thought, Spencer treats time on an analogy with
space as a series of discrete numerical units: instants, seconds, minutes. When
confronted with experience, however
especially with that of our own psychological states such concepts are, Bergson concludes,
patently inadequate. Real duration, unlike clock time, is qualitative, dynamic,
irreversible. It cannot be “spatialized” without being deformed. It gives rise
in us, moreover, to free acts, which, being qualitative and spontaneous, cannot
be predicted. Bergson’s dramatic contrast of real duration and geometrical
space, first developed in Time and Free Will 0, was followed in 6 by the mind
body theory of Matter and Memory. He argues here that the brain is not a locale
for thought but a motor organ that, receiving stimuli from its environment, may
respond with adaptive behavior. To his psychological and metaphysical
distinction between duration and space Bergson adds, in An Introduction to
Metaphysics 3, an important epistemological distinction between intuition and
analysis. Intuition probes the flow of duration in its concreteness; analysis
breaks up duration into static, fragmentary concepts. In Creative Evolution 7,
his best-known work, Bergson argues against both Lamarck and Darwin, urging
that biological evolution is impelled by a vital impetus or élan vital that
drives life to overcome the downward entropic drift of matter. Biological
organisms, unlike dice, must compete and survive as they undergo permutations.
Hence the unresolved dilemma of Darwinism. Either mutations occur one or a few
at a time in which case how can they be “saved up” to constitute new organs? or
they occur all at once in which case one has a “miracle”. Bergson’s vitalism,
popular in literary circles, was not accepted by many scientists or philosophers.
His most general contention, however
that biological evolution is not consistent with or even well served by
a mechanistic philosophy was broadly
appreciated and to many seemed convincing. This aspect of Bergson’s writings
influenced thinkers as diverse as Lloyd Morgan, Alexis Carrel, Sewall Wright,
Pierre Teilhard de Chardin, and A. N. Whitehead. The contrasts in terms of
which Bergson developed his thought duration/space, intuition/ analysis,
life/entropy are replaced in The Two Sources of Morality and Religion 2 by a
new duality, that of the “open” and the “closed.” The Judeo-Christian
tradition, he contends, if it has embraced in its history both the open society
and the closed society, exhibits in its great saints and mystics a profound
opening out of the human spirit toward all humanity. Bergson’s distinction
between the open and the closed society was popularized by Karl Popper in his
The Open Society and Its Enemies. While it has attracted serious criticism,
Bergson’s philosophy has also significantly affected subsequent thinkers.
Novelists as diverse as Bergson, Henri Louis Bergson, Henri Louis 82 82 Nikos Kazantzakis, Marcel Proust, and
William Faulkner; poets as unlike as Charles Péguy, Robert Frost, and Antonio
Machado; and psychologists as dissimilar as Pierre Janet and Jean Piaget were
to profit significantly from his explorations of duration, conceptualization,
and memory. Both existentialism and process philosophy bear the imprint of his
thought.
berkeleyianism: g., -- H. P. Grice
thought he had found in Berkeley a good test for the Austinian code – If
something sounds harsh to Berkeley it sounds harsh. Irish philosopher and
bishop in the Anglican Church of Ireland, one of the three great British
empiricists along with Locke and Hume. He developed novel and influential views
on the visual perception of distance and size, and an idealist metaphysical
system that he defended partly on the seemingly paradoxical ground that it was
the best defense of common sense and safeguard against skepticism. Berkeley
studied at Trinity , Dublin, from which he graduated at nineteen. He was
elected to a fellowship at Trinity in 1707, and did the bulk of his
philosophical writing between that year and 1713. He was made dean of Derry in
1724, following extensive traveling on the Continent; he spent the years 172832
in Rhode Island, waiting in vain for promised Crown funds to establish a in Bermuda. He was made bishop of Cloyne,
Ireland, in 1734, and he remained there as a cleric for nearly the remainder of
his life. Berkeley’s first major publication, the Essay Towards a New Theory of
Vision 1709, is principally a work in the psychology of vision, though it has
important philosophical presuppositions and implications. Berkeley’s theory of
vision became something like the received view on the topic for nearly two
hundred years and is a landmark work in the history of psychology. The work is
devoted to three connected matters: how do we see, or visually estimate, the
distances of objects from ourselves, the situation or place at which objects
are located, and the magnitude of such objects? Earlier views, such as those of
Descartes, Malebranche, and Molyneux, are rejected on the ground that their
answers to the above questions allow that a person can see the distance of an
object without having first learned to correlate visual and other cues. This
was supposedly done by a kind of natural geometry, a computation of the
distance by determining the altitude of a triangle formed by light rays from
the object and the line extending from one retina to the other. On the
contrary, Berkeley holds that it is clear that seeing distance is something one
learns to do through trial and error, mainly by correlating cues that suggest
distance: the distinctness or confusion of the visual appearance; the feelings
received when the eyes turn; and the sensations attending the straining of the
eyes. None of these bears any necessary connection to distance. Berkeley infers
from this account that a person born blind and later given sight would not be
able to tell by sight alone the distances objects were from her, nor tell the
difference between a sphere and a cube. He also argues that in visually
estimating distance, one is really estimating which tangible ideas one would
likely experience if one were to take steps to approach the object. Not that
these tangible ideas are themselves necessarily connected to the visual
appearances. Instead, Berkeley holds that tangible and visual ideas are
entirely heterogeneous, i.e., they are numerically and specifically distinct.
The latter is a philosophical consequence of Berkeley’s theory of vision, which
is sharply at odds with a central doctrine of Locke’s Essay, namely, that some
ideas are common to both sight and touch. Locke’s doctrines also receive a
great deal of attention in the Principles of Human Knowledge 1710. Here
Berkeley considers the doctrine of abstract general ideas, which he finds in
Book III of Locke’s Essay. He argues against such ideas partly on the ground
that we cannot engage in the process of abstraction, partly on the ground that
some abstract ideas are impossible objects, and also on the ground that such
ideas are not needed for either language learning or language use. These
arguments are of fundamental importance for Berkeley, since he thinks that the
doctrine of abstract ideas helps to support metaphysical realism, absolute
space, absolute motion, and absolute time Principles, 5, 100, 11011, as well as
the view that some ideas are common to sight and touch New Theory, 123. All of
these doctrines Berkeley holds to be mistaken, and the first is in direct
conflict with his idealism. Hence, it is important for him to undermine any
support these doctrines might receive from the abstract ideas thesis.
Berkeleyan idealism is the view that the only existing entities are finite and
infinite perceivers each of which is a spirit or mental substance, and entities
that are perceived. Such a thesis implies that ordinary physical objects exist
if and only if they are perceived, something Berkeley encapsulates in the esse
est percipi principle: for all senBerkeley, George Berkeley, George 83 83 sible objects, i.e., objects capable of
being perceived, their being is to be perceived. He gives essentially two
arguments for this thesis. First, he holds that every physical object is just a
collection of sensible qualities, and that every sensible quality is an idea.
So, physical objects are just collections of sensible ideas. No idea can exist
unperceived, something everyone in the period would have granted. Hence, no
physical object can exist unperceived. The second argument is the socalled
master argument of Principles 2224. There Berkeley argues that one cannot
conceive a sensible object existing unperceived, because if one attempts to do
this one must thereby conceive that very object. He concludes from this that no
such object can exist “without the mind,” that is, wholly unperceived. Many of
Berkeley’s opponents would have held instead that a physical object is best
analyzed as a material substratum, in which some sensible qualities inhere. So
Berkeley spends some effort arguing against material substrata or what he
sometimes calls matter. His principal argument is that a sensible quality
cannot inhere in matter, because a sensible quality is an idea, and surely an
idea cannot exist except in a mind. This argument would be decisive if it were
true that each sensible quality is an idea. Unfortunately, Berkeley gives no
argument whatever for this contention in the Principles, and for that reason
Berkeleyan idealism is not there well founded. Nor does the master argument
fare much better, for there Berkeley seems to require a premise asserting that
if an object is conceived, then that object is perceived. Yet such a premise is
highly dubious. Probably Berkeley realized that his case for idealism had not
been successful, and certainly he was stung by the poor reception of the
Principles. His next book, Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous 1713, is
aimed at rectifying these matters. There he argues at length for the thesis
that each sensible quality is an idea. The master argument is repeated, but it
is unnecessary if every sensible quality is an idea. In the Dialogues Berkeley
is also much concerned to combat skepticism and defend common sense. He argues
that representative realism as held by Locke leads to skepticism regarding the
external world and this, Berkeley thinks, helps to support atheism and free
thinking in religion. He also argues, more directly, that representative
realism is false. Such a thesis incorporates the claim that somesensible ideas
represent real qualities in objects, the so-called primary qualities. But
Berkeley argues that a sensible idea can be like nothing but another idea, and
so ideas cannot represent qualities in objects. In this way, Berkeley
eliminates one main support of skepticism, and to that extent helps to support
the commonsensical idea that we gain knowledge of the existence and nature of
ordinary physical objects by means of perception. Berkeley’s positive views in
epistemology are usually interpreted as a version of foundationalism. That is,
he is generally thought to have defended the view that beliefs about currently
perceived ideas are basic beliefs, beliefs that are immediately and
non-inferentially justified or that count as pieces of immediate knowledge, and
that all other justified beliefs in contingent propositions are justified by
being somehow based upon the basic beliefs. Indeed, such a foundationalist
doctrine is often taken to help define empiricism, held in common by Locke,
Berkeley, and Hume. But whatever the merits of such a view as an interpretation
of Locke or Hume, it is not Berkeley’s theory. This is because he allows that
perceivers often have immediate and noninferential justified beliefs, and
knowledge, about physical objects. Hence, Berkeley accepts a version of
foundationalism that allows for basic beliefs quite different from just beliefs
about one’s currently perceived ideas. Indeed, he goes so far as to maintain
that such physical object beliefs are often certain, something neither Locke
nor Hume would accept. In arguing against the existence of matter, Berkeley
also maintains that we literally have no coherent concept of such stuff because
we cannot have any sensible idea of it. Parity of reasoning would seem to
dictate that Berkeley should reject mental substance as well, thereby
threatening his idealism from another quarter. Berkeley is sensitive to this
line of reasoning, and replies that while we have no idea of the self, we do
have some notion of the self, that is, some lessthan-complete concept. He
argues that a person gains some immediate knowledge of the existence and nature
of herself in a reflex act; that is, when she is perceiving something she is
also conscious that something is engaging in this perception, and this is
sufficient for knowledge of that perceiving entity. To complement his idealism,
Berkeley worked out a version of scientific instrumentalism, both in the
Principles and in a later Latin work, De Motu 1721, a doctrine that anticipates
the views of Mach. In the Dialogues he tries to show how his idealism is
consistent with the biblical account of the creation, and consistent as well
with common sense. Berkeley, George Berkeley, George 84 84 Three later works of Berkeley’s gained
him an enormous amount of attention. Alciphron 1734 was written while Berkeley
was in Rhode Island, and is a philosophical defense of Christian doctrine. It
also contains some additional comments on perception, supplementing earlier work
on that topic. The Analyst 1734 contains trenchant criticism of the method of
fluxions in differential calculus, and it set off a flurry of pamphlet replies
to Berkeley’s criticisms, to which Berkeley responded in his A Defense of Free
Thinking in Mathematics. Siris 1744 contains a detailed account of the
medicinal values of tar-water, water boiled with the bark of certain trees.
This book also contains a defense of a sort of corpuscularian philosophy that
seems to be at odds with the idealism elaborated in the earlier works for which
Berkeley is now famous. In the years 170708, the youthful Berkeley kept a
series of notebooks in which he worked out his ideas in philosophy and
mathematics. These books, now known as the Philosophical Commentaries, provide
the student of Berkeley with the rare opportunity to see a great philosopher’s
thought in development. H. P. Grice was
a member of the Oxford Berkeley Society. The Bishop and The Cricketer Agree: It
Does Sound Harsh! When "The Times"
published a note on Grice, anonymous, as obituaries should be, but some suspect
P. F. S.) it went, "H. P. Grice, professional philosopher and amateur
cricketer."Surely P. F. S. may have been involved, since some always
preferred the commuted conjunction: "H. P. Grice, cricketer -- and
philosopher."At one time, to be a 'professional' cricketer was a no-no.At
one time, to be a 'professional' philosopher was a no-no -- witness
Socrates!But you never know.It's TOTALLY different when it comes to
BISHOPS!Grice loved that phrase, "sounds harsh." "The Austinian
in the Bishop."Bishop Berkeley and H. P. Grice -- Two Ways of
Representing: Likeness Or Not.Bishop Berkeley’s views on representation,
broadly construed, relate to H. P. Grice’s views on representation, broadly
construed.In essay, “Berkeley: An Interpretation,” Kenneth Winkler
argues that Bishop Berkeley sees representation as working in one of two
ways.Representation works either in the same way that an expression signifies
an idea (Grice’s non-iconic) or by means of resemblance (Grice’s iconic).But we
need to explore that distinction.This all relates to Bishop Berkeley’s and
Grice’s views on language, their theory of resemblance, and the role that
representation plays in their philosophiesmore widely.It is interesting to consider,
of course, Berkeley’s predecessors (e.g., Descartes, Locke, that Grice revered
in the choice of the title of his compilation of essays, “Studies in THE WAY OF
WORDS,” or WoW for short), Bishop Berkeley’s contemporaries (e.g., William
King, Anthony Collins), and subsequent thinkers (e.g. Hume, Shepherd, and of
course Grice) accepted this distinction – and their connection to the
development of both Bishoop Berkeley’s and Grice’s thought.Some philosophers
connect Bishop Berkeley and Grice to non-canonical figures or those which
defend novel interpretations of Berkeley’s or Grice’s own thought.Which ARE
Bishop Berkeley’s and Grice’s view on the connection between representation and
resemblance?Is Winkler right to attribute two types of representation to Berkeley?
Could Winkler’s observations have a bearing on Grice?Do Bishop Berkeley’s and
Grice’s contemporaries accept the distinction between signification and
representation? (Grice’s favourite example: “A cricket team may do for England
what England cannot do: engage in a game of cricket.”)Grice explores this in
the “Valediction” to his “Way of Words”:“We
might we well advised,” Grice says, “to consider more closely the nature of
representation and its connection with meaning, and to do so in the light of three
perhaps not implausible suppositions.”(1) that representation by means of
verbal formulation is an artificial and noniconic mode of representation.(2)
that to replace an iconic system by a noniconic system will be to introduce a
new and more powerful extension of the original system, one which can do
everything the former system can do and more besides.(3) that every
artificial or noniconic system is based on an antecedent NATURAL iconic
system.Descriptive representation must look back to and in part do the work of
prior iconic representation.That work will consist in the representation of
objects and situations in the world in something like the way in which a team
of North Oxfordshire cricketers may represent, say North Oxfordshire. The
cricketers do on behalf of North Oxfordshire something that North Oxfordshire
cannot do for itself, namely engage in a game of cricket.“Similarly, our
representations (initially iconic but also noniconic) enable objects and
situations in the world to do something which objects and situations cannot do
for themselves, namely govern our actions and behaviour.”Etc.Grice loved
to quote the Bishop on this or that ‘sounding harsh.’ “Surely, the Bishop would
agree with me that it sounds harsh to say that Smith’s brain’s s being in such and such a
state at noon is a case of judging something to be true on insufficient evidence."We
hope neither will agree THIS sounds harsh, either, as North-Oxfordshire
engaging in a game of cricket does not really, either.
berlin: “If Berlin and I have
something in common is a tutor!” – H. P. Grice. Berlin: I. Russian-born philosopher
and historian of ideas. He is widely acclaimed for his doctrine of radical
objective pluralism; his writings on liberty; his modification, refinement, and
defense of traditional liberalism against the totalitarian doctrines of the
twentieth century not least Marxism-Leninism; and his brilliant and
illuminating studies in the history of ideas from Machiavelli and Vico to Marx
and Sorel. A founding father with Austin, Ayer, and others of Oxford philosophy
in the 0s, he published several influential papers in its general spirit, but,
without abandoning its empirical approach, he came increasingly to dissent from
what seemed to him its unduly barren, doctrinaire, and truthdenying tendencies.
From the 0s onward he broke away to devote himself principally to social and
political philosophy and to the study of general ideas. His two most important
contributions in social and political theory, brought together with two other valuable
essays in Four Essays on Liberty 9, are “Historical Inevitability” 4 and his 8
inaugural lecture as Chichele Professor of Social and Political Theory at
Oxford, “Two Concepts of Liberty.” The first is a bold and decisive attack on
historical determinism and moral relativism and subjectivism and a ringing
endorsement of the role of free will and responsibility in human history. The
second contains Berlin’s enormously influential attempt to distinguish clearly
between “negative” and “positive” liberty. Negative liberty, foreshadowed by
such thinkers as J. S. Mill, Constant, and above all Herzen, consists in making
minimal assumptions about the ultimate nature and needs of the subject, in
ensuring a minimum of external interference by authority of any provenance, and
in leaving open as large a field for free individual choice as is consonant
with a minimum of social organization and order. Positive liberty, associated
with monist and voluntarist thinkers of all kinds, not least Hegel, the G.
Idealists, and their historical progeny, begins with the notion of self-mastery
and proceeds to make dogmatic and far-reaching metaphysical assumptions about
the essence of the subject. It then deduces from these the proper paths to
freedom, and, finally, seeks to drive flesh-and-blood individuals down these
preordained paths, whether they wish it or not, within the framework of a
tight-knit centralized state under the irrefragable rule of rational experts,
thus perverting what begins as a legitimate human ideal, i.e. positive
self-direction and self-mastery, into a tyranny. “Two Concepts of Liberty” also
sets out to disentangle liberty in either of these senses from other ends, such
as the craving for recognition, the need to belong, or human solidarity,
fraternity, or equality. Berlin’s work in the history of ideas is of a piece
with his other writings. Vico and Herder 6 presents the emergence of that
historicism and pluralism which shook the two-thousand-yearold monist
rationalist faith in a unified body of truth regarding all questions of fact
and principle in all fields of human knowledge. From this profound intellectual
overturn Berlin traces in subsequent volumes of essays, such as Against the
Current 9, The Crooked Timber of Humanity 0, and The Sense of Reality 6, the
growth of some of the principal intellectual movements that mark our era, among
them nationalism, fascism, relativism, subjectivism, nihilism, voluntarism, and
existentialism. He also presents with persuasiveness and clarity that peculiar
objective pluralism which he identified and made his own. There is an
irreducible plurality of objective human values, many of which are incompatible
with one another; hence the ineluctable need for absolute choices by
individuals and groups, a need that confers supreme value upon, and forms one
of the major justifications of, his conception of negative liberty; Berlin,
Isaiah Berlin, Isaiah 85 85 hence, too,
his insistence that utopia, namely a world where all valid human ends and
objective values are simultaneously realized in an ultimate synthesis, is a
conceptual impossibility. While not himself founder of any definable school or
movement, Berlin’s influence as a philosopher and as a human being has been
immense, not least on a variety of distinguished thinkers such as Stuart
Hampshire, Charles Taylor, Bernard Williams, Richard Wollheim, Gerry Cohen,
Steven Lukes, David Pears, and many others. His general intellectual and moral
impact on the life of the twentieth century as writer, diplomat, patron of
music and the arts, international academic elder statesman, loved and trusted
friend to the great and the humble, and dazzling lecturer, conversationalist,
and animateur des idées, will furnish inexhaustible material to future
historians.
bernardus: chartrensis. of Chartres,,
philosopher. He was first a teacher 111419 and later chancellor 116 of the
cathedral school at Chartres, which was then an active center of learning in
the liberal arts and philosophy. Bernard himself was renowned as a grammarian,
i.e., as an expositor of difficult texts, and as a teacher of Plato. None of
his works has survived whole, and only three fragments are preserved in works
by others. He is now best known for an image recorded both by his student, John
of Salisbury, and by William of Conches. In Bernard’s image, he and all his
medieval contemporaries were in relation to the ancient authors like “dwarfs
sitting on the shoulders of giants.” John of Salisbury takes the image to mean
both that the medievals could see more and further than the ancients, and that
they could do so only because they had been lifted up by such powerful
predecessors.
bernardus: of Clairvaux,
Saint – Grice’s personal saint, seeing that St. John’s was originally a
Cistercian monastery almost burned by Henry VIII. Cistercian monk, mystic, and
religious leader. He is most noted for his doctrine of Christian humility and
his depiction of the mystical experience, which exerted considerable influence
on later Christian mystics. Educated in France, he entered the monastery at
Cîteaux in 1112, and three years later founded a daughter monastery at
Clairvaux. According to Bernard, honest self-knowledge should reveal the extent
to which we fail to be what we should be in the eyes of God. That selfknowledge
should lead us to curb our pride and so become more humble. Humility is
necessary for spiritual purification, which in turn is necessary for
contemplation of God, the highest form of which is union with God. Consistent
with orthodox Christian doctrine, Bernard maintains that mystical union does
not entail identity. One does not become God; rather, one’s will and God’s will
come into complete conformity.
bernoulli’s theorem: studied by Grice
in his “Probability, Desirability, Credibility” -- also called the weak law of
large numbers, the principle that if a series of trials is repeated n times
where a there are two possible outcomes, 0 and 1, on each trial, b the
probability p of 0 is the same on each trial, and c this probability is
independent of the outcome of other trials, then, for arbitrary positive e, as
the number n of trials is increased, the probability that the absolute value
Kr/n pK of the difference between the
relative frequency r/n of 0’s in the n trials and p is less than e approaches
1. The first proof of this theorem was given by Jakob Bernoulli in Part IV of
his posthumously published Ars Conjectandi of 1713. Simplifications were later
constructed and his result has been generalized in a series of “weak laws of
large numbers.” Although Bernoulli’s theorem derives a conclusion about the
probability of the relative frequency r/n of 0’s for large n of trials given
the value of p, in Ars Conjectandi and correspondence with Leibniz, Bernoulli
thought it could be used to reason from information about r/n to the value of p
when the latter is unknown. Speculation persists as to whether Bernoulli
anticipated the inverse inference of Bayes, the confidence interval estimation
of Peirce, J. Neyman, and E. S. Pearson, or the fiducial argument of R. A.
Fisher.
Bertrand’s box
paradox:
studied by Grice in his “Probability, Desirability, Credibility” -- a puzzle
concerning conditional probability. Imagine three boxes with two drawers
apiece. Each drawer of the first box contains a gold medal. Each drawer of the
second contains a silver medal. One drawer of the third contains a gold medal,
and the other a silver medal. At random, a box is selected and one of its
drawers is opened. If a gold medal appears, what is the probability that the
third box was selected? The probability seems to be ½, because the box is
either the first or the third, and they seem equally probable. But a gold medal
is less probable from the third box than from the first, Bernard of Chartres
Bertrand’s box paradox 86 86 so the
third box is actually less probable than the first. By Bayes’s theorem its
probability is 1 /3. Joseph Bertrand, a
mathematician, published the paradox in Calcul des probabilités Calculus
of Probabilities, 9.
Bertrand’s paradox: an inconsistency
arising from the classical definition of an event’s probability as the number
of favorable cases divided by the number of possible cases. Given a circle, a
chord is selected at random. What is the probability that the chord is longer
than a side of an equilateral triangle inscribed in the circle? The event has
these characterizations: 1 the apex angle of an isosceles triangle inscribed in
the circle and having the chord as a leg is less than 60°, 2 the chord
intersects the diameter perpendicular to it less than ½ a radius from the
circle’s center, and 3 the chord’s midpoint lies within a circle concentric
with the original and of ¼ its area. The definition thus suggests that the
event’s probability is 1 /3, 1 /2, and also ¼. Joseph Bertrand, a mathematician, published the paradox in
Calcul des probabilités 9.
Beth’s definability
theorem:
Grice loved an emplicit definition. a theorem for first-order logic. A theory
defines a term t implicitly if and only if an explicit definition of the term,
on the basis of the other primitive concepts, is entailed by the theory. A
theory defines a term implicitly if any two models of the theory with the same
domain and the same extension for the other primitive terms are identical,
i.e., also have the same extension for the term. An explicit definition of a
term is a sentence that states necessary and sufficient conditions for the
term’s applicability. Beth’s theorem was implicit in a method to show
independence of a term that was first used by the logician Alessandro Padoa. Padoa suggested,
in 0, that independence of a primitive algebraic term from the other terms
occurring in a set of axioms can be established by two true interpretations of
the axioms that differ only in the interpretation of the term whose
independence has to be proven. He claimed, without proof, that the existence of
two such models is not only sufficient for, but also implied by, independence.
Tarski first gave a proof of Beth’s theorem in 6 for the logic of the Principia
Mathematica of Whitehead and Russell, but the result was only obtained for
first-order logic in 3 by E. Beth. In modern expositions Beth’s theorem is a
direct implication of Craig’s interpolation theorem. In a variation on Padoa’s
method, Karel de Bouvère described in 9 a one-model method to show
indefinability: if the set of logical consequences of a theory formulated in
terms of the remaining vocabulary cannot be extended to a model of the full
theory, a term is not explicitly definable in terms of the remaining
vocabulary. In the philosophy of science literature this is called a failure of
Ramsey-eliminability of the term.
bi-conditional: As Grice notes,
‘if’ is the only non-commutative operator; so trust Mill to make it
commutative, “if p, q, then if q, p.” Cited by Strawson after ‘if,’ but
dismissed by Grice in his list of
‘formal devices’ as ‘too obvious.’ --
the logical operator, usually written with a triple-bar sign S or a
doubleheaded arrow Q, used to indicate that two propositions have the same
truth-value: that either both are true or else both are false. The term also
designates a proposition having this sign, or a natural language expression of
it, as its main connective; e.g., P if and only if Q. The truth table for the
biconditional is The biconditional is so called because its application is
logically equivalent to the conjunction
‘P-conditional-Q-and-Q-conditional-P’.
According to Pears, and rightly, too, ‘if’ conversationally implicates
‘iff.’
black box – used by Grice in
his method in philosophical psychology -- a hypothetical unit specified only by
functional role, in order to explain some effect or behavior. The term may
refer to a single entity with an unknown structure, or unknown internal
organization, which realizes some known function, or to any one of a system of
such entities, whose organization and functions are inferred from the behavior
of an organism or entity of which they are constituents. Within behaviorism and
classical learning theory, the basic functions were taken to be generalized
mechanisms governing the relationship of stimulus to response, including
reinforcement, inhibition, extinction, and arousal. The organism was treated as
a black box realizing these functions. Within cybernetics, though there are no
simple inputoutput rules describing the organism, there is an emphasis on
functional organization and feedback in controlling behavior. The components
within a cybernetic system are treated as black boxes. In both cases, the
details of underlying structure, mechanism, and dynamics are either unknown or
regarded as unimportant.
Blackburn’s skull. Blackburn's
"one-off predicament" of communicating without a shared language
illustrates how Grice's theory can be applied to iconic signals such as the
drawing of a skull to wam of danger. See his Spreading the Word. III. 112.
blindsight: studied by Grice
and Warnock, “Visa.” -- a residual visual capacity resulting from lesions in
certain areas of the brain the striate cortex, area 17. Under routine clinical
testing, persons suffering such lesions appear to be densely blind in particular
regions of the visual field. Researchers have long recognized that, in
primates, comparable lesions do not result in similar deficits. It has seemed
unlikely that this disparity could be due to differences in brain function,
however. And, indeed, when human subjects are tested in the way non-human
subjects are tested, the disparity vanishes. Although subjects report that they
can detect nothing in the blind field, when required to “guess” at properties
of items situated there, they perform remarkably well. They seem to “know” the
contents of the blind field while remaining unaware that they know, often
expressing astonishment on being told the results of testing in the blind
field.
bloch: e., philosopher
studied by H. P. Grice for his “ontological marxism.” influenced by Marxism,
his views went beyond Marxism as he matured. He fled G.y in the 0s, but
returned after World War II to a professorship in East G.y, where his
increasingly unorthodox ideas were eventually censured by the Communist authorities,
forcing a move to West G.y in the 0s. His major work, The Principle of Hope
459, is influenced by G. idealism, Jewish mysticism, Neoplatonism, utopianism,
and numerous other sources besides Marxism. Humans are essentially unfinished,
moved by a cosmic impulse, “hope,” a tendency in them to strive for the
as-yet-unrealized, which manifests itself as utopia, or vision of future
possibilities. Despite his atheism, Bloch wished to retrieve the sense of
self-transcending that he saw in the religious and mythical traditions of
humankind. His ideas have consequently influenced theology as well as
philosophy, e.g. the “theology of hope” of Jurgen Moltmann.
blondel: m. cf. Hampshire,
“Thought and action,” philosopher who discovered the deist background of human
action. In his main work, Action 3, 2d rev. ed. 0, Blondel held that action is
part of the very nature of human beings and as such becomes an object of
philosophy; through philosophy, action should find its meaning, i.e. realize
itself rationally. An appropriate phenomenology of action through
phenomenological description uncovers the phenomenal level of action but points
beyond it. Such a supraphenomenal sense of action provides it a metaphysical
status. This phenomenology of action rests on an immanent dialectics of action:
a gap between the aim of the action and its realization. This gap, while
dissatisfying to the actor, also drives him toward new activities. The only
immanent solution of this dialectics and its consequences is a transcendent
one. We have to realize that we, like other humans, cannot grasp our own
activities and must accept our limitations and our finitude as well as the
insufficiency of our philosophy, which is now understood as a philosophy of
insufficiency and points toward the existence of the supernatural element in
every human act, namely God. Human activity is the outcome of divine grace.
Through action bit Blondel, Maurice 90
90 one touches the existence of God, something not possible by logical
argumentation. In the later phase of his development Blondel deserted his early
“anti-intellectualism” and stressed the close relation between thought and
action, now understood as inseparable and mutually interrelated. He came to see
philosophy as a rational instrument of understanding one’s actions as well as
one’s insufficiency.
bodin: j., Discussed by
H. P. Grice in his exploration on legal versus moral right. -- philosopher
whose philosophy centers on the concept of sovereignty. His Six livres de la
république 1577 defines a state as constituted by common public interests,
families, and the sovereign. The sovereign is the lawgiver, who stands beyond
the absolute rights he possesses; he must, however, follow the law of God,
natural law, and the constitution. The ideal state was for Bodin a monarchy
that uses aristocratic and democratic structures of government for the sake of
the common good. In order to achieve a broader empirical picture of politics
Bodin used historical comparisons. This is methodologically reflected in his
Methodus ad facilem historiarum cognitionem 1566. Bodin was clearly a theorist
of absolutism. As a member of the Politique group he played a practical role in
emancipating the state from the church. His thinking was influenced by his
experience of civil war. In his Heptaplomeres posthumous he pleaded for
tolerance with respect to all religions, including Islam and Judaism. As a
public prosecutor, however, he wrote a manual for judges in witchcraft trials
De la démonomanie des sorciers, 1580. By stressing the peacemaking role of a
strong state Bodin was a forerunner of Hobbes.
boehme: j. Cited by Grice
in “From Genesis to Revelations” -- protestant speculative mystic. Influenced
especially by Paracelsus, Boehme received little formal education, but was
successful enough as a shoemaker to devote himself to his writing, explicating
his religious experiences. He published little in his lifetime, though enough
to attract charges of heresy from local clergy. He did gather followers, and
his works were published after his death. His writings are elaborately symbolic
rather than argumentative, but respond deeply to fundamental problems in the
Christian worldview. He holds that the Godhead, omnipotent will, is as nothing
to us, since we can in no way grasp it. The Mysterium Magnum, the ideal world,
is conceived in God’s mind through an impulse to self-revelation. The actual
world, separate from God, is created through His will, and seeks to return to
the peace of the Godhead. The world is good, as God is, but its goodness falls
away, and is restored at the end of history, though not entirely, for some
souls are damned eternally. Human beings enjoy free will, and create themselves
through rebirth in faith. The Fall is necessary for the selfknowledge gained in
recovery from it. Recognition of one’s hidden, free self is a recognition of
God manifested in the world, so that human salvation completes God’s act of
self-revelation. It is also a recognition of evil rooted in the blind will
underlying all individual existence, without which there would be nothing
except the Godhead. Boehme’s works influenced Hegel and the later
Schelling.
No comments:
Post a Comment