determinatum: There’s the determinatum and there’s the indeeterminatum –
“And then there’s ‘indeterminacy.”” “A determinatum is like a definitum, in
that a ‘term’ is like the ‘end’ – “Thus, I am a Mercian, from Harborne.” “The
Mericans were thus called because the lived at the end of England.” “Popper,
who doesn’t know the first thing about this, prefers, ‘demarcatum’, which is
cognate with “mercian.’” Grice was always cautious and self-apologetic. “I’m
not expecting that you’ll find this to be a complete theory of implication, but
that was not my goal, and the endeavour should be left for another day, etc.”
But consider the detail into which he, like any other philosopher before, went
when it came to what he called the ‘catalyst’ tests or ideas or tests or ideas
for the implicaturum. In “Causal Theory” there are FOUR ideas. It is good to
revise the treatment in “Causal.” He proposes two ideas with the first two
examples and two further ideas with the two further examples. Surely his goal
is to apply the FOUR ideas to his own example of the pillar box. Grice notes
re: “You have not ceased eating iron” – the cxample is “a stock case of what is
sometimes called " prcsupposition " and it is often held that here
1he truth of what is irnplicd is a necessary condition of the original
statement's beirrg cither true or false.” So the first catalyst in the first
published version concerns the value, or satisfactory value. This will be
retained and sub-grouped in Essay II. “It is often held” Implicture: but often
not, and trust me I won’t. “that here the truth of what is implied [implicated
in the negative, entailed in the affirmative] is a necessary condition of the
original statement's being either true or false.” So the first catalyst in the
first published version concerns the value, or satisfactory value. This will be
retained and sub-grouped in Essay II. “This might be disputed, but it is at least
arguable that it is so, and its being arguable might be enough to distinguish this
type of case from others.” So he is working on a ‘distinctive feature’ model.
And ‘feature’ is exactly the expression he uses in Essay II. He is looking for
‘distinctive features’ for this or that implication. When phonologists speak of
‘distinctive feature’ they are being philosophical or semioticians.“I shall
however for convenience assume that the common view mentioned is correct.”“This
consideration clearly distinguishes “you have not ceased eating iron” from [a
case of a conventional implicaturum] “poor BUT honest.”“Even if the implied
proposition were false, i.e. if there were no reason in the world to contrast
poverty with honesty either in general or in her case, the original statement
COULD still be false.” “She [is] poor
but she [is] honest” would be false if for example she were rich and dishonest.”“One
might perhaps be less comfortable about assenting to its TRUTH if the implied
contrast did not in fact obtain; but the possibility of falsity is enough for
the immediate purpose.”“My next experiment [test, litmus idea – that he’ll
apply as one of the criteria to provide distinctive features for this or that implicaturum,
with a view to identify the nature of the animal that a conversational implicaturum
is] on these examples is to ask what it is in each case which could properly be
said to be the vehicle of implication (to do the implying).”In Essay II, since
he elaborates this at an earlier stage than when he is listing the distinctive
features, he does not deal much. It is understood that in Essay II by the time
he is listing the distinctive features, the vehicle is the UTTERER. But back in
“Causal,” he notes: “There are AT LEAST FOUR candidates, not necessarily
mutually exclusive.”“Supposing someone to have ‘uttered’ one or other of [the] sample
sentences, we may ask whether the vehicle of implication would be (FIRST) WHAT
the emissor communicated (or asserted or stated or explicitly conveyed), or
(SECOND) the emissor himself ("Surely you’re not implying that ….’ ) or (THIRD) the
utterance (FOURTH) his communicating, or
explicitly conveying that (or again his explicitly conveying that in that way);
or possibly some plurality of these items.”“As regards the first option for the
vehicle, ‘what the emissor has explicitly conveyed,’ Grice takes it that “You
have not ceased eating iron” and “Poor but honest” may differ.It seems correct
for Grice to say in the case of “eating iron” that indeed it is the case that
it is what he emissor explicitly conveys which implies that Smith has been
eating iron.On the other hand, Grice feels it would be ‘incorrect,’ or
improper, or bad, or unnatural or artificial, to say in the case of “poor but
honest” that it is the case. Rather it is NOT the case that it is WHAT the emissor explicitly conveys
which implies that there is a contrast between, e. g., honesty and poverty.”“A sub-test
on which Grice would rely is the following.If accepting that the conventional implicaturum
holds (contrast between honesty and poverty) involves the emissor in accepting
an hypothetical or conditional ‘if p, q,’ where 'p’ represents the original
statement (“She [is] poor and she [is] honest) and 'q' represents what is
implied (“There is a contrast between honesty and poverty”), it is the case
that it is what the emissor explicitly conveys which is a (or the) vehicle of
implication. If that chain of acceptances does not hold, it is not. To apply
this rule to the “eat iron” and “poor but honest”, if the emissor accepts the
implication alleged to hold in the case of “eat iron”, I should feel COMPELLED
(forced, by the force of entailment) to accept the conditional or hypothetical
"If you have not ceased eating iron, you may have never started.”[In
“Causal,” Grice has yet not stressed the asymmetry between the affirmative and
the negative in alleged cases of presupposition. When, due to the success of
his implicaturum, he defines the presuppositum as a form of implicaturum, he
does stress the asymmetry: the entailment holds for the affirmative, and the implicaturum
for the negative). On the other hand, when it comes to a CONVENTIONAL implicaturum
(“poor but honest”) if the emissor accepted the alleged implication in the case
of “poor but honest”, I should NOT feel compelled to accept the conditional or
hypothetical "If she was poor but honest, there is some contrast between
poverty and honesty, or between her poverty and her honesty." Which would
yield that in the presuppositum case, we have what is explicitly conveyed as a
vehicle, but not in the case of the conventional implicaturum.The rest of the
candidates (Grice lists four and allows for a combination) can be dealt with
more cursorily.As regards OPTION II (second):Grice should be inclined to say
with regard to both “eat iron” and “poor but honest” that the emissor could be
said to have implied whatever it is that is irnplied.As regards Option III
(third: the utterance): In the case of “poor but honest” it seems fairly clear
that the utterance could be said, if metabolically, and animistically, to
‘imply’ a contrast.It is much less clear whether in the case of “eat iron” the
utterance could be said to ‘imply’ that Smith has been eating iron.As for
option IV, in neither case would it be evidently appropriate (correct, natural)
to speak of the emissor’s explicitly conveying that, or of his explicitly
conveying that in that way, as ‘implying’ what is implied. A third catalyst
idea with which Grice wish to assail my two examples is really a TWIN idea, or
catalyst, or test [That’s interesting – two sides of the same coin] that of the
detachability or cancellability of the implication. Consider “eat iron.”One
cannot find an alternative utterance which could be used to assert explicitly
just what the utterance “Smith has not ceased from eating iron" might be
used to convey explicitly, such that when this alternative utterance is used
the implication that Smith never started eating iron is absent. Any way of (or
any utterance uttered with a view to) conveying explicitly what is explicitly
conveyed in (1) involves the implication in question. Grice expresses this fact
– which he mentioned in seminars, but this is the first ‘popularisation’ -- by
saying that in the case of (l) the implication is NOT detachable FROM what is
asserted (or simpliciter, is not detachable). Furthermore, and here comes the
twin of CANCELLABILITY: one cannot take any form of words for which both what
is asserted and what is implied is the same as for (l), AND THEN ADD a further
clause withholding commitment from what would otherwise be implied, with the
idea of ANNULLING THE IMPLICATURUM *without* ANNULLING annulling the
EXPLICITUM. One cannot intelligibly say
" Smith has left off beating his wife but I do not mean to imply that he
has been beating her." But one surely can intelligibly say, “You have not
ceased eating iron because you never started.”While Grice uses “Smith,” the
sophisma (or Griceisma) was meant in the second person, to test the tutee’s
intelligence (“Have you stopped beating your dog?”). The point is that the
tutee will be offended – whereas he shouldn’t, and answer, “I never started,
and I never will.”Grice expresses this fact by saying that in the case of ‘eat
iron’ the implication is not cancellable or annullable (without cancelling or
annulling the assertion). If we turn to “poor but honest” we find, Grice thinks,
that there is quite a strong case for saying that here the implication IS
detachable. Therc sccms quite a good case for maintaining that if, instead of
saying " She is poor but she is honcst " I were to say, alla Frege,
without any shade, " She is poor AND she is honcst", I would assert
just what I would havc asscrtcct ii I had used thc original senterrce; but
there would now be no irnplication of a contrast between e.g', povery and
honesty. Of course, this is not a philosophical example, and it would be good
to revise what Frege thought about ‘aber.’ By the time Grice is lecturing
“Causal Theory” he had lectured for the Logic Paper for Strawson before the
war, so Whitehead and Russell are in the air.Surely in Anglo-Saxon, the contrast
is maintained, since ‘and’ means ‘versus.’“She is poor contra her being
honest.”Oddly, the same contrariety is present in Deutsche, that Frege speaks,
with ‘UND.”It’s different with Roman “et.” While Grecian ‘kai,’ even Plato
thought barbaric!The etymology of ‘by-out’ yields ‘but.’So Grice is thinking
that he can have a NEUTRAL conjoining – but ‘and’ has this echo of contrariety,
which is still present in ‘an-swer, i. e. and-swear, to contradict. Perhaps a
better neutral version would be. Let’s start with the past version and then the
present tense version.“She was pooo-ooor, she was honest, and her parents were
the same, till she met a city feller, and she lost her honest name.”In terms of
the concepts CHOSEN, the emissor wants to start the ditty with pointing to the
fact that she is poor – this is followed by stating that she is honest. There’s
something suspicious about that.I’m sure a lady may feel offended without the
‘and’ OR ‘but’ – just the mere ‘succession’ or conjoining of ‘poor’ as
pre-ceding the immediate ‘honest’ ‘triggers’ an element of contrast. The
present tense seems similar: “She is poooor, she is honest, and her parents are
the same, but she’ll meet a city feller, and she’ll lose her honest name.”The
question whether, in thre case of ‘poor but honest,’ the implication is cancellable,
is slightly more cornplex, which shouldn’t if the catalysts are thought of as
twins.There is a way in which we may say that it is not cancellable, or
annullable.Imagine a Tommy marching and
screaming: “She is poor but she is honest,”“HALT!” the sargent shouts.The Tommy
catches the implicaturum:“though of course, sir, I do not mean to imply, sir, that
there is any contrast, sir, between her poverty, sir, and her honesty, sir.”As
Grice notes, this would be a puzzling and eccentric thing for a Tommy to engage
in.And though the sargent might wish to quarrel with the tommy (Atkins – Tommy
Atkins is the name”), an Oxonian philosopher should NOT go so far as to say
that the tommy’s utterance is unintelligible – or as Vitters would say,
‘nunsense.’The sargent should rather suppose, or his lieutenant, since he knows
more, that private Tommy Atkins has adopted a “most pecooliar” way of conveying
the news that she was poor and honest.The sargent’s argument to the lieu-tenant:“Atkins
says he means no disrespect, sir, but surely, sir, just conjoining poverty and
honesty like that makes one wonder.”“Vitters: this is a Cockney song! You’re
reading too much into it!”“Cockney? And why the citty feller, then – aren’t
Cockneys citty fellers. I would rather, sir, think it is what Sharp would call
a ‘sharp’ folk, sir, song, sir.’ The fourth and last test Grice imposes on his
examples is to ask whether we would be inclined to regard the fact that the
appropriate (or corresponding, since they are hardly appropriate – either of
them! – Grice changes the tune as many Oxford philosophers of ordinary language
do when some female joins the Union) implication is present as being a matter
of the, if we may be metabolic and animistic, ‘meaning’ of some particular word
or phrase occurring in the sentences in question. Grice is aware and thus
grants that this may not be always a very clear or easy question to answer.Nevertheless,
Grice risks the assertion that we would be fairly happy and contented to say
that, as regards ‘poor but honest,’ the fact that the implication obtains is a
matter of the ‘meaning’ of 'but ' – i. e. what Oxonians usually mean when they
‘but.’So far as “he has not ceased from…’ is concerned we should have at least
some inclination to say that the presence of the implication is a matter of
the, metabolically, ‘meaning’ of some of the words in the sentence, but we
should be in some difficulty when it came to specifying precisely which this
word, or words are, of which this is true. Well, it’s semantics. Why did Roman
think that it was a good thing to create a lexeme, ‘cease.’“Cease” means
“stop,” or ‘leave off.”It is not a natural verb, like ‘eat.’A rational creature
felt the need to have this concept: ‘stop,’ ‘leave off,’ ‘cease.’The
communication-function it serves is to indicate that SOMETHING has been taken
place, and then this is no longer the case.“The fire ceased,” one caveman said
to his wife.The wife snaps back – this is the Iron Age:“Have you ceased eating
iron, by the way, daa:ling?”“I never started!”So it’s the ‘cease’ locution that
does the trick – or equivalents, i.e. communication devices by which this or
that emissor explicitly convey more or less the same thing: a halting of some
activity.Surely the implication has nothing to do with the ‘beat’ and the
‘wife.’After third example (‘beautiful handwriting) introduced, Grice goes back
to IDEA OR TEST No. 1 (the truth-value thing). Grice notes that it is plain
that there is no case at all for regarding the truth of what is implied here (“Strawson
is hopeless at philosophy”) as a pre-condition of the truth or falsity of what
the tutor has asserted.A denial of the truth of what is implied would have no
bearing at all on whether what I have asserted is true or false. So ‘beautiful
handwring’ is much closer to ‘poor but honest’ than ‘cease eating iron’ in this
respect. Next, as for the vehicle we have the at least four options and
possible combinations.The emissor, the tutor, could certainly be said to have
implied that Strawson is hopeless (provided that this is what the tutor
intended to ‘get across’) and the emissor’s, the tutor’s explicitly saying that
(at any rate the emissor’s saying that and no more) is also certainly a vehicle
of implication. On the other hand the emissor’s words and what the emissor
explicitly conveys are, Grice thinks, not naturally here characterised as the
‘vehicle’ of implication. “Beautiful handwriting” thus differs from BOTH “don’t
cease eating iron” and “poor but honest” – so the idea is to have a table alla
distinctive features, with YES/NO questions answered for each of the four
implication, and the answers they get.As for the third twin, the result is as
expected: The implication is cancellable but not detachable. And it looks as if
Grice created the examples JUST to exemplify those criteria.If the tutor adds, 'I
do not of course mean to imply that Strawson is no good at philosophy” the
whole utterance is intelligible and linguistically impeccable, even though it
may be extraordinary tutorial behaviour – at the other place, not Oxford --.The
tutor can no longer be said to have, or be made responsible for having implied
that Strawson was no good, even though perhaps that is what Grice’s colleagues
might conclude to be the case if Grice had nothing else to say. The implication
is not however, detachable.Any other way of making, in the same context of
utterance, just the assertion I have made would involve the same implication.“His
calligraphy is splendid and he is on time.”“Calligraphy splendid,” Ryle
objected. “That’s slightly oxymoronic, Grice – ‘kallos agathos’”Finally, for
TEST No. 4, ‘meaning’ of expression? The fact that the implication holds is surely
NOT a matter of any particular word or phrase within the sentence which I have
uttered.It is just the whole sentence. Had he gone tacit and say,“Beautiful
handwriting!”Rather than“He has beautiful handwriting.”The implication SEEMS to
be a matter of two particular words: the handwriting word, viz. ‘handwriting.’
And the ‘beautiful’ word, i. e. ‘beautiful.’Any lexeme expressing same concept,
‘Calligraphy unique!’would do the trick because this is damn by faint praise,
or suggestio falsi, suppressio veri. So in this respect “Beautiful handwring”
is certainly different from “Poor but honest” and, possibly different from
“Don’t cease to eat iron!”One obvious fact should be mentioned before one
passes to the fourth example (“kitchen or bedroom”).This case of implication is
unlike the others in that the utterance of the sentence "Strawson has
beautiful handwriting" does not really STANDARDLY involve the implication
here attributed to it (but cf. “We should have lunch together sometime” meaning
“Get lost” – as Grice said, “At Oxford, that’s the standard – that’s what the
‘expression’ “means”); it requires a special context (that it should be uttered
at Collections) to attach the implication to its utterance. More generally: it
requires a special scenario (one should avoid the structuralist Derrideian
‘context’ cf. Grice, “The general theory of context”). If back in the house,
Mrs. Grice asks, “He has beautiful handwriting,” while not at Collections, the implicaturum
would hold. Similarly at the “Lamb and Flag,” or “Bird and Baby.”But one gets
Grice’s point. The scenario is one where Strawson is being assessed or
evaluated AS A PHILOSOPHER. Spinoza’s handwriting was, Stuart Hampshire said,
“terrible – which made me wonder at first whether I should actually waste my
time with him.”After fourth and last example is introduced (“kitchen or
bedroom”): in the case of the Test No. I (at least four possible vehicles) one can
produce a strong argument in favour of holding that the fulfllment of the
implication of the speaker's ignorance (or that he is introducing “or” on
grounds other than Whitehead’s and Russell’s truth-functional ones) is not a
precaution (or precondition) of the truth or falsity of the disjunctive
statement. Suppose that the emissor KNOWS that his wife IS in the KITCHEN, that
the house has only two rooms, and no passages. Even though the utterer knows that
his wife is in the kitchen (as per given), the utterer can certainly still say
truly (or rather truthfully) "She is IN THE HOUSE.”SCENARIOA: Where is
your wife? ii. Where in your house is your wife?B: i. In the kitchen. ii. In
the bedroom. iiia. She’s in the house, don’t worry – she’s in the house, last
time I checked. iii. In the HOUSE (but inappropriate if mentioned in the
question – unless answered: She’s not. iv. In the kitchen or in the bedroom (if
it is common ground that the house only has two rooms there are more options)
vi. v. I’m a bachelor. vi. If she’s not
in the bedroom, she is in the kitchen. vii. If she’s not in the kitchen, she’s
in the bedroom. viii. Verbose but informative: “If she’s not in the bedroom
she’s in the kitchen, and she’s not in the kitchen” Or consider By uttering
“She is in the house,” the utterer is answering in a way that he is merely not
being as informative as he could bc if need arose. But the true proposition [cf. ‘propositional
complex’] that his wife is IN THE HOUSE together with the true proposition that
‘THE HOUSE’ consists entirely of a ‘kitchen’ and a ‘bedroom,’ ENTAIL or yield
the proposition that his wife is in the kitchen or in the bedroom. But IF to express
the proposition p (“My wife is in the house, that much I can tell”) in certain
circumstances (a house consisting entirely of a kitchen and a bedroom – an
outback bathroom which actually belongs to the neighbour – cf. Blenheim) would
be to speak truly, and p (“My wife is, do not worry, in the house”) togelher with
another true proposition – assumed to be common ground, that the house consists
entirely of a kitchen and a bedroom -- entails q (“My wife is in the kitchen OR
in the bedroom”), surely to express what is entailed (“My wife is in the
kitchen or in the bedroom”) in the same circvmstances must be, has to be to
speak truly. So we have to take it that
the disjunctive statement – “kitchen or bedroom” -- does not fail to be TRUE or
FALSE if the implied ignorance (or the implied consideration that the utterer
is uttering ‘or’ on grounds other than the truth-functional ones that
‘introduce’ “or” for Gentzen) is in fact not realized, i. e. it is false. Secondly,
as for Test No. 2 (the four or combo vehicles), Grice thinks it is fairly clear
that in this case, as in the case of “beautiful handwriting”, we could say that
the emissor had implies that he did not know (or that his ground is other than
truth-functional – assuming that he takes the questioner to be interested in
the specific location – i. e. to mean, “where IN THE HOUSE is your wife?”) and
also that his conveying explicilty that (or his conveying explicitly that
rather than something else, viz, in which room or where in the house she is, or
‘upstairs,’ or ‘downstairs,’ or ‘in the basement,’ or ‘in the attic,’ ‘went
shopping,’ ‘at the greengrocer’ – ‘she’s been missing for three weeks’) implied
that he did not know in which one of the two selected rooms his wife is
‘resident’ (and that he has grounds other than Gentzen’s truth-functional ones for
the introduction of ‘or.’). Thirdly, the implication (‘kitchen or bedroom’) is
in a way non-detachable, in that if in a given context the utterance of the
disjunctive sentence would involve the implication that the emissor did not
know in which room his his wife was (or strictly, that the emissor is
proceeding along non-truth-functional grounds for the introduction of ‘or,’ or
even more strictly still, that the emissor has grounds other than
truth-functional for the uttering of the disjunction), this implication would
also be involved in the utterance of any other form of words which would make
the same disjunctive assertion (e.g., "Look, knowing her, the alternatives
are she is either preparing some meal in the kitchen or snoozing in the
bedroom;” “One of the following things is the case, I’m pretty confident. First
thing: she is in the kitchen, since she enjoys watching the birds from the
kitchen window. Second thing: she is in the bedroom, since she enjoys watching birds
from the bedroom window.” Etymologically, “or” is short for ‘other,’ meaning
second. So a third possibility: “I will be Anglo-Saxon: First, she is the
kitchen. Second, she is in the bedroom.” “She is in the kitchen UNLESS she is
in the bedroom”“She is in the kitchen IF SHE IS NOT in the bedroom.”“Well, it
is not the case that she is in the KITCHEN *AND* in the bedroom, De Morgan!” She
is in the kitchen, provided she is not in the bedroom” “If she is not in the kitchen,
she is in the bedroom” “Bedroom, kitchen; one of the two.” “Kitchen, bedroom;
check both just in case.”“Sleeping; alternatively, cooking – you do the maths.”“The
choices are: bedroom and kitchen.”“My choices would be: bedroom and kitchen.”“I
would think: bedroom? … kitchen?”“Disjunctively, bedroom – kitchen – kitchen –
bedroom.”“In alternation: kitchen, bedroom, bedroom, kitchen – who cares?”“Exclusively,
bedroom, kitchen.”ln another possible way, however, the implication could
perhaps bc said to BE indeed detachable: for there will be some contexts of
utterance (as Firth calls them) in which the ‘normal’ implication (that the
utterer has grounds other than truth-functional for the utterance of a
disjunction) will not hold.Here, for the first time, Grice brings a different
scenario for ‘or’:“Thc Secretary of the Aristotelian Society, announcing ‘Our
coming symposium will be in Oxford OR not take place at all” perhaps does not
imply that he is has grounds other than truth-functional for the utterance of
the disjunction. He is just being wicked, and making a bad-taste joke. This totally
extraneous scenario points to the fact that the implication of a disjunction is
cancellable.Once we re-apply it to the ‘Where in the hell in your house your
wife is? I hear the noise, but can’t figure!’ Mutatis mutandi with the
Secretary to The Aristotelian Socieety, a man could say, “My wife is in the
kitchen or in the bedroorn.”in circumstances in which the implication (that the
man has grounds other than truth-functional for the uttering of the
disjunction) would normally be present, but he is not being co-operative –
since one doesn’t HAVE to be co-operative (This may be odd, that one appeals to
helpfulness everywhere but when it comes to the annulation!).So the man goes
on, “Mind you, I am not saying that I do not know which.”This is why we love
Grice. Why I love Grice. One would never think of finding that sort of wicked
English humour in, say Strawson. Strawson yet says that Grice should ‘let go.’
But to many, Grice is ALWAYS humorous, and making philosophy fun, into the
bargain, if that’s not the same thing. Everybody else at the Play Group
(notably the ones Grice opposed to: Strawson, Austin, Hare, Hampshire, and
Hart) would never play with him. Pears, Warnock, and Thomson would!“Mind you, I
am not saying that I do not know which.”A: Where in the house is your wife? I
need to talk to her.B: She is in the kitchen – or in the bedroom. I know where
she is – but since you usually bring trouble, I will make you decide so that
perhaps like Buridan’s ass, you find the choice impossible and refrain from
‘talking’ (i. e. bringing bad news) to her.A: Where is your wife? B: In the
kitchen or in the bedroom. I know where she is. But I also know you are always
saying that you know my wife so well. So, calculate, by the time of the day –
it’s 4 a.m – where she could be. A: Where is your wife? B: In the bedroom or in
the kitchen. I know where she is – but remember we were reading Heidegger
yesterday? He says that a kitchen is where one cooks, and a bedroom is where
one sleeps. So I’ll let you decide if Heidegger has been refuted, should you
find her sleeping in the kitchen, or cooking in the bedroom.A: Where is your
wife? B: In the kitchen or the bedroom. I know where she is. What you may NOT
know, is that we demolished the separating wall. We have a loft now. So all I’ll
say is that she may be in both! All this
might be unfriendly, unocooperative, and perhaps ungrammatical for Austen
[Grice pronounced the surname so that the Aristotelian Society members might
have a doubt] – if not Vitters, but, on the other hand, it would be a perfectly
intelligible thing for a (married) man to say. We may not even GO to bachelors.
Finally, the fact that the utterance of the disjunctive sentence normally or
standardly or caeteris paribus involves the implication of the emissor's ignorance
of the truth-values of the disjuncts (or more strictly, the implication of the
emissor’s having grounds other than truth-functional for the uttering of the
disjunctive) is, I should like to say, to be ‘explained’ – and Grice is being
serious here, since Austin never cared to ‘explain,’ even if he could -- by
reference to a general principle governing – or if that’s not too strong,
guiding – conversation, at least of the cooperative kind the virtues of which
we are supposed to be exulting to our tuttees. Exactly what this principle we
should not go there. To explain why the implicaturum that the emissor is having
grounds other than truth-functional ones for the utterance of a disjunction one
may appeal to the emissor being rational, assuming his emissee to be rational,
and abiding by something that Grice does NOT state in the imperative form, but
using what he calls a Hampshire modal (Grice divides the modals as Hampshire:
‘should,’ the weakest, ‘ought’ the Hare modal, the medium, and ‘must,’ Grice,
the stronges)"One, a man, a rational man, should not make conversational
move communicating ‘p’ which may be characterised (in strict terms of
entailment) as weaker (i.e. poor at conversational fortitude) rather than a
stronger (better at conversational fortitude) one unless there is a good reason
for so doing." So Gentzen is being crazey-basey if he thinks:p; therefore,
p or q.For who will proceed like that?“Or” is complicated, but so is ‘if.’ The
Gentzen differs from the evaluation assignemt:‘p or q’ is 1 iff p is 1 or q is
1. When we speak of ‘truth-functional’ grounds it is this assignment above we
are referring to.Of courseif p, p or q [a formulation of the Gentzen
introduction]is a TAUTOLOGY [which is what makes the introduction a rule of
inference].In terms of entailment P Or Q (independently) Is stronger than ‘p v q’ In that either p or q
entail ‘p or q’ but the reverse is not true. Grice says that he first thought
of the pragmatic rule in terms of the theory of perception, and Strawson hints
at this when he says in the footnote to “Introduction to Logical theory” that
the rule was pointed out by his tutor in the Logic Paper, Grice, “in a
different connection.” The logic paper took place before the war, so this is
early enough in Grice’s career – so the ghosts of Whitehead and Russell were
there! We can call the above ‘the principle of conversational fortitude.’ This
is certainly not an adequate formulation but will perhaps be good enough for
Grice’s purpose in “Causal.” On the assumption that such a principle as this is
of general application, one can DRAW or infer or explain the conclusion that
the utterance of a disjunctive sentence would imply that the emissor has
grounds other than truth-functional for the uttering of a disjunctum, given
that, first, the obvious reason for not making a statemcnt which there is some
call on one to make VALIDLY is that one is not in a position (or entitled) to
make it, and given, second, the logical ‘fact’ that each disjunct entails the
disjunctive, but not vice versa; which being so, each disjunct is stronger (bears
more conversational ‘fortitude’) than the disjunctive. If the outline just
given is on the right lines, Grice would wish to say, we have a reason for
REFUSING (as Strawson would not!) in the case of “kitchen or bedroom” to regard
the implication of the emissor having grounds other than truth-functional for
the uttering of the disjunctive as being part of the ‘meaning’ (whatever that
‘means’) of 'or' – but I should doublecheck with O. P. Wood – he’s our man in
‘or’ – A man who knows about the logical relation between a disjunction and
each disjunct, i. e. a man who has at least BROWSED Whitehead and Russell – and
diregards Bradley’s exclusivist account -- and who also ‘knew,’ qua Kantian
rational agent, about the alleged general principle or guiding conversational,
could work out for hirnself, surely, that a disjunctive utterance would involve
the implication which it does in fact involve. Grice insists, however, that his
aim in discussing this last point – about the principle of conversational
fortitude EXPLAING the generation of the implicaturum -- has been merelyto
indicate the position I would wish to take up, and not to argue scriously in
favour of it. Grice’s main purpose in the excursus on implication was to introduce
four ideas or catalysts, or tesets – TEST No. I: truth-value; TEST No. 2:
Vehicle out of four; Test No. 3/Twin Test: Annulation and Non-Detachment (is
there a positive way to express this – non-detached twins as opposed to
CONJOINT twins), and Test No. 4 – ‘Meaning’ of expression? -- of which Grice
then goes to make some use re: the pillar box seeming red.; and to provide some
conception of the ways in which each of the four tests apply or fail to apply
to various types of implication. By the numbering of it, it seems that by the
time of Essay II he has, typically, added an extra. It’s FIVE catalysts now,
but actually, since he has two of the previous tests all rolled up in one, it
is SIX CATALSTS. He’ll go back to them in Essay IV (“Indicative conditionals”
with regard to ‘if’), and in Presupposition and Conversational (with regard to
Example I here: “You have not ceased eating iron”). Implicaturum.He needs those
catalysts. Why? It seems like he is always thinking that someone will challenge
him! This is Grice: “We can now show that, it having been stipulated as being
what it is, a conversational implicaturum must possess certain distinctive
features, they are six. By using distinctive feature Grice is serious. He wants
each of the six catalysts to apply to each type of ‘implicaturum’, so that a
table can be constructed. With answers yes/no. Or rather here are some catalyst
ideas which will help us to determine or individuate. Six tests for implicaturum
as it were. SO THESE FEATURES – six of them – apply to three of the examples –
not the ‘poor but honest’ – but the “you have not ceased eating iron,”
“Beautiful handwriting,” and “Kitchen or bedroom.”First test – nothing about
the ‘twin’ – it’s ANNULATION or CANCELLABILITY – as noted in “Causal Theory” –
for two of the examples (‘beautiful handwriting’ and ‘kitchen or bedroom’ and
NEGATIVE version of “You don’t cease to eat iron”) and the one of the pillar
box – He adds a qualifier now: the annulation should best be IMPLICIT. But for
the fastidious philosopher, he allows for an EXPLICITATION which may not sound
grammatical enough to Austen (pronounced to rhyme with the playgroup master, or
the kindergarten’s master). To assume the presence of a conversational implicaturum,
the philosopher (and emissee) has to assume that the principle of
conversational co-operation (and not just conversational fortitude) is being
observed.However, it is mighty possible to opt out of this and most things at
Oxford, i. e. the observation of this principle of conversational cooperation
(or the earlier principle of conversational fortitude).It follows then that now
we CAN EXPLAIN WHY CANCELLABILITY IS A DISTINCTIVE FEATURE. He left it to be
understood in “Causal.”It follows then, deductively, that an implicaturum can
be canceled (or annulled) in a particular case. The conversational implicaturum
may be, drearily – but if that’s what the fastidious philosopher axes -- explicitly
canceled, if need there be, by the addition of a clause by which the utterer
states or implies that he opts out (e. g. “The pillar box seems red but it is.”
“Where is your wife?” “My lips are sealed”). Then again the conversational implicaturum
may be contextually (or implicitly) canceled, as Grice prefers (e. g. to a very
honest person, who knows I disbelieve the examiner exists, “The loyalty
examiner won’t be summoning you at any rate”). The utterance that usually would
carry an implicaturum is used on an occasion that makes it clear or obvious
that the utterer IS opting out without having to bore his addressee by making
this obviousness explicit. SECOND DISTINCTIVE FEATURE: CONJOINING, i.e.
non-detachability.There is a second litmus test or catalyst idea.Insofar as the
calculation that a implicaturum is present requires, besides contextual and
background information only an intuitive rational knowledge or understanding or
processing of what has been explicitly conveyed (‘are you playing squash? B
shows bandaged leg) (or the, shall we say, ‘conventional’ ‘arbitrary’
‘commitment’ of the utterance), and insofar as the manner or style, of FORM,
rather than MATTER, of expression should play at best absolutely no role in the
calculation, it is NOT possible to find another way of explicitly conveying or
putting forward the same thing, the same so-and-so (say that q follows from p)
which simply ‘lacks’ the unnecessary implicaturum in question -- except [will
his excluders never end?] where some special feature of the substituted version
[this other way which he says is not conceivable] is itself relevant to the determination
of the implicaturum (in virtue of this or that conversational maxims pertaining
to the category of conversational mode. THIS BIG CAVEAT makes you wonder that
Grice regretted making fun of Kant. By adopting jocularly the four
conversational categories, he now finds himself in having to give an excuse or
exception for those implicatura generated by a flout to what he earlier
referred to as the ‘desideratum of conversational clarity,’ and which he
jocularly rephrased as a self-defeating maxim, ‘be perspicuous [sic], never
mind perspicacious!’If we call this feature, as Grice does in “Causal Theory,”
‘non-detachability’ (or conjoining)– in that the implicaturum cannot be
detached or disjointed from any alternative expression that makes the same
point -- one may expect the implicaturum carried by this or that locution to
have a high degree of non-detachability. ALTERNATIVES FOR “NOT” Not, it is not
the case, it is false that. There’s nothing unique about ‘not’.ALTERNATIVES FOR
“AND” and, nothing, furthermore, but. There isnothing unique about
‘and’ALTERNATIVES FOR “OR”: One of the following is true. There is nothing
unique about ‘or’ALTERNATIVES FOR “IF” Provided. ‘There is nothing unique about
‘if’ALTERNATIVES FOR “THE” – There is at least one and at most one. And it
exists. (existence and uniqueness). There is nothing unique about ‘the’.THIS
COVERS STRAWSON’S first problem.What about the other English
philosophers?AUSTIN – on ‘voluntarily’ ALTERNATIVES to ‘voluntarily,’ with the
will, willingly, intentionally. Nothing unique about ‘voluntarily.’STRAWSON on
‘true’ – it is the case, redundance theory, nothing. Nothing unique about
‘true’HART ON good. To say that ‘x is commendable’ is to recommend x. Nothing
unique about ‘good.’HART on ‘carefully.’ Da Vinci painted Mona Lisa carefully,
with caution, with precaution. Nothing unique about ‘carefully.’THIRD LITMUS
TEST or idea and ATTENDING THIRD DISTINCTIVE
FEATURE. THIRD DISTINCTIVE FEATURE is in the protasis of the conditional.The implicaturum
depends on the explicatum or explicitum, and a fortiori, the implicaturum
cannot INVOLVE anything that the explicatum involves – There is nothing about
what an emissor explicitly conveys about “or” or a disjunctum in general, which
has to do with the emissor having grounds other than truth-functional for the
utterance of a disjunctum.The calculation of the presence of an implicaturum
presupposes an initial knowledge, or grasping, or understanding, or taking into
account of the ‘conventional’ force (not in Austin’s sense, but translating
Latin ‘vis’) of the expression the utterance of which carries the implicaturum.A
conversational implicaturum will be a condition (but not a truth-condition), i.
e. a condition that is NOT, be definition, on risk of circularity of otiosity,
included in what the emissor explicitly conveys, i. e. the original
specification of the expression's ‘conventional’ or arbitrary forceIf I’m
saying that ‘seems’ INVOLVES, as per conventional force, ‘doubt or
denial,’what’s my point? If Strawson is right that ‘if’ has the conventional
force of conventionally committing the utterer with the belief that q follows
from p, why bother? And if that were so, how come the implicaturum is still
cancellable?Though it may not be impossible for what starts life, so to speak,
as a conversational implicaturum to become conventionalized, to suppose that
this is so in a given case would require special justification. (Asking Lewis).
So, initially at least, a conversational implicaturum is, by definition and
stipulation, not part of the sense, truth-condition, conventional force, or
part of what is explicitly conveyed or put forward, or ‘meaning’ of the
expression to the employment of which the impicatum attaches. FOURTH LITMUS
TEST or catalyst idea. Mentioned in “Causal theory” YIELDS THE FOUTH DISICTINVE
FEATURE and the FIFTH distinctive feature.FOURTH DISTINCTIVE FEATURE: in the
protasis of the conditional – truth value.The alethic value – conjoined with
the test about the VEHICLE --. He has these as two different tests – and
correspondingly two distinctive features in “Causal”. The truth of a
conversational implicaturum is not required by (is not a condition for) the
truth of what is said or explicitly conveyed (what is said or explicated – the
explicatum or explicitum, or what is explicitly conveyed or communicated) may
be true -- what is implicated may be false – that he has beautiful handwriting,
that q follows from p, that the utterer is ENDORSING what someone else said,
that the utterer is recommending x, that the person who is said to act
carefully has taken precaution), FIFTH DISTINCTIVE FEATURE: vehicle – this is
the FOURTH vehicle of the four he mentions in “Causal”: ‘what the emissor
explicitly conveys,’ ‘the emissor himself,’ the emissor’s utterance, and
fourth, the emissor’s explicitly conveying, or explicitly conveying it that way
--. The apodosis of the conditional – or inferrability schema, since he uses
‘since,’ rather than ‘if,’ i. e. ‘GIVEN THAT p, q. Or ‘p; therefore, q’. The implicaturum
is NOT carried by what is said or the EXPLICATUM or EXPLICITUM, or is
explicitly conveyed, but only by the ‘saying’ or EXPLICATING or EXPLICITING of
what is said or of the explicatum or explicitum, or by 'putting it that way.’The
fifth and last litmus test or catalyst idea YIELDS A SIXTH DISTINCTIVE FEATURE:Note
that he never uses ‘first, second, etc.’ just the numerals, which in a lecture
format, are not visible!SIXTH DISTINCTIVE FEATURE: INDETERMINACY. Due to the
open character of the reasoning – and the choices available to fill the gap of
the content of the propositional attitude that makes the conversational
rational:“He is potentially dishonest.” “His colleagues are treacherous”Both implicatura
possible for “He hasn’t been to prison at his new job at the bank – yet.”Since,
to calculate a conversational implicaturum is to calculate what has to be
supposed in order to preserve the supposition that the utterer is a rational,
benevolent, altruist agent, and that the principle of conversational
cooperation is being observed, and since there may be various possible specific
explanations or alternatives that fill the gap here – as to what is the content
of the psychological attitude to be ascribed to the utterer, a list of which
may be open, or open-ended, the conversational implicaturum in such cases will
technically be an open-ended disjunction of all such specific explanations,
which may well be infinitely non-numerable. Since the list of these IS open,
the implicaturum will have just the kind of INDETERMINACY or lack of determinacy
that an implicaturum appears in most cases to possess. indeterminacy of
translation, a pair of theses derived, originally, from a thought experiment
regarding radical translation first propounded by Quine in Word and Object
(1960) and developed in his Ontological Relativity (1969), Theories and Things
(1981), and Pursuit of Truth (1990). Radical translation is an imaginary
context in which a field linguist is faced with the challenge of translating a
hitherto unknown language. Furthermore, it is stipulated that the linguist has
no access to bilinguals and that the language to be translated is historically
unrelated to that of the linguist. Presumably, the only data the linguist has
to go on are the observable behaviors of incompleteness indeterminacy of
translation 422 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 422 native speakers amid
the publicly observable objects of their environment. (1) The strong thesis of
indeterminacy, indeterminacy of translation of theoretical sentences as wholes,
is the claim that in the context of radical translation a linguist (or
linguists) could construct a number of manuals for translating the (natives’)
source language into the (linguists’) target language such that each manual
could be consistent with all possible behavior data and yet the manuals could
diverge with one another in countless places in assigning different
target-language sentences (holophrastically construed) as translations of the
same source-language sentences (holophrastically construed), diverge even to the
point where the sentences assigned have conflicting truth-values; and no
further data, physical or mental, could single out one such translation manual
as being the uniquely correct one. All such manuals, which are consistent with
all the possible behavioral data, are correct. (2) The weak thesis of
indeterminacy, indeterminacy of reference (or inscrutability of reference), is
the claim that given all possible behavior data, divergent target-language
interpretations of words within a source-language sentence could offset one
another so as to sustain different targetlanguage translations of the same
source-language sentence; and no further data, physical or mental, could single
out one such interpretation as the uniquely correct one. All such interpretations,
which are consistent with all the possible behavioral data, are correct. This
weaker sort of indeterminacy takes two forms: an ontic form and a syntactic
form. Quine’s famous example where the source-language term ‘gavagai’ could be
construed either as ‘rabbit’, ‘undetached rabbit part’, ‘rabbithood’, etc. (see
Word and Object), and his proxy function argument where different ontologies
could be mapped onto one another (see Ontological Relativity, Theories and
Things, and Pursuit of Truth), both exemplify the ontic form of indeterminacy
of reference. On the other hand, his example of the Japanese classifier, where
a particular three-word construction of Japanese can be translated into English
such that the third word of the construction can be construed with equal
justification either as a term of divided reference or as a mass term (see
Ontological Relativity and Pursuit of Truth), exemplifies the syntactic form of
indeterminacy of reference.
indexical: Bradley’s
thisness, and whatness – “Grice is improving on Scotus: Aristotle’s tode ti is
exactly Bradley’s thisness whatness – and more familiar to the English ear than
Scotus feminine ‘haecceitas.’” “Russell, being pretentious, call Bradley’s
“thisness” and “thatness,” but not “whatness” – as a class of the ‘egocentric
particular’ -- a type of expression
whose semantic value is in part determined by features of the context of
utterance, and hence may vary with that context. Among indexicals are the
personal pronouns, such as ‘I’, ‘you’, ‘he’, ‘she’, and ‘it’; demonstratives,
such as ‘this’ and ‘that’; temporal expressions, such as ‘now’, ‘today’,
‘yesterday’; and locative expressions, such as ‘here’, ‘there’, etc. Although
classical logic ignored indexicality, many recent practitioners, following
Richard Montague, have provided rigorous theories of indexicals in the context
of formal semantics. Perhaps the most plausible and thorough treatment of
indexicals is by David Kaplan, a prominent philosopher of language and logic
whose long-unpublished “Demonstratives” was especially influential; it
eventually appeared in J. Almog, J. Perry, and H. Wettstein, eds., Themes from
Kaplan. Kaplan argues persuasively that indexical singular terms are directly
referential and a species of rigid designator. He also forcefully brings out a
crucial lesson to be learned from indexicals, namely, that there are two types
of meaning, which Kaplan calls “content” and “character.” A sentence containing
an indexical, such as ‘I am hungry’, can be used to say different things in different
contexts, in part because of the different semantic contributions made by ‘I’
in these contexts. Kaplan calls a term’s contribution to what is said in a
context the term’s content. Though the content of an indexical like ‘I’ varies
with its context, it will nevertheless have a single meaning in the language,
which Kaplan calls the indexical’s character. This character may be conceived
as a rule of function that assigns different contents to the indexical in
different contexts.
implicaturum: in his Oxford
seminars. Grice: “I distinguish between the ‘implicaturum’ and the
‘implicaturum.’” “The ‘implicaturum’ corresponds to Moore’s entailment.” “For
the ‘pragmatic-type’ of thing, one should use ‘implicaturum.’” “The –aturum’
form is what at Clifton I learned as the future, and a ‘future’ twist it has,
since it refers to the future.” “ ‘Implicaturum esse’ is, strictly, the
infinitivum futurum, made out of the ‘esse’ plus the ‘indicaturum.’ We loved
these things at Clifton!”
indicatum. “oριστική,” “oristike,” – The Roman ‘indicatum’ is a
composite of ‘in’ plus ‘dicatum.’ The Romans were never sure about this.
Literally for the Greeks it’s the ‘definitive’ – ‘horistike’ klesis, inclinatio
or modus animae affectationem demonstrans indefinitivus – While indefinitivus
is the transliteration, the Romans also used ‘finitivus’ ‘finitus,’ and
‘indicativus’ and ‘pronuntiativus’. ‘Grice distinguishes between the indicative
mode and the informational mode. One can hardly inform oneself. Yet one can
utter an utterance in the indicative mode without it being in what he calls the
informational sub-mode. It’s interesting that Grice thinks he has to
distinguish between the ‘informational’ and the mere ‘indicative.’ Oddly when
he sets the goal to which ‘co-operation’ leads, it’s the informing/being
informed, influencing/being influenced. Surely he could have simplified that
by, as he later will, psi-transmission, whatever. So the emissor INDICATES,
even in an imperative utterance, what his will is. All moves are primarily ‘exhibitive,’
(and the function of the mode is to EXPRESS the corresponding attitude). Only
some moves are ‘protreptic.’ Grice was well aware, if perhaps not TOO aware,
since Austin was so secretive, about Austin on the ‘perlocution.’ Because
Austin wanted to deprieve the act from the cause of the act. Thus, Austin’s
communicative act may have a causal intention, leading to this or that effect –
but that would NOT be part of the philosopher’s interest. Suppose !p; whether
the order is successful and Smith does get a job he is promised, it hardly
matters to Kant, Austin, or Grice. Interestingly, ‘indicatum’ has the same root
as ‘dic-‘, to say – but surely you don’t need to say to indicate, as in Grice’s
favourite indicative mood: a hand wave signaling that the emissor knows the
route or is about to leave the emissee.
directum.
“Searle
thought he was being witty when adapting my implicaturum to what he called an
Indirect Austinian thing. Holdcroft was less obvious!” – Grice. – indirectum --
indirect discourse, also called oratio obliqua, the use of words to report what
others say, but without direct quotation. When one says “John said, ‘Not every
doctor is honest,’ “ one uses the words in one’s quotation directly – one uses
direct discourseto make an assertion about what John said. Accurate direct
discourse must get the exact words. But in indirect discourse one can use other
words than John does to report what he said, e.g., “John said that some
physicians are not honest.” The words quoted here capture the sense of John’s
assertion (the proposition he asserted). By extension, ‘indirect discourse’
designates the use of words in reporting beliefs. One uses words to
characterize the proposition believed rather than to make a direct assertion.
When Alice says, “John believes that some doctors are not honest,” she uses the
words ‘some doctors are not honest’ to present the proposition that John
believes. She does not assert the proposition. By contrast, direct discourse,
also called oratio recta, is the ordinary use of words to make assertions. Grice
struggled for years as to what the ‘fundamentum distinctionis’ is between the
central and the peripheric communicatum. He played with first-ground versus
second-ground. He played with two different crtieria: formal/material, and
dictive-non-dictive. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Holdcroft on direct and indirect communication.”
discernibile – “There’s the
discernible and the indiscernible, and Leibniz was a bit of a genius in
focusing on the second!” – Grice. indiscernibility: of identicals, the
principle that if A and B are identical, there is no difference between A and
B: everything true of A is true of B, and everything true of B is true of A; A
and B have just the same properties; there is no property such that A has it
while B lacks it, or B has it while A lacks it. A tempting formulation of this
principle, ‘Any two things that are identical have all their properties in
common’, verges on nonsense; for two things are never identical. ‘A is
numerically identical with B’ means that A and B are one and the same. A and B
have just the same properties because A, that is, B, has just the properties
that it has. This principle is sometimes called Leibniz’s law. It should be
distinguished from its converse, Leibniz’s more controversial principle of the
identity of indiscernibles. A contraposed form of the indiscernibility of
identicals – call it the distinctness of discernibles – reveals its point in
philosophic dialectic. If something is true of A that is not true of B, or (to
say the same thing differently) if something is true of B that is not true of
A, then A and B are not identical; they are distinct. One uses this principle
to attack identity claims. Classical arguments for dualism attempt to find
something true of the mind that is not true of anything physical. For example,
the mind, unlike everything physical, is indivisible. Also, the existence of
the mind, unlike the existence of everything physical, cannot be doubted. This
last argument shows that the distinctness of discernibles requires great care
of application in intentional contexts. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Definite
descriptions in Leibniz and in the vernacular.”
individuum: versus the
dividuum – or divisum. Cicero’s attempt to translate ‘a-tomon.’ In metaphysics,
a process whereby a universal, e.g., cat, becomes instantiated in an individual
– also called a particular e.g., Minina; (2) in epistemology, a process whereby
a knower discerns an individual, e.g., someone discerns Minina. The double
understanding of individuation raises two distinct problems: identifying the
causes of metaphysical individuation, and of epistemological individuation. In
both cases the causes are referred to as the principle of individuation.
Attempts to settle the metaphysical and epistemological problems of
individuation presuppose an understanding of the nature of individuality.
Individuality has been variously interpreted as involving one or more of the
following: indivisibility, difference, division within a species, identity
through time, impredicability, and non-instantiability. In general, theories of
individuation try to account variously for one or more of these. Individuation
may apply to both substances (e.g., Minina) and their features (e.g., Minina’s
fur color), generating two different sorts of theories. The theories of the
metaphysical individuation of substances most often proposed identify six types
of principles: a bundle of features (Russell); space and/or time (Boethius);
matter (Aristotle); form (Averroes); a decharacterized, sui generis component
called bare particular (Bergmann) or haecceity (Duns Scotus); and existence
(Avicenna). Sometimes several principles are combined. For example, for Aquinas
the principle of individuation is matter under dimensions (materia signata).
Two sorts of objections are often brought against these views of the
metaphysical individuation of substances. One points out that some of these
theories violate the principle of acquaintance,since they identify as
individuators entities for which there is no empirical evidence. The second
argues that some of these theories explain the individuation of substances in
terms of accidents, thus contradicting the ontological precedence of substance
over accident. The two most common theories of the epistemological individuation
of substances identify spatiotemporal location and/or the features of
substances as their individuators; we know a thing as an individual by its
location in space and time or by its features. The objections that are brought
to bear against these theories are generally based on the ineffectiveness of
those principles in all situations to account for the discernment of all types
of individuals. The theories of the metaphysical individuation of the features
of substances fall into two groups. Some identify the substance itself as the
principle of individuation; others identify some feature(s) of the substance as
individuator(s). Most accounts of the epistemological individuation of the
features of substances are similar to these views. The most common objections
to the metaphysical theories of the individuation of features attempt to show
that these theories are either incomplete or circular. It is argued, e.g., that
an account of the individuation of features in terms of substance is incomplete
because the individuation of the substance must also be accounted for: How
would one know what tree one sees, apart from its features? However, if the
substance is individuated by its features, one falls into a vicious circle.
Similar points are made with respect to the epistemological theories of the
individuation of features. Apart from the views mentioned, some philosophers
hold that individuals are individual essentially (per se), and therefore that
they do not undergo individuation. Under those conditions either there is no
need for a metaphysical principle of individuation (Ockham), or else the
principle of individuation is identified as the individual entity itself
(Suárez).
inductum: in the narrow
sense, inference to a generalization from its instances; (2) in the broad
sense, any ampliative inference – i.e., any inference where the claim made by
the conclusion goes beyond the claim jointly made by the premises. Induction in
the broad sense includes, as cases of particular interest: argument by analogy,
predictive inference, inference to causes from signs and symptoms, and
confirmation of scientific laws and theories. The narrow sense covers one
extreme case that is not ampliative. That is the case of mathematical
induction, where the premises of the argument necessarily imply the
generalization that is its conclusion. Inductive logic can be conceived most
generally as the theory of the evaluation of ampliative inference. In this
sense, much of probability theory, theoretical statistics, and the theory of computability
are parts of inductive logic. In addition, studies of scientific method can be
seen as addressing in a less formal way the question of the logic of inductive
inference. The name ‘inductive logic’ has also, however, become associated with
a specific approach to these issues deriving from the work of Bayes, Laplace,
De Morgan, and Carnap. On this approach, one’s prior probabilities in a state
of ignorance are determined or constrained by some principle for the
quantification of ignorance and one learns by conditioning on the evidence. A
recurrent difficulty with this line of attack is that the way in which
ignorance is quantified depends on how the problem is described, with different
logically equivalent descriptions leading to different prior probabilities.
Carnap laid down as a postulate for the application of his inductive logic that
one should always condition on one’s total evidence. This rule of total
evidence is usually taken for granted, but what justification is there for it?
Good pointed out that the standard Bayesian analysis of the expected value of
new information provides such a justification. Pure cost-free information
always has non-negative expected value, and if there is positive probability
that it will affect a decision, its expected value is positive. Ramsey made the
same point in an unpublished manuscript. The proof generalizes to various
models of learning uncertain evidence. A deductive account is sometimes
presented indubitability induction 425 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 425
where induction proceeds by elimination of possibilities that would make the
conclusion false. Thus Mill’s methods of experimental inquiry are sometimes
analyzed as proceeding by elimination of alternative possibilities. In a more
general setting, the hypothetico-deductive account of science holds that
theories are confirmed by their observational consequences – i.e., by
elimination of the possibilities that this experiment or that observation
falsifies the theory. Induction by elimination is sometimes put forth as an
alternative to probabilistic accounts of induction, but at least one version of
it is consistent with – and indeed a consequence of – probabilistic accounts.
It is an elementary fact of probability that if F, the potential falsifier, is
inconsistent with T and both have probability strictly between 0 and 1, then
the probability of T conditional on not-F is higher than the unconditional
probability of T. In a certain sense, inductive support of a universal
generalization by its instances may be a special case of the foregoing, but
this point must be treated with some care. In the first place, the universal
generalization must have positive prior probability. (It is worth noting that
Carnap’s systems of inductive logic do not satisfy this condition, although
systems of Hintikka and Niiniluoto do.) In the second place, the notion of
instance must be construed so the “instances” of a universal generalization are
in fact logical consequences of it. Thus ‘If A is a swan then A is white’ is an
instance of ‘All swans are white’ in the appropriate sense, but ‘A is a white
swan’ is not. The latter statement is logically stronger than ‘If A is a swan
then A is white’ and a complete report on species, weight, color, sex, etc., of
individual A would be stronger still. Such statements are not logical
consequences of the universal generalization, and the theorem does not hold for
them. For example, the report of a man 7 feet 11¾ inches tall might actually
reduce the probability of the generalization that all men are under 8 feet
tall. Residual queasiness about the foregoing may be dispelled by a point made
by Carnap apropos of Hempel’s discussion of paradoxes of confirmation.
‘Confirmation’ is ambiguous. ‘E confirms H’ may mean that the probability of H
conditional on E is greater than the unconditional probability of H, in which
case deductive consequences of H confirm H under the conditions set forth
above. Or ‘E confirms H’ may mean that the probability of H conditional on E is
high (e.g., greater than .95), in which case if E confirms H, then E confirms
every logical consequence of H. Conflation of the two senses can lead one to
the paradoxical conclusion that E confirms E & P and thus P for any
statement, P.
inductivism: “A philosophy of science
invented by Popper and P. K. Feyerabend as a foil for their own views. Why, I
must just have well invented ‘sensism’ as a foil for my theory of implicaturum!”
-- According to inductivism, a unique a priori inductive logic enables one to
construct an algorithm that will compute from any input of data the best
scientific theory accounting for that data.
inductum: Not deductum, --
nor abductum -- epapoge, Grecian term for ‘induction’. Especially in the logic
of Aristotle, epagoge is opposed to argument by syllogism. Aristotle describes
it as “a move from particulars to the universal.” E.g., premises that the
skilled navigator is the best navigator, the skilled charioteer the best
charioteer, and the skilled philosopher the best philosopher may support the
conclusion by epagoge that those skilled in something are usually the best at
it. Aristotle thought it more persuasive and clearer than the syllogistic
method, since it relies on the senses and is available to all humans. The term
was later applied to dialectical arguments intended to trap opponents. R.C.
epicheirema, a polysyllogism in which each premise represents an enthymematic
argument; e.g., ‘A lie creates disbelief, because it is an assertion that does
not correspond to truth; flattery is a lie, because it is a conscious
distortion of truth; therefore, flattery creates disbelief’. Each premise
constitutes an enthymematic syllogism. Thus, the first premise could be
expanded into the following full-fledged syllogism: ‘Every assertion that does
not correspond to truth creates disbelief; a lie is an assertion that does not
correspond to truth; therefore a lie creates disbelief’. We could likewise
expand the second premise and offer a complete argument for it. Epicheirema can
thus be a powerful tool in oral polemics, especially when one argues
regressively, first stating the conclusion with a sketch of support in terms of
enthymemes, and then if challenged to do
so expanding any or all of these
enthymemes into standard categorical syllogisms.
illatum: A form of the conjugation Grice
enjoyed was “inferentia,” cf essentia,
sententia, prudentia, etc.. – see illatum -- Cf. illatio. Consequentia.
Implicatio. Grice’s implicaturum and what the emissor implicates as a variation
on the logical usage.
infima species (Latin, ‘lowest species’),
a species that is not a genus of any other species. According to the theory of
classification, division, and definition that is part of traditional or
Aristotelian logic, every individual is a specimen of some infima species. An
infima species is a member of a genus that may in turn be a species of a more
inclusive genus, and so on, until one reaches a summum genus, a genus that is
not a species of a more inclusive genus. Socrates and Plato are specimens of
the infima specis human being (mortal rational animal), which is a species of
the genus rational animal, which is a species of the genus animal, and so on,
up to the summum genus substance. Whereas two specimens of animal – e.g., an
individual human and an individual horse – can differ partly in their essential
characteristics, no two specimens of the infima species human being can differ
in essence.
infinite-off
predicament, or ∞-off predicament.
infinitum: “What is not
finite.” “I know that there are infinitely many stars” – an example of a stupid
thing to say by the man in the street. apeiron, Grecian term meaning ‘the
boundless’ or ‘the unlimited’, which evolved to signify ‘the infinite’.
Anaximander introduced the term to philosophy by saying that the source of all
things was apeiron. There is some disagreement about whether he meant by this
the spatially antinomy apeiron unbounded, the temporally unbounded, or the
qualitatively indeterminate. It seems likely that he intended the term to
convey the first meaning, but the other two senses also happen to apply to the
spatially unbounded. After Anaximander, Anaximenes declared as his first
principle that air is boundless, and Xenophanes made his flat earth extend
downward without bounds, and probably outward horizontally without limit as
well. Rejecting the tradition of boundless principles, Parmenides argued that
“what-is” must be held within determinate boundaries. But his follower Melissus
again argued that what-is must be boundless
in both time and space for it can
have no beginning or end. Another follower of Parmenides, Zeno of Elea, argued
that if there are many substances, antinomies arise, including the consequences
that substances are both limited and unlimited apeira in number, and that they
are so small as not to have size and so large as to be unlimited in size.
Rejecting monism, Anaxagoras argued for an indefinite number of elements that
are each unlimited in size, and the Pythagorean Philolaus made limiters
perainonta and unlimiteds apeira the principles from which all things are
composed. The atomists Leucippus and Democritus conceived of a boundless
universe, partly full of an infinite number of atoms and partly void; and in
the universe are countless apeiroi worlds. Finally Aristotle arrived at an
abstract understanding of the apeiron as “the infinite,” claiming to settle
paradoxes about the boundless by allowing for real quantities to be infinitely
divisible potentially, but not actually Physics III.48. The development of the
notion of the apeiron shows how Grecian philosophers evolved ever more abstract
philosophical ideas from relatively concrete conceptions. Infinity -- Grice thougth that “There are
infinitely many stars” was a stupid thing to say -- diagonal procedure, a
method, originated by Cantor, for showing that there are infinite sets that
cannot be put in one-to-one correspondence with the set of natural numbers
i.e., enumerated. For example, the method can be used to show that the set of
real numbers x in the interval 0 ‹ x m 1 is not enumerable. Suppose x0, x1, x2,
. . . were such an enumeration x0 is the real correlated with 0; x1, the real
correlated with 1; and so on. Then consider the list formed by replacing each
real in the enumeration with the unique non-terminating decimal fraction
representing it: The first decimal fraction represents x0; the second, x1; and
so on. By diagonalization we select the decimal fraction shown by the arrows:
and change each digit xnn, taking care to avoid a terminating decimal. This
fraction is not on our list. For it differs from the first in the tenths place,
from the second in the hundredths place, and from the third in the thousandths
place, and so on. Thus the real it represents is not in the supposed
enumeration. This contradicts the original assumption. The idea can be put more
elegantly. Let f be any function such that, for each natural number n, fn is a
set of natural numbers. Then there is a set S of natural numbers such that n 1
S S n 2 fn. It is obvious that, for each n, fn & S. Infinity -- eternal return, the doctrine that
the same events, occurring in the same sequence and involving the same things,
have occurred infinitely many times in the past and will occur infinitely many
times in the future. Attributed most notably to the Stoics and Nietzsche, the
doctrine is antithetical to philosophical and religious viewpoints that claim
that the world order is unique, contingent in part, and directed toward some
goal. The Stoics interpret eternal return as the consequence of perpetual
divine activity imposing exceptionless causal principles on the world in a
supremely rational, providential way. The world, being the best possible, can
only be repeated endlessly. The Stoics do not explain why the best world cannot
be everlasting, making repetition unnecessary. It is not clear whether
Nietzsche asserted eternal return as a cosmological doctrine or only as a
thought experiment designed to confront one with the authenticity of one’s
life: would one affirm that life even if one were consigned to live it over
again without end? On either interpretation, Nietzsche’s version, like the
Stoic version, stresses the inexorability and necessary interconnectedness of
all things and events, although unlike the Stoic version, it rejects divine
providence. infinitary logic, the logic
of expressions of infinite length. Quine has advanced the claim that firstorder
logic (FOL) is the language of science, a position accepted by many of his
followers. Howinferential justification infinitary logic 428 4065h-l.qxd
08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 428 ever, many important notions of mathematics and
science are not expressible in FOL. The notion of finiteness, e.g., is central
in mathematics but cannot be expressed within FOL. There is no way to express
such a simple, precise claim as ‘There are only finitely many stars’ in FOL.
This and related expressive limitations in FOL seriously hamper its
applicability to the study of mathematics and have led to the study of stronger
logics. There have been various approaches to getting around the limitations by
the study of so-called strong logics, including second-order logic (where one
quantifies over sets or properties, not just individuals), generalized
quantifiers (where one adds quantifiers in addition to the usual ‘for all’ and
‘there exists’), and branching quantifiers (where notions of independence of
variables is introduced). One of the most fruitful methods has been the
introduction of idealized “infinitely long” statements. For example, the above
statement about the stars would be formalized as an infinite disjunction: there
is at most one star, or there are at most two stars, or there are at most three
stars, etc. Each of these disjuncts is expressible in FOL. The expressive
limitations in FOL are closely linked with Gödel’s famous completeness and
incompleteness theorems. These results show, among other things, that any
attempt to systematize the laws of logic is going to be inadequate, one way or
another. Either it will be confined to a language with expressive limitations,
so that these notions cannot even be expressed, or else, if they can be
expressed, then an attempt at giving an effective listing of axioms and rules
of inference for the language will fall short. In infinitary logic, the rules
of inference can have infinitely many premises, and so are not effectively
presentable. Early work in infinitary logic used cardinality as a guide:
whether or not a disjunction, conjunction, or quantifier string was permitted
had to do only with the cardinality of the set in question. It turned out that
the most fruitful of these logics was the language with countable conjunctions
and finite strings of first-order quantifiers. This language had further
refinements to socalled admissible languages, where more refined set-theoretic
considerations play a role in determining what counts as a formula. Infinitary
languages are also connected with strong axioms of infinity, statements that do
not follow from the usual axioms of set theory but for which one has other
evidence that they might well be true, or at least consistent. In particular,
compact cardinals are infinite cardinal numbers where the analogue of the
compactness theorem of FOL generalizes to the associated infinitary language.
These cardinals have proven to be very important in modern set theory. During
the 1990s, some infinitary logics played a surprising role in computer science.
By allowing arbitrarily long conjunctions and disjunctions, but only finitely
many variables (free or bound) in any formula, languages with attractive
closure properties were found that allowed the kinds of inductive procedures of
computer science, procedures not expressible in FOL. -- infinite regress
argument, a distinctively philosophical kind of argument purporting to show
that a thesis is defective because it generates an infinite series when either
(form A) no such series exists or (form B) were it to exist, the thesis would
lack the role (e.g., of justification) that it is supposed to play. The mere
generation of an infinite series is not objectionable. It is misleading therefore
to use ‘infinite regress’ (or ‘regress’) and ‘infinite series’ equivalently.
For instance, both of the following claims generate an infinite series: (1)
every natural number has a successor that itself is a natural number, and (2)
every event has a causal predecessor that itself is an event. Yet (1) is true
(arguably, necessarily true), and (2) may be true for all that logic can say
about the matter. Likewise, there is nothing contrary to logic about any of the
infinite series generated by the suppositions that (3) every free act is the
consequence of a free act of choice; (4) every intelligent operation is the
result of an intelligent mental operation; (5) whenever individuals x and y
share a property F there exists a third individual z which paradigmatically has
F and to which x and y are somehow related (as copies, by participation, or
whatnot); or (6) every generalization from experience is inductively inferable
from experience by appeal to some other generalization from experience. What
Locke (in the Essay concerning Human Understanding) objects to about the theory
of free will embodied in (3) and Ryle (in The Concept of Mind) objects to about
the “intellectualist leginfinite, actual infinite regress argument 429
4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 429 end” embodied in (4) can therefore be
only that it is just plain false as a matter of fact that we perform an
infinite number of acts of choice or operations of the requisite kinds. In
effect their infinite regress arguments are of form A: they argue that the
theories concerned must be rejected because they falsely imply that such
infinite series exist. Arguably the infinite regress arguments employed by
Plato (in the Parmenides) regarding his own theory of Forms and by Popper (in
the Logic of Scientific Discovery) regarding the principle of induction
proposed by Mill, are best construed as having form B, their objections being
less to (5) or (6) than to their epistemic versions: (5*) that we can
understand how x and y can share a property F only if we understand that there
exists a third individual (the “Form” z) which paradigmatically has F and to
which x and y are related; and (6*) that since the principle of induction must
itself be a generalization from experience, we are justified in accepting it
only if it can be inferred from experience by appeal to a higherorder, and
justified, inductive principle. They are arguing that because the series
generated by (5) and (6) are infinite, the epistemic enlightenment promised by
(5*) and (6*) will forever elude us. When successful, infinite regress
arguments can show us that certain sorts of explanation, understanding, or
justification are will-o’-thewisps. As Passmore has observed (in Philosophical
Reasoning) there is an important sense of ‘explain’ in which it is impossible
to explain predication. We cannot explain x’s and y’s possession of the common
property F by saying that they are called by the same name (nominalism) or fall
under the same concept (conceptualism) any more than we can by saying that they
are related to the same form (Platonic realism), since each of these is itself
a property that x and y are supposed to have in common. Likewise, it makes no
sense to try to explain why anything at all exists by invoking the existence of
something else (such as the theist’s God). The general truths that things
exist, and that things may have properties in common, are “brute facts” about
the way the world is. Some infinite regress objections fail because they are
directed at “straw men.” Bradley’s regress argument against the pluralist’s
“arrangement of given facts into relations and qualities,” from which he
concludes that monism is true, is a case in point. He correctly argues that if
one posits the existence of two or more things, then there must be relations of
some sort between them, and then (given his covert assumption that these
relations are things) concludes that there must be further relations between
these relations ad infinitum. Bradley’s regress misfires because a pluralist
would reject his assumption. Again, some regress arguments fail because they
presume that any infinite series is vicious. Aquinas’s regress objection to an
infinite series of movers, from which he concludes that there must be a prime
mover, involves this sort of confusion. -- infinity, in set theory, the
property of a set whereby it has a proper subset whose members can be placed in
one-to-one correspondence with all the members of the set, as the even integers
can be so arranged in respect to the natural numbers by the function f(x) =
x/2, namely: Devised by Richard Dedekind in defiance of the age-old intuition
that no part of a thing can be as large as the thing, this set-theoretical
definition of ‘infinity’, having been much acclaimed by philosophers like
Russell as a model of conceptual analysis that philosophers were urged to
emulate, can elucidate the putative infinity of space, time, and even God, his
power, wisdom, etc. If a set’s being denumerable – i.e., capable of having its
members placed in one-to-one correspondence with the natural numbers – can well
appear to define much more simply what the infinity of an infinite set is,
Cantor exhibited the real numbers (as expressed by unending decimal expansions)
as a counterexample, showing them to be indenumerable by means of his famous
diagonal argument. Suppose all the real numbers between 0 and 1 are placed in
one-to-one correspondence with the natural numbers, thus: Going down the
principal diagonal, we can construct a new real number, e.g., .954 . . . , not
found in the infinite “square array.” The most important result in set theory,
Cantor’s theorem, is denied its full force by the maverick followers infinity
infinity 430 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 430 of Skolem, who appeal to
the fact that, though the real numbers constructible in any standard axiomatic
system will be indenumerable relative to the resources of the system, they can
be seen to be denumerable when viewed from outside it. Refusing to accept the
absolute indenumerability of any set, the Skolemites, in relativizing the
notion to some system, provide one further instance of the allure of
relativism. More radical still are the nominalists who, rejecting all abstract
entities and sets in particular, might be supposed to have no use for Cantor’s
theorem. Not so. Assume with Democritus that there are infinitely many of his
atoms, made of adamant. Corresponding to each infinite subset of these atoms
will be their mereological sum or “fusion,” namely a certain quantity of
adamant. Concrete entities acceptable to the nominalist, these quantities can
be readily shown to be indenumerable. Whether Cantor’s still higher infinities
beyond F1 admit of any such nominalistic realization remains a largely
unexplored area. Aleph-zero or F0 being taken to be the transfinite number of
the natural numbers, there are then F1 real numbers (assuming the continuum
hypothesis), while the power set of the reals has F2 members, and the power set
of that F3 members, etc. In general, K2 will be said to have a greater number
(finite or transfinite) of members than K1 provided the members of K1 can be
put in one-to-one correspondence with some proper subset of K2 but not vice
versa. Skepticism regarding the higher infinities can trickle down even to F0,
and if both Aristotle and Kant, the former in his critique of Zeno’s paradoxes,
the latter in his treatment of cosmological antinomies, reject any actual, i.e.
completed, infinite, in our time Dummett’s return to verificationism, as
associated with the mathematical intuitionism of Brouwer, poses the keenest
challenge. Recognition-transcendent sentences like ‘The total number of stars
is infinite’ are charged with violating the intersubjective conditions required
for a speaker of a language to manifest a grasp of their meaning. Strawson,
or Grice’s favourite informalist: THE INFORMALISTS – A Group under which Grice
situated his post-generational Strawson and his pre-generational Ryle. informal
fallacy, an error of reasoning or tactic of argument that can be used to
persuade someone with whom you are reasoning that your argument is correct when
really it is not. The standard treatment of the informal fallacies in logic
textbooks draws heavily on Aristotle’s list, but there are many variants, and
new fallacies have often been added, some of which have gained strong footholds
in the textbooks. The word ‘informal’ indicates that these fallacies are not
simply localized faults or failures in the given propositions (premises and
conclusion) of an argument to conform to a standard of semantic correctness (like
that of deductive logic), but are misuses of the argument in relation to a
context of reasoning or type of dialogue that an arguer is supposed to be
engaged in. Informal logic is the subfield of logical inquiry that deals with
these fallacies. Typically, informal fallacies have a pragmatic (practical)
aspect relating to how an argument is being used, and also a dialectical
aspect, pertaining to a context of dialogue – normally an exchange between two
participants in a discussion. Both aspects are major concerns of informal
logic. Logic textbooks classify informal fallacies in various ways, but no
clear and widely accepted system of classification has yet become established.
Some textbooks are very inventive and prolific, citing many different fallacies,
including novel and exotic ones. Others are more conservative, sticking with
the twenty or so mainly featured in or derived from Aristotle’s original
treatment, with a few widely accepted additions. The paragraphs below cover
most of these “major” or widely featured fallacies, the ones most likely to be
encountered by name in the language of everyday educated conversation. The
genetic fallacy is the error of drawing an inappropriate conclusion about the
goodness or badness of some property of a thing from the goodness or badness of
some property of the origin of that thing. For example, ‘This medication was
derived from a plant that is poisonous; therefore, even though my physician
advises me to take it, I conclude that it would be very bad for me if I took
it.’ The error is inappropriately arguing from the origin of the medication to
the conclusion that it must be poisonous in any form or situation. The genetic
fallacy is often construed very broadly making it coextensive with the personal
attack type of argument (see the description of argumentum ad hominem below)
that condemns a prior argument by condemning its source or proponent.
Argumentum ad populum (argument to the people) is a kind of argument that uses
appeal to popular sentiments to support a conclusion. Sometimes called “appeal
to the gallery” or “appeal to popular pieties” or even “mob appeal,” this kind
of argument has traditionally been portrayed as fallacious. However, there
infinity, axiom of informal fallacy 431 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 431
need be nothing wrong with appealing to popular sentiments in argument, so long
as their evidential value is not exaggerated. Even so, such a tactic can be
fallacious when the attempt to arouse mass enthusiasms is used as a substitute
to cover for a failure to bring forward the kind of evidence that is properly
required to support one’s conclusion. Argumentum ad misericordiam (argument to
pity) is a kind of argument that uses an appeal to pity, sympathy, or
compassion to support its conclusion. Such arguments can have a legitimate
place in some discussions – e.g., in appeals for charitable donations. But they
can also put emotional pressure on a respondent in argument to try to cover up
a weak case. For example, a student who does not have a legitimate reason for a
late assignment might argue that if he doesn’t get a high grade, his
disappointed mother might have a heart attack. The fallacy of composition is
the error of arguing from a property of parts of a whole to a property of the
whole – e.g., ‘The important parts of this machine are light; therefore this
machine is light.’ But a property of the parts cannot always be transferred to
the whole. In some cases, examples of the fallacy of composition are arguments
from all the parts to a whole, e.g. ‘Everybody in the country pays her debts.
Therefore the country pays its debts.’ The fallacy of division is the converse
of that of composition: the error of arguing from a property of the whole to a
property of its parts – e.g., ‘This machine is heavy; therefore all the parts
of this machine are heavy.’ The problem is that the property possessed by the
whole need not transfer to the parts. The fallacy of false cause, sometimes
called post hoc, ergo propter hoc (after this, therefore because of this), is the
error of arguing that because two events are correlated with one another,
especially when they vary together, the one is the cause of the other. For
example, there might be a genuine correlation between the stork population in
certain areas of Europe and the human birth rate. But it would be an error to
conclude, on that basis alone, that the presence of storks causes babies to be
born. In general, however, correlation is good, if sometimes weak, evidence for
causation. The problem comes in when the evidential strength of the correlation
is exaggerated as causal evidence. The apparent connection could just be
coincidence, or due to other factors that have not been taken into account,
e.g., some third factor that causes both the events that are correlated with
each other. The fallacy of secundum quid (neglecting qualifications) occurs
where someone is arguing from a general rule to a particular case, or vice
versa. One version of it is arguing from a general rule while overlooking or
suppressing legitimate exceptions. This kind of error has also often been
called the fallacy of accident. An example would be the argument ‘Everyone has
the right to freedom of speech; therefore it is my right to shout “Fire” in
this crowded theater if I want to.’ The other version of secundum quid,
sometimes also called the fallacy of converse accident, or the fallacy of hasty
generalization, is the error of trying to argue from a particular case to a
general rule that does not properly fit that case. An example would be the argument
‘Tweetie [an ostrich] is a bird that does not fly; therefore birds do not fly’.
The fault is the failure to recognize or acknowledge that Tweetie is not a
typical bird with respect to flying. Argumentum consensus gentium (argument
from the consensus of the nations) is a kind that appeals to the common consent
of mankind to support a conclusion. Numerous philosophers and theologians in
the past have appealed to this kind of argument to support conclusions like the
existence of God and the binding character of moral principles. For example,
‘Belief in God is practically universal among human beings past and present;
therefore there is a practical weight of presumption in favor of the truth of
the proposition that God exists’. A version of the consensus gentium argument
represented by this example has sometimes been put forward in logic textbooks
as an instance of the argumentum ad populum (described above) called the
argument from popularity: ‘Everybody believes (accepts) P as true; therefore P
is true’. If interpreted as applicable in all cases, the argument from
popularity is not generally sound, and may be regarded as a fallacy. However,
if regarded as a presumptive inference that only applies in some cases, and as
subject to withdrawal where evidence to the contrary exists, it can sometimes
be regarded as a weak but plausible argument, useful to serve as a provisional
guide to prudent action or reasoned commitment. Argumentum ad hominem
(literally, argument against the man) is a kind of argument that uses a
personal attack against an arguer to refute her argument. In the abusive or
personal variant, the character of the arguer (especially character for
veracity) is attacked; e.g., ‘You can’t believe what Smith says – he is a
liar’. In evaluating testimony (e.g., in legal cross-examination), attacking an
arguer’s character can be legitimate in some cases. Also in political debate,
character can be a legitimate issue. However, ad hominem arguinformal fallacy
informal fallacy 432 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 432 ments are commonly
used fallaciously in attacking an opponent unfairly – e.g., where the attack is
not merited, or where it is used to distract an audience from more relevant
lines of argument. In the circumstantial variant, an arguer’s personal
circumstances are claimed to be in conflict with his argument, implying that
the arguer is either confused or insincere; e.g., ‘You don’t practice what you
preach’. For example, a politician who has once advocated not raising taxes may
be accused of “flip-flopping” if he himself subsequently favors legislation to
raise taxes. This type of argument is not inherently fallacious, but it can go
badly wrong, or be used in a fallacious way, for example if circumstances
changed, or if the alleged conflict was less serious than the attacker claimed.
Another variant is the “poisoning the well” type of ad hominem argument, where
an arguer is said to have shown no regard for the truth, the implication being
that nothing he says henceforth can ever be trusted as reliable. Yet another
variant of the ad hominem argument often cited in logic textbooks is the tu
quoque (you-too reply), where the arguer attacked by an ad hominem argument
turns around and says, “What about you? Haven’t you ever lied before? You’re
just as bad.” Still another variant is the bias type of ad hominem argument,
where one party in an argument charges the other with not being honest or
impartial or with having hidden motivations or personal interests at stake.
Argumentum ad baculum (argument to the club) is a kind of argument that appeals
to a threat or to fear in order to support a conclusion, or to intimidate a
respondent into accepting it. Ad baculum arguments often take an indirect form;
e.g., ‘If you don’t do this, harmful consequences to you might follow’. In such
cases the utterance can often be taken as a threat. Ad baculum arguments are
not inherently fallacious, because appeals to threatening or fearsome sanctions
– e.g., harsh penalties for drunken driving – are not necessarily failures of critical
argumentation. But because ad baculum arguments are powerful in eliciting
emotions, they are often used persuasively as sophistical tactics in
argumentation to avoid fulfilling the proper requirements of a burden of proof.
Argument from authority is a kind of argument that uses expert opinion (de
facto authority) or the pronouncement of someone invested with an institutional
office or title (de jure authority) to support a conclusion. As a practical but
fallible method of steering discussion toward a presumptive conclusion, the
argument from authority can be a reasonable way of shifting a burden of proof.
However, if pressed too hard in a discussion or portrayed as a better
justification for a conclusion than the evidence warrants, it can become a fallacious
argumentum ad verecundiam (see below). It should be noted, however, that
arguments based on expert opinions are widely accepted both in artificial
intelligence and everyday argumentation as legitimate and sound under the right
conditions. Although arguments from authority have been strongly condemned
during some historical periods as inherently fallacious, the current climate of
opinion is to think of them as acceptable in some cases, even if they are
fallible arguments that can easily go wrong or be misused by sophistical
persuaders. Argumentum ad judicium represents a kind of knowledge-based
argumentation that is empirical, as opposed to being based on an arguer’s
personal opinion or viewpoint. In modern terminology, it apparently refers to
an argument based on objective evidence, as opposed to somebody’s subjective
opinion. The term appears to have been invented by Locke to contrast three
commonly used kinds of arguments and a fourth special type of argument. The
first three types of argument are based on premises that the respondent of the
argument is taken to have already accepted. Thus these can all be called
“personal” in nature. The fourth kind of argument – argumentum ad judicium –
does not have to be based on what some person accepts, and so could perhaps be
called “impersonal.” Locke writes that the first three kinds of arguments can
dispose a person for the reception of truth, but cannot help that person to the
truth. Only the argumentum ad judicium can do that. The first three types of arguments
come from “my shamefacedness, ignorance or error,” whereas the argumentum ad
judicium “comes from proofs and arguments and light arising from the nature of
things themselves.” The first three types of arguments have only a preparatory
function in finding the truth of a matter, whereas the argumentum ad judicium
is more directly instrumental in helping us to find the truth. Argumentum ad
verecundiam (argument to reverence or respect) is the fallacious use of expert
opinion in argumentation to try to persuade someone to accept a conclusion. In
the Essay concerning Human Understanding (1690) Locke describes such arguments
as tactics of trying to prevail on the assent of someone by portraying him as
irreverent or immodest if he does not readily yield to the authority of some
learned informal fallacy informal fallacy 433 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM
Page 433 opinion cited. Locke does not claim, however, that all appeals to
expert authority in argument are fallacious. They can be reasonable if used
judiciously. Argumentum ad ignorantiam (argument to ignorance) takes the
following form: a proposition a is not known or proved to be true (false);
therefore A is false (true). It is a negative type of knowledge-based or
presumptive reasoning, generally not conclusive, but it is nevertheless often
non-fallacious in balance-of-consideration cases where the evidence is
inconclusive to resolve a disputed question. In such cases it is a kind of
presumption-based argumentation used to advocate adopting a conclusion provisionally,
in the absence of hard knowledge that would determine whether the conclusion is
true or false. An example would be: Smith has not been heard from for over
seven years, and there is no evidence that he is alive; therefore it may be
presumed (for the purpose of settling Smith’s estate) that he is dead.
Arguments from ignorance ought not to be pressed too hard or used with too
strong a degree of confidence. An example comes from the U.S. Senate hearings
in 1950, in which Senator Joseph McCarthy used case histories to argue that
certain persons in the State Department should be considered Communists. Of one
case he said, “I do not have much information on this except the general
statement of the agency that there is nothing in the files to disprove his
Communist connections.” The strength of any argument from ignorance depends on
the thoroughness of the search made. The argument from ignorance can be used to
shift a burden of proof merely on the basis of rumor, innuendo, or false
accusations, instead of real evidence. Ignoratio elenchi (ignorance of
refutation) is the traditional name, following Aristotle, for the fault of
failing to keep to the point in an argument. The fallacy is also called
irrelevant conclusion or missing the point. Such a failure of relevance is
essentially a failure to keep closely enough to the issue under discussion.
Suppose that during a criminal trial, the prosecutor displays the victim’s
bloody shirt and argues at length that murder is a horrible crime. The
digression may be ruled irrelevant to the question at issue of whether the
defendant is guilty of murder. Alleged failures of this type in argumentation
are sometimes quite difficult to judge fairly, and a ruling should depend on
the type of discussion the participants are supposed to be engaged in. In some
cases, conventions or institutional rules of procedure – e.g. in a criminal
trial – are aids to determining whether a line of argumentation should be
judged relevant or not. Petitio principii (asking to be granted the “principle”
or issue of the discussion to be proved), also called begging the question, is
the fallacy of improperly arguing in a circle. Circular reasoning should not be
presumed to be inherently fallacious, but can be fallacious where the circular
argument has been used to disguise or cover up a failure to fulfill a burden of
proof. The problem arises where the conclusion that was supposed to be proved
is presumed within the premises to be granted by the respondent of the
argument. Suppose I ask you to prove that this bicycle (the ownership of which
is subject to dispute) belongs to Hector, and you reply, “All the bicycles
around here belong to Hector.” The problem is that without independent evidence
that shows otherwise, the premise that all the bicycles belong to Hector takes
for granted that this bicycle belongs to Hector, instead of proving it by
properly fulfilling the burden of proof. The fallacy of many questions (also
called the fallacy of complex question) is the tactic of packing unwarranted
presuppositions into a question so that any direct answer given by the
respondent will trap her into conceding these presuppositions. The classical
case is the question, “Have you stopped beating your spouse?” No matter how the
respondent answers, yes or no, she concedes the presuppositions that (a) she
has a spouse, and (b) she has beaten that spouse at some time. Where one or
both of these presumptions are unwarranted in the given case, the use of this
question is an instance of the fallacy of many questions. The fallacy of
equivocation occurs where an ambiguous word has been used more than once in an
argument in such a way that it is plausible to interpret it in one way in one
instance of its use and in another way in another instance. Such an argument
may seem persuasive if the shift in the context of use of the word makes these
differing interpretations plausible. Equivocation, however, is generally
seriously deceptive only in longer sequences of argument where the meaning of a
word or phrase shifts subtly but significantly. A simplistic example will
illustrate the gist of the fallacy: ‘The news media should present all the
facts on anything that is in the public interest; the public interest in lives
of movie stars is intense; therefore the news media should present all the
facts on the private lives of movie stars’. This argument goes from plausible
premises to an implausible conclusion by trading on the ambiguity of ‘public
interest’. In one sense informal fallacy informal fallacy 434 4065h-l.qxd
08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 434 it means ‘public benefit’ while in another sense it
refers to something more akin to curiosity. Amphiboly (double arrangement) is a
type of traditional fallacy (derived from Aristotle’s list of fallacies) that
refers to the use of syntactically ambiguous sentences like ‘Save soap and
waste paper’. Although the logic textbooks often cite examples of such
sentences as fallacies, they have never made clear how they could be used to
deceive in a serious discussion. Indeed, the example cited is not even an
argument, but simply an ambiguous sentence. In cases of some advertisements
like ‘Two pizzas for one special price’, however, one can see how the amphiboly
seriously misleads readers into thinking they are being offered two pizzas for
the regular price of one. Accent is the use of shifting stress or emphasis in
speech as a means of deception. For example, if a speaker puts stress on the
word ‘created’ in ‘All men were created equal’ it suggests (by implicaturum)
the opposite proposition to ‘All men are equal’, namely ‘Not all men are (now)
equal’. The oral stress allows the speaker to covertly suggest an inference the
hearer is likely to draw, and to escape commitment to the conclusion suggested
by later denying he said it. The slippery slope argument, in one form, counsels
against some contemplated action (or inaction) on the ground that, once taken,
it will be a first step in a sequence of events that will be difficult to
resist and will (or may or must) lead to some dangerous (or undesirable or disastrous)
outcome in the end. It is often argued, e.g., that once you allow euthanasia in
any form, such as the withdrawal of heroic treatments of dying patients in
hospitals, then (through erosion of respect for human life), you will
eventually wind up with a totalitarian state where old, feeble, or politically
troublesome individuals are routinely eliminated. Some slippery slope arguments
can be reasonable, but they should not be put forward in an exaggerated way,
supported with insufficient evidence, or used as a scare tactic.
informal logic: Grice preferred ‘material’
logic – “What Strawson means by ‘informal logic’ is best expressed by
‘ordinary-language logic,’ drawing on Bergmann’s distinction between the
ordinary and the ideal.” Also called practical logic, the use of logic to
identify, analyze, and evaluate arguments as they occur in contexts of
discourse in everyday conversations. In informal logic, arguments are assessed
on a case-by-case basis, relative to how the argument was used in a given context
to persuade someone to accept the conclusion, or at least to give some reason
relevant to accepting the conclusion.
informatum – “What has
‘forma’ to do with ‘inform’?” – Grice. While etymologically it means ‘to
mould,’ Lewis and Short render ‘informare’ as “to
inform, instruct, educate (syn.: “instruere, instituere): artes quibus aetas
puerilis ad humanitatem informari solet,” Cic. Arch. 3, 4: “animus a natura
bene informatus,” formed, id. Off. 1, 4, 13. I. e. “the soul is well informed
by nature.” Informativus – informational. Grice distinguishes between
the indicative and the informational. “Surely it is stupid to inform myself,
but not Strawson, that it is raining. Grammarians don’t care, but I do!”
information theory, also called communication theory, a primarily mathematical
theory of communication. Prime movers in its development include Claude
Shannon, H. Nyquist, R. V. L. Hartley, Norbert Wiener, Boltzmann, and Szilard.
Original interests in the theory were largely theoretical or applied to
telegraphy and telephony, and early development clustered around engineering
problems in such domains. Philosophers (Bar-Hillel, Dretske, and Sayre, among
others) are mainly interested in information theory as a source for developing
a semantic theory of information and meaning. The mathematical theory has been
less concerned with the details of how a message acquires meaning and more
concerned with what Shannon called the “fundamental problem of communication” –
reproducing at one point either exactly or approximately a message (that
already has a meaning) selected at another point. Therefore, the two interests
in information – the mathematical and the philosophical – have remained largely
orthogonal. Information is an objective (mind-independent) entity. It can be
generated or carried by messages (words, sentences) or other products of
cognizers (interpreters). Indeed, communication theory focuses primarily on
conditions involved in the generation and transmission of coded (linguistic)
messages. However, almost any event can (and usually does) generate information
capable of being encoded or transmitted. For example, Colleen’s acquiring red
spots can contain information about Colleen’s having the measles and graying
hair can carry information about her grandfather’s aging. This information can
be encoded into messages about measles or aging (respectively) and transmitted,
but the information would exist independently of its encoding or transmission.
That is, this information would be generated (under the right conditions) by
occurrence of the measles-induced spots and the age-induced graying themselves
– regardless of anyone’s actually noticing. This objective feature of
information explains its potential for epistemic and semantic development by
philosophers and cognitive scientists. For example, in its epistemic dimension,
a single (event, message, or Colleen’s spots) that contains informal logic
information theory 435 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 435 (carries) the
information that Colleen has the measles is something from which one (mom,
doctor) can come to know that Colleen has the measles. Generally, an event
(signal) that contains the information that p is something from which one can
come to know that p is the case – provided that one’s knowledge is indeed based
on the information that p. Since information is objective, it can generate what
we want from knowledge – a fix on the way the world objectively is configured.
In its semantic dimension, information can have intentionality or aboutness. What
is happening at one place (thermometer reading rising in Colleen’s mouth) can
carry information about what is happening at another place (Colleen’s body
temperature rising). The fact that messages (or mental states, for that matter)
can contain information about what is happening elsewhere, suggests an exciting
prospect of tracing the meaning of a message (or of a thought) to its
informational origins in the environment. To do this in detail is what a
semantic theory of information is about. The mathematical theory of information
is purely concerned with information in its quantitative dimension. It deals
with how to measure and transmit amounts of information and leaves to others
the work of saying what (how) meaning or content comes to be associated with a
signal or message. In regard to amounts of information, we need a way to
measure how much information is generated by an event (or message) and how to
represent that amount. Information theory provides the answer. Since
information is an objective entity, the amount of information associated with
an event is related to the objective probability (likelihood) of the event.
Events that are less likely to occur generate more information than those more
likely to occur. Thus, to discover that the toss of a fair coin came up heads
contains more information than to discover this about the toss of a coin biased
(.8) toward heads. Or, to discover that a lie was knowingly broadcast by a
censored, state-run radio station, contains less information than that a lie was
knowingly broadcast by a non-censored, free radio station (say, the BBC). A
(perhaps surprising) consequence of associating amounts of information with
objective likelihoods of events is that some events generate no information at
all. That is, that 55 % 3125 or that water freezes at 0oC. (on a specific
occasion) generates no information at all – since these things cannot be
otherwise (their probability of being otherwise is zero). Thus, their
occurrence generates zero information. Shannon was seeking to measure the
amount of information generated by a message and the amount transmitted by its
reception (or about average amounts transmissible over a channel). Since his
work, it has become standard to think of the measure of information in terms of
reductions of uncertainty. Information is identified with the reduction of
uncertainty or elimination of possibilities represented by the occurrence of an
event or state of affairs. The amount of information is identified with how
many possibilities are eliminated. Although other measures are possible, the
most convenient and intuitive way that this quantity is standardly represented
is as a logarithm (to the base 2) and measured in bits (short for how many
binary digits) needed to represent binary decisions involved in the reduction
or elimination of possibilities. If person A chooses a message to send to
person B, from among 16 equally likely alternative messages (say, which number
came up in a fair drawing from 16 numbers), the choice of one message would
represent 4 bits of information (16 % 24 or log2 16 % 4). Thus, to calculate
the amount of information generated by a selection from equally likely messages
(signals, events), the amount of information I of the message s is calculated
I(s) % logn. If there is a range of messages (s1 . . . sN) not all of which are
equally likely (letting (p (si) % the probability of any si’s occurrence), the
amount of information generated by the selection of any message si is
calculated I(si) % log 1/p(si) % –log p(si) [log 1/x % –log x] While each of
these formulas says how much information is generated by the selection of a
specific message, communication theory is seldom primarily interested in these
measures. Philosophers are interested, however. For if knowledge that p requires
receiving the information that p occurred, and if p’s occurrence represents 4
bits of information, then S would know that p occurred only if S received
information equal to (at least) 4 bits. This may not be sufficient for S to
know p – for S must receive the right amount of information in a non-deviant
causal way and S must be able to extract the content of the information – but
this seems clearly necessary. Other measures of information of interest in
communication theory include the average information, or entropy, of a source,
information theory information theory 436 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page
436 I(s) % 9p(si) $ I(si), a measure for noise (the amount of information that
person B receives that was not sent by person A), and for equivocation (the
amount of information A wanted or tried to send to B that B did not receive).
These concepts from information theory and the formulas for measuring these
quantities of information (and others) provide a rich source of tools for
communication applications as well as philosophical applications. informed
consent, voluntary agreement in the light of relevant information, especially
by a patient to a medical procedure. An example would be consent to a specific
medical procedure by a competent adult patient who has an adequate
understanding of all the relevant treatment options and their risks. It is
widely held that both morality and law require that no medical procedures be
performed on competent adults without their informed consent. This doctrine of
informed consent has been featured in case laws since the 1950s, and has been a
focus of much discussion in medical ethics. Underwritten by a concern to
protect patients’ rights to self-determination and also by a concern with
patients’ well-being, the doctrine was introduced in an attempt to delineate
physicians’ duties to inform patients of the risks and benefits of medical
alternatives and to obtain their consent to a particular course of treatment or
diagnosis. Interpretation of the legitimate scope of the doctrine has focused
on a variety of issues concerning what range of patients is competent to give
consent and hence from which ones informed consent must be required; concerning
how much, how detailed, and what sort of information must be given to patients
to yield informed consent; and concerning what sorts of conditions are required
to ensure both that there is proper understanding of the information and that
consent is truly voluntary rather than unduly influenced by the institutional
authority of the physician.
ingarden: a leading phenomenologist,
who taught in Lvov and Cracow and became prominent in the English-speaking
world above all through his work in aesthetics and philosophy of literature.
His Literary Work of Art (German 1931, English 1973) presents an ontological
account of the literary work as a stratified structure, including word sounds
and meanings, represented objects and aspects, and associated metaphysical and
aesthetic qualities. The work forms part of a larger ontological project of combating
the transcendental idealism of his teacher Husserl, and seeks to establish the
essential difference in structure between minddependent ‘intentional’ objects
and objects in reality. Ingarden’s ontological investigations are set out in
his The Controversy over the Existence of the World (Polish 1947/48, German
1964–74, partial English translation as Time and Modes of Being, 1964). The
work rests on a tripartite division of formal, material, and existential
ontology and contains extensive analyses of the ontological structures of
individual things, events, processes, states of affairs, properties and
relations. It culminates in an attempted refutation of idealism on the basis of
an exhaustive account of the possible relations between consciousness and reality.
inscriptum -- inscriptionalism -- nominalism. While Grice pours scorn
on the American School of Latter-Day
Nominalists, nominalism, as used by Grice is possibly a misnomer. He
doesn’t mean Occam, and Occam did not use ‘nominalismus.’ “Terminimus’ at most.
So one has to be careful. The implicaturum is that the nominalist calls a
‘name’ what others shouldn’t. Mind,
Grice had two nominalist friends: S. N. Hamphsire (Scepticism and meaning”) and
A. M. Quinton, of the play group! In “Properties and classes,” for the
Aristotelian Society. And the best Oxford philosophical stylist, Bradley, is
also a nominalist. There are other, more specific arguments against universals.
One is that postulating such things leads to a vicious infinite regress. For
suppose there are universals, both monadic and relational, and that when an
entity instantiates a universal, or a group of entities instantiate a
relational universal, they are linked by an instantiation relation. Suppose now
that a instantiates
the universal F. Since
there are many things that instantiate many universals, it is plausible to
suppose that instantiation is a relational universal. But if instantiation is a
relational universal, when a instantiates F, a, F and
the instantiation relation are linked by an instantiation relation. Call this
instantiation relation i2 (and suppose it, as is plausible, to be
distinct from the instantiation relation (i1) that links a and F). Then
since i2 is
also a universal, it looks as if a, F, i1 and i2 will have to
be linked by another instantiation relation i3, and so on ad infinitum.
(This argument has its source in Bradley 1893, 27–8.)
insinuatum: Cf. ‘indirectum’ Oddly, Ryle found an ‘insinuation’
abusive, which Russell found abusive. When McGuinness listed the abusive terms
by Gellner, ‘insinuation’ was one of them, so perhaps Grice should take note! insinuation
insinuate. The etymology is abscure. Certainly not Ciceronian. A bit of
linguistic botany, “E implicates that p” – implicate to do duty for, in
alphabetic order: mean, suggest, hint, insinuate, indicate, implicitly convey,
indirectly convey, imply. Intransitive meaning "hint obliquely" is from
1560s. The problem is that Grice possibly used it transitively, with a
‘that’-clause. “Emissor E communicates that p, via insinuation,” i.e. E
insinuates that p.” In fact, there’s nothing odd with the ‘that’-clause
following ‘insinuate.’ Obviosuly, Grice will be saying that what is a mere
insinuation it is taken by Austin, Strawson, Hart or Hare or Hampshire – as he
criticizes him in the “Mind” article on intention and certainty -- (to restrict
to mistakes by the play group) as part of the ‘analysans.’ `Refs. D. Holdcroft,
“Forms of indirect communication,” Journal of Rhetoric, H. P. Grice,
“Communicatum: directum-indirectum.”
Swinehead: “I like
Swinehead – it sounds almost like Grice!” – Grice.
solubile -- insolubile: “As
opposed to the ‘piece-of-cake’ solubilia” – Grice. A solubile is a piece of a
cake. An insolubile is a sentences embodying a semantic antinomy such as the
liar paradox. The insolubile is used by philosophers to analyze a self-nullifying
sentences, the possibility that every sentence implies that they are true, and
the relation between a communicatum and an animatum (psi). At first, Grice
focuses on nullification to explicate a sentence like ‘I am lying’ (“Mento.”
“Mendax”) which, when spoken, entails that the utterer “says nothing.” Grice:
“Bradwardine suggests that such a sentence as “Mento” signifies that it is at
once true and false, prompting Burleigh to argue that every sentences implies
that it is true.” “Swineshead uses the insolubile to distinguish between truth and
correspondence to reality.” While ‘This sentence is false’ is itself false, it
corresponds to reality, while its contradiction, ‘This sentence is not false,’
does not, although the latter is also false. “Wyclif uses the insolubile to
describe the senses (or implicatura) in which a sentence can be true, which led
to his belief in the reality of logical beings or entities of reason, a central
tenet of his realism.” “d’Ailly uses the insolubile to explain how the animatum
(or soul) differs from the communicatum, holding that there is no insoluble in
the soul, but that communication lends itself to the phenomenon by admitting a
single sentence corresponding to two distinct states of the soul. Grice: “Of
course that was Swine’s unEnglish overstatement, ‘unsolvable;’ everything is
solvable!” Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Liars at Oxford.”
institutum – Grice speaks of
the institution of decision as the goal of conversation -- institution. (1) An
organization such as a corporation or college. (2) A social practice such as
marriage or making promises. (3) A system of rules defining a possible form of
social organization, such as capitalist versus Communist principles of economic
exchange. In light of the power of institutions to shape societies and
individual lives, writers in professional ethics have explored four main
issues. First, what political and legal institutions are feasible, just, and
otherwise desirable (Plato, Republic; Rawls, A Theory of Justice)? Second, how
are values embedded in institutions through the constitutive rules that define
them (for example, “To promise is to undertake an obligation”), as well as
through regulatory rules imposed on them from outside, such that to participate
in institutions is a value-laden activity (Searle, Speech Acts, 1969)? Third,
do institutions have collective responsibilities or are the only
responsibilities those of individuals, and in general how are the responsibilities
of individuals, institutions, and communities related? Fourth, at a more
practical level, how can we prevent institutions from becoming corrupted by
undue regard for money and power (MacIntyre, After Virtue, 1981) and by
patriarchal prejudices (Susan Moller Okin, Justice, Gender, and the Family,
1989)? -- institutional theory of art, the view that something becomes an
artwork by virtue of occupying a certain position within the context of a set
of institutions. George Dickie originated this theory of art (Art and the
Aesthetic, 1974), which was derived loosely from Arthur Danto’s “The Artworld”
(Journal of Philosophy, 1964). In its original form it was the view that a work
of art is an artifact that has the status of candidate for appreciation
conferred upon it by some person acting on behalf of the art world. That is,
there are institutions – such as museums, galleries, and journals and
newspapers that publish reviews and criticism – and there are individuals who
work within those institutions – curators, directors, dealers, performers,
critics – who decide, by accepting objects or events for discussion and
display, what is art and what is not. The concept of artifactuality may be
extended to include found art, conceptual art, and other works that do not
involve altering some preexisting material, by holding that a use, or context
for display, is sufficient to make something into an artifact. This definition
of art raises certain questions. What determines – independently of such
notions as a concern with art – whether an institution is a member of the art
world? That is, is the definition ultimately circular? What is it to accept
something as a candidate for appreciation? Might not this concept also threaten
circularity, since there could be not only artistic but also other kinds of
appreciation?
instrumentum:
is
Grice an instrumentalist? According to C. Lord (“Griceian instrumentalism”) he
is – but he is not! Lord takes ‘tool’ literally. In Grice’s analysandum of the
act of the communicatum, Lord takes ‘x’ to be a ‘tool’ or instrument for the
production of a response in the emisor’s sendee. But is this the original Roman
meaning of ‘instrumentum’? Griceian aesthetic instrumetalism according to
Catherine Lord. instrumentalism, in its most common meaning, a kind of
anti-realistic view of scientific theories wherein theories are construed as
calculating devices or instruments for conveniently moving from a given set of
observations to a predicted set of observations. As such the theoretical statements
are not candidates for truth or reference, and the theories have no ontological
import. This view of theories is grounded in a positive distinction between
observation statements and theoretical statements, and the according of
privileged epistemic status to the former. The view was fashionable during the
era of positivism but then faded; it was recently revived, in large measure
owing to the genuinely perplexing character of quantum theories in physics.
’Instrumentalism’ has a different and much more general meaning associated with
the pragmatic epistemology of Dewey. Deweyan instrumentalism is a general
functional account of all concepts (scientific ones included) wherein the
epistemic status of concepts and the rationality status of actions are seen as
a function of their role in integrating, predicting, and controlling our
concrete interactions with our experienced world. There is no positivistic
distinction instantiation instrumentalism 438 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM
Page 438 between observation and theory, and truth and reference give way to
“warranted assertability.”
intellectum: hile the ‘dianoia’ is the intellectus, the ‘intellectum’
is the Griceian diaphanous ‘what is understood.’ (dianoia): Grice was
fascinated by Cicero. “The way he managed to translate the Grecian ‘dia’ by the
‘inter is genial!” As Short and Lewis have it, it’s from
“inter-legere,” to see into, perceive, understand. “intelligere,” originally meaning to comprehend, appeared
frequently in Cicero, then underwent a slippage in its passive form,
“intelligetur,” toward to understand, to communicate, to mean, ‘to give it to
be understood.’ What is understood – INTELLECTUM -- by an expression can be not
only its obvious sense but also something that is connoted, implied, insinuated,
IMPLICATED, as Grice would prefer. Verstand, corresponding to Greek dianoia and
Latin intellectio] Kant distinguished understanding from sensibility and
reason. While sensibility is receptive, understanding is spontaneous. While
understanding is concerned with the range of phenomena and is empty without
intuition, reason, which moves from judgment to judgment concerning phenomena,
is tempted to extend beyond the limits of experience to generate fallacious
inferences. Kant claimed that the main act of understanding is judgment and
called it a faculty of judgment. He claimed that there is an a priori concept
or category corresponding to each kind of judgment as its logical function and
that understanding is constituted by twelve categories. Hence understanding is
also a faculty of concepts. Understanding gives the synthetic unity of
appearance through the categories. It thus brings together intuitions and
concepts and makes experience possible. It is a lawgiver of nature. Herder
criticized Kant for separating sensibility and understanding. Fichte and Hegel
criticized him for separating understanding and reason. Some neo-Kantians
criticized him for deriving the structure of understanding from the act of
judgment. “Now we can reduce all acts of the understanding to judgements, and
the understanding may therefore be represented as a faculty of judgement.”
Kant, Critique of Pure Reason Intellectus -- dianoia, Grecian term for the faculty
of thought, specifically of drawing conclusions from assumptions and of constructing
and following arguments. The term may also designate the thought that results
from using this faculty. We would use dianoia to construct a mathematical
proof; in contrast, a being if there is
such a being it would be a god that
could simply intuit the truth of the theorem would use the faculty of
intellectual intuition, noûs. In contrast with noûs, dianoia is the distinctly
human faculty of reason. Plato uses noûs and dianoia to designate,
respectively, the highest and second levels of the faculties represented on the
divided line Republic 511de. PLATO.
E.C.H. dialectical argument dianoia 233
233 dichotomy paradox. Refs: Grice, “The criteria of intelligence.”
intensionalism: Grice finds a way to relieve a predicate that is vacuous
from the embarrassing consequence of denoting or being satisfied by the empty
set. Grice exploits the nonvoidness of a predicate which is part of the
definition of the void predicate. Consider the vacuous predicate:‘... is
married to a daughter of an English queen and a pope.'The class '... is a
daugther of an English queen and a pope.'is co-extensive with the
predicate '... stands in relation to a sequence composed of the
class married to, daughters, English queens, and popes.'We correlate the
void predicate with the sequence composed of relation R, the set ‘married
to,’ the set ‘daughters,’ the set ‘English queens,’ and the set ‘popes.'Grice
uses this sequence, rather than the empty set, to determine the explanatory
potentiality of a void predicate. The admissibility of a nonvoid predicate
in an explanation of a possible phenomenon (why it would happen if it did
happen) may depends on the availability of a generalisation whithin which the
predicate specifies the antecedent condition. A non-trivial generalisations
of this sort is certainly available if derivable from some further
generalisation involving a less specific antecedent condition, supported by an
antecedent condition that is specified by means a nonvoid predicate. intension, the
meaning or connotation of an expression, as opposed to its extension or
denotation, which consists of those things signified by the expression. The
intension of a declarative sentence is often taken to be a proposition and the
intension of a predicate expression (common noun, adjective) is often taken to
be a concept. For Frege, a predicate expression refers to a concept and the
intension or Sinn (“sense”) of a predicate expression is a mode of presentation
distinct from the concept. Objects like propositions or concepts that can be the
intension of terms are called intensional objects. (Note that ‘intensional’ is
not the same word as ‘intentional’, although the two are related.) The
extension of a declarative sentence is often taken to be a state of affairs and
that of a predicate expression to be the set of objects that fall under the
concept which is the intension of the term. Extension is not the same as
reference. For example, the term ‘red’ may be said to refer to the property
redness but to have as its extension the set of all red things. Alternatively
properties and relations are sometimes taken to be intensional objects, but the
property redness is never taken to be part of the extension of the adjective
‘red’. intensionality, failure of extensionality. A linguistic context is extensional
if and only if the extension of the expression obtained by placing any
subexpression in that context is the same as the extension of the expression
obtained by placing in that context any subexpression with the same extension
as the first subexpression. Modal, intentional, and direct quotational contexts
are main instances of intensional contexts. Take, e.g., sentential contexts.
The extension of a sentence is its truth or falsity (truth-value). The
extension of a definite description is what it is true of: ‘the husband of
Xanthippe’ and ‘the teacher of Plato’ have the same extension, for they are
true of the same man, Socrates. Given this, it is easy to see that
‘Necessarily, . . . was married to Xanthippe’ is intensional, for ‘Necessarily,
the husband of Xanthippe was married to Xanthippe’ is true, but ‘Necessarily,
the teacher of Plato was married to Xanthippe’ is not. Other modal terms that
generate intensional contexts include ‘possibly’, ‘impossibly’, ‘essentially’,
‘contingently’, etc. Assume that Smith has heard of Xanthippe but not Plato.
‘Smith believes that . . . was married to Xanthippe’ is intensional, for ‘Smith
believes that the husband of Xanthippe was married to Xanthippe’ is true, but
‘Smith believes that the teacher of Plato was married to Xanthippe’ is not.
Other intentional verbs that generate intensional contexts include ‘know’,
‘doubt’, ‘wonder’, ‘fear’, ‘intend’, ‘state’, and ‘want’. ‘The fourth word in
“. . . “ has nine letters’ is intensional, for ‘The fourth word in “the husband
of Xanthippe” has nine letters’ is true but ‘the fourth word in “the teacher of
Plato” has nine letters’ is not. intensional logic, that part of deductive
logic which treats arguments whose validity or invalidity depends on strict
difference, or identity, of meaning. The denotation of a singular term (i.e., a
proper name or definite description), the class of things of which a predicate
is true, and the truth or falsity (the truth-value) of a sentence may be called
the extensions of these respective linguistic expressions. Their intensions are
their meanings strictly so called: the (individual) concept conveyed by the
singular term, the property expressed by the predicate, and the proposition
asserted by the sentence. The most extensively studied part of formal logic
deals largely with inferences turning only on extensions. One principle of
extensional logic is that if two singular terms have identical denotations, the
truth-values of corresponding sentences containing the terms are identical.
Thus the inference from ‘Bern is the capital of Switzerland’ to ‘You are in
Bern if and only if you are in the capital of Switzerland’ is valid. But this
is invalid: ‘Bern is the capital of Switzerland. Therefore, you believe that
you are in Bern if and only if you believe that you are in the capital of
Switzerland.’ For one may lack the belief instrumental rationality intensional
logic 439 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 439 that Bern is the capital of
Switzerland. It seems that we should distinguish between the intensional
meanings of ‘Bern’ and of ‘the capital of Switzerland’. One supposes that only
a strict identity of intension would license interchange in such a context, in
which they are in the scope of a propositional attitude. It has been questioned
whether the idea of an intension really applies to proper names, but parallel
examples are easily constructed that make similar use of the differences in the
meanings of predicates or of whole sentences. Quite generally, then, the
principle that expressions with the same extension may be interchanged with
preservation of extension of the containing expression, seems to fail for such
“intensional contexts.” The range of expressions producing such sensitive
contexts includes psychological verbs like ‘know’, ‘believe’, ‘suppose’,
‘assert’, ‘desire’, ‘allege’, ‘wonders whether’; expressions conveying modal
ideas such as necessity, possibility, and impossibility; some adverbs, e.g.
‘intentionally’; and a large number of other expressions – ’prove’, ‘imply’,
‘make probable’, etc. Although reasoning involving some of these is well
understood, there is not yet general agreement on the best methods for dealing
with arguments involving many of these notions.
intentionalism: Grice analyses ‘intend’ in two prongs; the first is a
willing-clause, and the second is a causal clause about the willing causing the
action. It’s a simplified account that he calls Prichardian because he relies
on ‘willin that.’ The intender intends that some action takes place. It does
not have to be an action by the intender. Cf. Suppes’s specific section. when
Anscombe comes out with her “Intention,” Grice’s Play Group does not know what
to do. Hampshire is almost finished with his “Thought and action” that came out
the following year. Grice is lecturing on how a “dispositional” reductive
analysis of ‘intention’ falls short of his favoured instrospectionalism. Had he
not fallen for an intention-based semantics (or strictly, an analysis of
"U means that p" in terms of U intends that p"), Grice
would be obsessed with an analysis of ‘intending that …’ James makes an
observation about the that-clause. I will that the distant table slides over
the floor toward me. It does not. The Anscombe Society. Irish-born Anscombe’s
views are often discussed by Oxonian philosophers. She brings Witters to the
Dreaming Spires, as it were. Grice is especially connected with Anscombes
reflections on intention. While he favoures an approach such as that of
Hampshire in Thought and Action, Grice borrows a few points from Anscombe, notably
that of direction of fit, originally Austin’s. Grice explicitly refers to
Anscombe in “Uncertainty,” and in his reminiscences he hastens to add that
Anscombe would never attend any of the Saturday mornings of the play group, as
neither does Dummett. The view of Ryle is standardly characterised as a
weaker or softer version of behaviourism According to this standard
interpretation, the view by Ryle is that a statements containin this or that
term relating to the ‘soul’ can be translated, without loss of meaning, into an
‘if’ utterance about what an agent does. So Ryle, on this account, is to be
construed as offering a dispositional analysis of a statement about the soul
into a statement about behaviour. It is conceded that Ryle does not confine a description
of what the agent does to purely physical behaviour—in terms, e. g. of a skeletal
or a muscular description. Ryle is happy to speak of a full-bodied action like
scoring a goal or paying a debt. But the soft behaviourism attributed to Ryle
still attempts an analysis or translation of statement about the soul into this
or that dispositional statement which is itself construed as subjunctive if
describing what the agent does. Even this soft behaviourism fails. A
description of the soul is not analysable or translatable into a statement
about behaviour or praxis even if this is allowed to include a
non-physical descriptions of action. The list of conditions and possible
behaviour is infinite since any one proffered translation may be ‘defeated,’ as
Hart and Hall would say, by a slight alteration of the circumstances. The
defeating condition in any particular case may involve a reference to a fact
about the agent’s soul, thereby rendering the analysis circular. In sum, the
standard interpretation of Ryle construes him as offering a somewhat weakened
form of reductive behaviourism whose reductivist ambition, however weakened, is
nonetheless futile. This characterisation of Ryle’s programme is wrong. Although
it is true that he is keen to point out the disposition behind this or that
concept about the soul, it would be wrong to construe Ryle as offering a
programme of analysis of a ‘soul’ predicate in terms of an ‘if’ utterance. The
relationship between a ‘soul’ predicate and the ‘if’ utterance with which he
unpack it is other than that required by this kind of analysis. It is helpful
to keep in mind that Ryle’s target is the official doctrine with its
eschatological commitment. Ryle’s argument serves to remind one that we have in
a large number of cases ways of telling or settling disputes, e. g., about
someone’s character or intellect. If A disputes a characterisation of Smith as
willing that p, or judging that p, B may point to what Smith says and does in
defending the attribution, as well as to features of the circumstances. But the
practice of giving a reason of this kind to defend or to challenge an
ascription of a ‘soul’ predicates would be put under substantial pressure if
the official doctrine is correct. For Ryle to remind us that we do, as a
matter of fact, have a way of settling disputes about whether Smith wills that
he eat an apple is much weaker than saying that the concept of willing is
meaningless unless it is observable or verifiable; or even that the successful
application of a soul predicate requires that we have a way of settling a
dispute in every case. Showing that a concept is one for which, in a large
number of cases, we have an agreement-reaching procedure, even if it do not
always guarantee success, captures an important point, however: it counts
against any theory of, e. g., willing that would render it unknowable in
principle or in practice whether or not the concept is correctly applied
in every case. And this is precisely the problem with the official doctrine
(and is still a problem, with some of its progeny. Ryle points out that there
is a form of dilemma that pits the reductionist against
the dualist: those whose battle-cry is ‘nothing but…’ and those who insist
on ‘something else as well.’ Ryle attempts a dissolution of the dilemma by
rejecting the two horns; not by taking sides with either one, though part of
what dissolution requires in this case, as in others, is a description of how
each side is to be commended for seeing what the other side does not, and
criticised for failing to see what the other side does. The attraction of
behaviourism, Ryle reminds us, is simply that it does not insist on an occult
happening as the basis upon which a ‘soul’ term is given meaning, and points to
a perfectly observable criterion that is by and large employed when we are
called upon to defend or correct our employment of a ‘soul’ term. The problem
with behaviourism is that it has a too-narrow view both of what counts as
behaviour and of what counts as observable. Then comes Grice to play with meaning
and intending, and allowing for deeming an avowal of this or that souly state as,
in some fashion, incorrigible. For Grice, while U does have, ceteris paribus
privileged access to each state of his soul, only his or that avowal of this or
that souly state is deemed incorrigible. This concerns communication as
involving intending. Grice goes back to this at Brighton. He plays with G
judges that it is raining, G judges that G judges that it is raining. Again,
Grice uses a subscript: “G judges2 that it is raining.” If now G
expresses that it is raining, G judges2 that it is raining. A
second-order avowal is deemed incorrigible. It is not surprising the the
contemporary progeny of the official doctrine sees a behaviourist in Grice. Yet
a dualist is badly off the mark in his critique of Grice. While Grice does
appeal to a practice and a habif, and even the more technical ‘procedure’ in
the ordinary way as ‘procedure’ is used in ordinary discussion. Grice does not
make a technical concept out of them as one expect of some behavioural
psychologist, which he is not. He is at most a philosophical psychologist, and
a functionalist one, rather than a reductionist one. There is nothing in any
way that is ‘behaviourist’ or reductionist or physicalist about Grice’s talk.
It is just ordinary talk about behaviour. There is nothing exceptional in
talking about a practice, a customs, or a habit regarding communication. Grice
certainly does not intend that this or that notion, as he uses it, gives anything
like a detailed account of the creative open-endedness of a
communication-system. What this or that anti-Griceian has to say IS essentially
a diatribe first against empiricism (alla Quine), secondarily against a
Ryle-type of behaviourism, and in the third place, Grice. In more reasoned and
dispassionate terms, one would hardly think of Grice as a behaviourist (he in
fact rejects such a label in “Method”), but as an intentionalist. When we call
Grice an intentionalist, we are being serious. As a modista, Grice’s keyword is
intentionalism, as per the good old scholastic ‘intentio.’ We hope so. This is
Aunt Matilda’s conversational knack. Grice keeps a useful correspondence with
Suppes which was helpful. Suppes takes Chomsky more seriously than an Oxonian
philosopher would. An Oxonian philosopher never takes Chomsky too seriously. Granted,
Austin loves to quote “Syntactic Structures” sentence by sentence for fun,
knowing that it would never count as tutorial material. Surely “Syntactic
Structures” would not be a pamphlet a member of the play group would use to
educate his tutee. It is amusing that when he gives the Locke lectures, Chomsky
cannot not think of anything better to do but to criticise Grice, and citing him
from just one reprint in the collection edited by, of all people, Searle. Some
gratitude. The references are very specific to Grice. Grice feels he needs to
provide, he thinks, an analysis ‘mean’ as metabolically applied to an expression.
Why? Because of the implicaturum. By uttering x (thereby explicitly conveying
that p), U implicitly conveys that q iff U relies on some procedure in his and
A’s repertoire of procedures of U’s and A’s communication-system. It is this
talk of U’s being ‘ready,’ and ‘having a procedure in his repertoire’ that
sounds to New-World Chomsky too Morrisian, as it does not to an Oxonian.
Suppes, a New-Worlder, puts himself in Old-Worlder Grice’s shoes about this. Chomsky
should never mind. When an Oxonian philosopher, not a psychologist, uses ‘procedure’
and ‘readiness,’ and having a procedure in a repertoire, he is being Oxonian
and not to be taken seriously, appealing to ordinary language, and so on.
Chomsky apparently does get it. Incidentally, Suppess has defended Grice
against two other targets, less influential. One is Hungarian-born J. I. Biro,
who does not distinguish between reductive analysis and reductionist analysis,
as Grice does in his response to Somervillian Rountree-Jack. The other target
is perhaps even less influential: P. Yu in a rather simplistic survey of the
Griceian programme for a journal that Grice finds too specialized to count, “Linguistics
and Philosophy.” Grice is always ashamed and avoided of being described as “our
man in the philosophy of language.” Something that could only have happened in
the Old World in a red-brick university, as Grice calls it. Suppes contributes to PGRICE with an
excellent ‘The primacy of utterers meaning,’ where he addresses what he rightly
sees as an unfair characterisations of Grice as a behaviourist. Suppes’s use of
“primacy” is genial, since its metabole which is all about. Biro actually responds
to Suppes’s commentary on Grice as proposing a reductive but not reductionist
analysis of meaning. Suppes rightly characterises Grice as an Oxonian ‘intentionalist’
(alla Ogden), as one would characterize Hampshire, with philosophical
empiricist, and slightly idealist, or better ideationalist, tendencies, rather.
Suppes rightly observes that Grice’ use of such jargon is meant to impress.
Surely there are more casual ways of referring to this or that utterer having a
basic procedure in his repertoire. It is informal and colloquial, enough,
though, rather than behaviouristically, as Ryle would have it. Grice is very
happy that in the New World Suppes teaches him how to use ‘primacy’ with a
straight face! Intentionalism is also all the vogue in Collingwood reading
Croce, and Gardiner reading Marty via Ogden, and relates to expression. In his
analysis of intending Grice is being very Oxonian, and pre-Austinian: relying,
just to tease leader Austin, on Stout, Wilson, Bosanquet, MacMurray, and
Pritchard. Refs.: There are two sets of essays. An early one on ‘disposition
and intention,’ and the essay for The British Academy (henceforth, BA). Also
his reply to Anscombe and his reply to Davidson. There is an essay on the
subjective condition on intention. Obviously, his account of communication has
been labeled the ‘intention-based semantic’ programme, so references under
‘communication’ above are useful. BANC.Grice's reductIOn, or partial reduction
anyway, of meamng to intention places a heavy load on the theory of intentions.
But in the articles he has written about these matters he has not been very
explicit about the structure of intentIOns. As I understand his position on
these matters, it is his view that the defence of the primacy of utterer's
meaning does not depend on having worked out any detailed theory of intention.
It IS enough to show how the reduction should be thought of in a schematic
fashion in order to make a convincing argument. I do think there is a fairly
straightforward extenSIOn of Grice's ideas that provides the right way of
developing a theory of intentIOns appropnate for Ius theory of utterer's
meaning. Slightly changing around some of the words m Grice we have the
following The Primacy of Utterer's Meaning 125 example. U utters '''Fido is
shaggy", if "U wants A to think that U thinks that Jones's dog is
hairy-coated.'" Put another way, U's intention is to want A to think U
thinks that Jones's dog is hairy-coated. Such intentions clearly have a
generative structure similar but different from the generated syntactic
structure we think of verbal utterances' having. But we can even say that the
deep structures talked about by grammarians of Chomsky's ilk could best be
thought of as intentions. This is not a suggestion I intend to pursue
seriously. The important point is that it is a mistake to think about
classifications of intentions; rather, we should think in terms of mechanisms
for generating intentions. Moreover, it seems to me that such mechanisms in the
case of animals are evident enough as expressed in purposeful pursuit of prey
or other kinds of food, and yet are not expressed in language. In that sense
once again there is an argument in defence of Grice's theory. The primacy of utterer's
meaning has primacy because of the primacy of intention. We can have intentions
without words, but we cannot have words of any interest without intentions. In
this general context, I now turn to Biro's (1979) interesting criticisms of
intentionalism in the theory of meaning. Biro deals from his own standpoint
with some of the issues I have raised already, but his central thesis about
intention I have not previously discussed. It goes to the heart of
controversies about the use of the concept of intention to explain the meaning
of utterances. Biro puts his point in a general way by insisting that utterance
meaning must be separate from and independent of speaker's meaning or, in the
terminology used here, utterer's meaning. The central part of his argument is
his objection to the possibility of explaining meaning in terms of intentions.
Biro's argument goes like this: 1. A central purpose of speech is to enable
others to learn about the speaker's intentions. 2. It will be impossible to
discover or understand the intentions of the speaker unless there are
independent means for understanding what he says, since what he says will be
primary evidence about his intentions. 3. Thus the meaning of an utterance must
be conceptually independent of the intentions of the speaker. This is an
appealing positivistic line. The data relevant to a theory or hypothesis must
be known independently of the hypothesis. Biro is quick to state that he is not
against theoretical entities, but the way in which he separates theoretical
entities and observable facts makes clear the limited role he wants them to
play, in this case the theoretical entities being intentions. The central idea
is to be found in the following passage: The point I am insisting on here is
merely that the ascription of an intention to an agent has the character of an
hypothesis, something invoked to explain phenomena which may be described
independently of that explanation (though not necessarily independently of the
fact that they fall into a class for which the hypothesis in question generally
or normally provides an explanation). (pp. 250-1.) [The italics are Biro's.]
Biro's aim is clear from this quotation. The central point is that the data
about intentions, namely, the utterance, must be describable independently of
hypotheses about the intentions. He says a little later to reinforce this: 'The
central pointis this: it is the intention-hypothesis that is revisable, not the
act-description' (p. 251). Biro's central mistake, and a large one too, is to
think that data can be described independently of hypotheses and that somehow
there is a clean and simple version of data that makes such description a
natural and inevitable thing to have. It would be easy enough to wander off
into a description of such problems in physics, where experiments provide a
veritable wonderland of seemingly arbitrary choices about what to include and
what to exclude from the experimental experience as 'relevant data', and where
the arbitrariness can only be even partly understood on the basis of
understanding the theories bemg tested. Real data do not come in simple linear
strips like letters on the page. Real experiments are blooming confusions that
never get sorted out completely but only partially and schematically, as
appropriate to the theory or theories being tested, and in accordance with the
traditions and conventions of past similar experiments. makes a point about the
importance of convention that I agree but it is irrelevant to my central of
controversy with What I say about
experiments is even more true of undisciplined and unregulated human
interactiono Experiments, especially in physics, are presumably among the best
examples of disciplined and structured action. Most conversations, in contrast,
are really examples of situations of confusion that are only straightened out
under strong hypotheses of intentions on the of speakers and listeners as well.
There is more than one level at which the takes The Primacy of Utterer's
Meaning 127 place through the beneficent use of hypotheses about intentions. I
shall not try to deal with all of them here but only mention some salient
aspects. At an earlier point, Biro says:The main reason for introducing
intentions into some of these analyses is precisely that the public (broadly
speaking) features of utterances -the sounds made, the circumstances in which
they are made and the syntactic and semantic properties of these noises
considered as linguistic items-are thought to be insufficient for the
specification of that aspect of the utterance which we call its meaning. [po
244.] If we were to take this line of thought seriously and literally, we would
begin with the sound pressure waves that reach our ears and that are given the
subtle and intricate interpretation required to accept them as speech. There is
a great variety of evidence that purely acoustical concepts are inadequate for
the analysis of speech. To determine the speech content of a sound pressure
wave we need extensive hypotheses about the intentions that speakers have in
order to convert the public physical features of utterances into intentional
linguistic items. Biro might object at where I am drawing the line between
public and intentional, namely, at the difference between physical and
linguistic, but it would be part of my thesis that it is just because of
perceived and hypothesized intentions that we are mentally able to convert
sound pressure waves into meaningful speech. In fact, I can envisage a kind of
transcendental argument for the existence of intentions based on the
impossibility from the standpoint of physics alone of interpreting sound
pressure waves as speech. Biro seems to have in mind the nice printed sentences
of science and philosophy that can be found on the printed pages of treatises
around the world. But this is not the right place to begin to think about
meaning, only the end point. Grice, and everybody else who holds an intentional
thesis about meaning, recognizes the requirement to reach an account of such
timeless sentence meaning or linguistic meaning.In fact, Grice is perhaps more
ready than I am to concede that such a theory can be developed in a relatively
straightforward manner. One purpose of my detailed discussion of congruence of
meaning in the previous section is to point out some of the difficulties of
having an adequate detailed theory of these matters, certainly an adequate
detailed theory of the linguistic meaning or the sentence meaning. Even if I
were willing to grant the feasibility of such a theory, I would not grant the
use of it that Biro has made. For the purposes of this discussion printed text
may be accepted as well-defined, theoryindependent data. (There are even issues
to be raised about the printed page, but ones that I will set aside in the
present context. I have in mind the psychological difference between perception
of printed letters, words, phrases, or sentences, and that of related but
different nonlinguistic marks on paper.) But no such data assumptions can be
made about spoken speech. Still another point of attack on Biro's positivistic
line about data concerns the data of stress and prosody and their role in
fixing the meaning of an utterance. Stress and prosody are critical to the
interpretation of the intentions of speakers, but the data on stress and
prosody are fleeting and hard to catch on the fly_ Hypotheses about speakers'
intentions are needed even in the most humdrum interpret atins of what a given
prosodic contour or a given point of stress has contributed to the meaning of
the utterance spoken. The prosodic contour and the points of stress of an
utterance are linguistic data, but they do not have the independent physical
description Biro vainly hopes for. Let me put my point still another way. I do
not deny for a second that conventions and traditions of speech play a role in
fixing the meaning of a particular utterance on a particular occasion. It is
not a matter of interpretmg afresh, as if the universe had just begun, a
particular utterance in terms of particular intentions at that time and place
without dependence upon past prior mtentions and the traditions of spoken
speech that have evolved in the community of which the speaker and listener are
a part. It is rather that hypotheses about intentions are operating continually
and centrally in the interpretation of what is said. Loose, live speech depends
upon such active 'on-line' interpretation of intention to make sense of what
has been said. If there were some absolutely agreed-upon concept of firm and
definite linguistlc meaning that Biro and others could appeal to, then it might
be harder to make the case I am arguing for. But I have already argued in the
discussion of congruence of meaning that this is precisely what is not the
case. The absence of any definite and satisfactory theory of linguistic meaning
argues also for movmg back to the more concrete and psychologically richer
concept of utterer's meaning. This is the place to begin the theory of meaning,
and this Itself rests to a very large extent on the concept of intention --
intention, (1) a characteristic of action, as when one acts intentionally or
with a certain intention; (2) a feature of one’s mind, as when one intends (has
an intention) to act in a certain way now or in the future. Betty, e.g.,
intentionally walks across the room, does so with the intention of getting a
drink, and now intends to leave the party later that night. An important
question is: how are (1) and (2) related? (See Anscombe, Intention, 1963, for a
groundbreaking treatment of these and other basic problems concerning intention.)
Some philosophers see acting with an intention as basic and as subject to a
three-part analysis. For Betty to walk across the room with the intention of
getting a drink is for Betty’s walking across the room to be explainable (in
the appropriate way) by her desire or (as is sometimes said) pro-attitude in
favor of getting a drink and her belief that walking across the room is a way
of getting one. On this desire-belief model (or wantbelief model) the main
elements of acting with an intention are (a) the action, (b) appropriate
desires (pro-attitudes) and beliefs, and (c) an appropriate explanatory
relation between (a) and (b). (See Davidson, “Actions, Reasons, and Causes” in
Essays on Actions and Events, 1980.) In explaining (a) in terms of (b) we give an
explanation of the action in terms of the agent’s purposes or reasons for so
acting. This raises the fundamental question of what kind of explanation this
is, and how it is related to explanation of Betty’s movements by appeal to
their physical causes. What about intentions to act in the future? Consider
Betty’s intention to leave the party later. Though the intended action is
later, this intention may nevertheless help explain some of Betty’s planning
and acting between now and then. Some philosophers try to fit such
futuredirected intentions directly into the desire-belief model. John Austin,
e.g., would identify Betty’s intention with her belief that she will leave
later because of her desire to leave (Lectures on Jurisprudence, vol. I, 1873).
Others see futuredirected intentions as distinctive attitudes, not to be
reduced to desires and/or beliefs. How is belief related to intention? One
question here is whether an intention to A requires a belief that one will A. A
second question is whether a belief that one will A in executing some intention
ensures that one intends to A. Suppose that Betty believes that by walking
across the room she will interrupt Bob’s conversation. Though she has no desire
to interrupt, she still proceeds across the room. Does she intend to interrupt
the conversation? Or is there a coherent distinction between what one intends
and what one merely expects to bring about as a result of doing what one
intends? One way of talking about such cases, due to Bentham (An Introduction
to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, 1789), is to say that Betty’s
walking across the room is “directly intentional,” whereas her interrupting the
conversation is only “obliquely intentional” (or indirectly intentional). --
intentional fallacy, the (purported) fallacy of holding that the meaning of a
work of art is fixed by the artist’s intentions. (Wimsatt and Beardsintensive
magnitude intentional fallacy 440 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 440 ley,
who introduced the term, also used it to name the [purported] fallacy that the
artist’s aims are relevant to determining the success of a work of art;
however, this distinct usage has not gained general currency.) Wimsatt and
Beardsley were formalists; they held that interpretation should focus purely on
the work of art itself and should exclude appeal to biographical information
about the artist, other than information concerning the private meanings the
artist attached to his words. Whether the intentional fallacy is in fact a
fallacy is a much discussed issue within aesthetics. Intentionalists deny that
it is: they hold that the meaning of a work of art is fixed by some set of the
artist’s intentions. For instance, Richard Wollheim (Painting as an Art) holds
that the meaning of a painting is fixed by the artist’s fulfilled intentions in
making it. Other intentionalists appeal not to the actual artist’s intentions,
but to the intentions of the implied or postulated artist, a construct of
criticism, rather than a real person. See also AESTHETIC FORMALISM, AESTHETICS,
INTENTION. B.Ga. intentionality, aboutness. Things that are about other things
exhibit intentionality. Beliefs and other mental states exhibit intentionality,
but so, in a derived way, do sentences and books, maps and pictures, and other
representations. The adjective ‘intentional’ in this philosophical sense is a
technical term not to be confused with the more familiar sense, characterizing
something done on purpose. Hopes and fears, for instance, are not things we do,
not intentional acts in the latter, familiar sense, but they are intentional
phenomena in the technical sense: hopes and fears are about various things. The
term was coined by the Scholastics in the Middle Ages, and derives from the
Latin verb intendo, ‘to point (at)’ or ‘aim (at)’ or ‘extend (toward)’.
Phenomena with intentionality thus point outside of themselves to something
else: whatever they are of or about. The term was revived by the
nineteenth-century philosopher and psychologist Franz Brentano, who claimed
that intentionality defines the distinction between the mental and the
physical; all and only mental phenomena exhibit intentionality. Since
intentionality is an irreducible feature of mental phenomena, and since no
physical phenomena could exhibit it, mental phenomena could not be a species of
physical phenomena. This claim, often called the Brentano thesis or Brentano’s
irreducibility thesis, has often been cited to support the view that the mind
cannot be the brain, but this is by no means generally accepted today. There was
a second revival of the term in the 1960s and 1970s by analytic philosophers,
in particular Chisholm, Sellars, and Quine. Chisholm attempted to clarify the
concept by shifting to a logical definition of intentional idioms, the terms
used to speak of mental states and events, rather than attempting to define the
intentionality of the states and events themselves. Intentional idioms include
the familiar “mentalistic” terms of folk psychology, but also their technical
counterparts in theories and discussions in cognitive science, ‘X believes that
p,’ and ‘X desires that q’ are paradigmatic intentional idioms, but according
to Chisholm’s logical definition, in terms of referential opacity (the failure
of substitutivity of coextensive terms salva veritate), so are such less
familiar idioms as ‘X stores the information that p’ and ‘X gives high priority
to achieving the state of affairs that q’. Although there continue to be deep
divisions among philosophers about the proper definition or treatment of the
concept of intentionality, there is fairly widespread agreement that it marks a
feature – aboutness or content – that is central to mental phenomena, and hence
a central, and difficult, problem that any theory of mind must solve.
intersubjective – Grice: “Who was
the first Grecian philosopher to philosophise on conversational
intersubjectivity? Surely Plato! Socrates is just his alter ego – and after
Aeschylus, there is always a ‘deuterogonist’”! conversational
intersubjectivity. Philosophical sociology – While Grice saw himself as a
philosophical psychologist, he would rather be seen dead than as a
philosophical sociologist – ‘intersubjective at most’! -- Comte: A. philosopher
and sociologist, the founder of positivism. He was educated in Paris at l’École
Polytechnique, where he briefly taught mathematics. He suffered from a mental
illness that occasionally interrupted his work. In conformity with empiricism,
Comte held that knowledge of the world arises from observation. He went beyond
many empiricists, however, in denying the possibility of knowledge of
unobservable physical objects. He conceived of positivism as a method of study
based on observation and restricted to the observable. He applied positivism
chiefly to science. He claimed that the goal of science is prediction, to be
accomplished using laws of succession. Explanation insofar as attainable has
the same structure as prediction. It subsumes events under laws of succession;
it is not causal. Influenced by Kant, he held that the causes of phenomena and
the nature of things-in-themselves are not knowable. He criticized metaphysics
for ungrounded speculation about such matters; he accused it of not keeping
imagination subordinate to observation. He advanced positivism for all the
sciences but held that each science has additional special methods, and has
laws not derivable by human intelligence from laws of other sciences. He
corresponded extensively with J. S. Mill, who Comte, Auguste Comte, Auguste
168 168 encouraged his work and
discussed it in Auguste Comte and Positivism 1865. Twentieth-century logical
positivism was inspired by Comte’s ideas. Comte was a founder of sociology,
which he also called social physics. He divided the science into two
branches statics and dynamics dealing
respectively with social organization and social development. He advocated a
historical method of study for both branches. As a law of social development,
he proposed that all societies pass through three intellectual stages, first
interpreting phenomena theologically, then metaphysically, and finally
positivistically. The general idea that societies develop according to laws of
nature was adopted by Marx. Comte’s most important work is his six-volume Cours
de philosophie positive Course in Positive Philosophy, 183042. It is an
encyclopedic treatment of the sciences that expounds positivism and culminates
in the introduction of sociology.
intervention -- intervening variable, in Grice’s
philosophical psychology, a state of an organism, person or, as Grice prefers,
a ‘pirot,’ (vide his ‘pirotology’) or ‘creature,’ postulated to explain the
pirot’s behaviour and defined in ‘functioanlist,’ Aristotelian terms of its
cause (perceptual input) and effect (the behavioural output to be explained by
attribution of a state of the ‘soul’) rather than its intrinsic properties. A
food drive or need for nuts, in a squarrel (as Grice calls his ‘Toby’) conceived
as an intervening variable, is defined in terms of the number of hours without
food (the cause) and the strength or robustness of efforts to secure it
(effect).. The squarrel’s feeling hungry (‘needing a nut), is no longer an
intrinsic property – the theoretical term ‘need’ is introduced in a ramseyified
sentence by describing – and it need not be co-related to a state in the brain
– since there is room for variable realisability. Grice sees at least three
reasons for postulating an intervening variable (like the hours without
nut-hobbling). First, time lapse between stimulus (perceptual input) and
behavioural output may be large, as when an animal – even a squirrel -- eats
food found hours earlier. Why did not the animal hobble the nut when it first
found it? Perhaps at the time of discovery, the squarrel had already eaten, so
food drive (the squarrel’s need) is reduced. Second, Toby may act differently
in the same sort of situation, as when Toby hobbles a nut at noon one day but
delay until sunset the next. Again, this may be because of variation in food
drive or the squarrel’s need. Third, behaviour may occur in the absence of
external stimulation or perceptual input, as when Toby forages for nut for the
winter. This, too, may be explained by the strength of the food drive or
squarrel’s need. An intervening variables has been viewed, as Grice notes
reviewing Oxonian philosophical psychology from Stout to Ryle via Prichard) depending
on the background theory, as a convenient ‘fiction’ (as Ramsey, qua theoretical
construct) or as a psychologically real state, or as a physically real state
with multiple realisability conditions. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Method in
philosophical psychology: from the banal to the bizarre,” in “The Conception of
value.”
intuitum: Grice: “At Oxford, the tutor
teaches to trust your ‘intuition’ – and will point to the cognateness of
‘tutor’ and ‘in-tuition’!” – tŭĕor , tuĭtus, 2 ( I.perf. only post-Aug.,
Quint. 5, 13, 35; Plin. Ep. 6, 29, 10; collat. form tūtus, in the part., rare,
Sall. J. 74, 3; Front. Strat. 2, 12, 13; but constantly in the P. a.; inf.
parag. tuerier, Plaut. Rud. 1, 4, 35; collat. form acc. to the 3d conj. tŭor ,
Cat. 20, 5; Stat. Th. 3, 151: “tuĕris,” Plaut. Trin. 3, 2, 82: “tuimur,” Lucr.
1, 300; 4, 224; 4, 449; “6, 934: tuamur,” id. 4, 361: “tuantur,” id. 4, 1004;
imper. tuĕre, id. 5, 318), v. dep. a. [etym. dub.], orig., to see, to look or gaze
upon, to watch, view; hence, pregn., to see or look to, to defend, protect,
etc.: tueri duo significat; unum ab aspectu, unde est Ennii illud: tueor te
senex? pro Juppiter! (Trag. v. 225 Vahl.); “alterum a curando ac tutela, ut cum
dicimus bellum tueor et tueri villam,” Varr. L. L. 7, § 12 Müll.
sq.—Accordingly, I. To look at, gaze at, behold, watch, view, regard, consider,
examine, etc. (only poet.; syn.: specto, adspicio, intueor): quam te post
multis tueor tempestatibus, Pac. ap. Non. 407, 32; 414, 3: “e tenebris, quae
sunt in luce, tuemur,” Lucr. 4, 312: “ubi nil aliud nisi aquam caelumque
tuentur,” id. 4, 434: “caeli templa,” id. 6, 1228 al.: “tuendo Terribiles
oculos, vultum, etc.,” Verg. A. 8, 265; cf. id. ib. 1, 713: “talia dicentem jam
dudum aversa tuetur,” id. ib. 4, 362: “transversa tuentibus hircis,” id. E. 3,
8: “acerba tuens,” looking fiercely, Lucr. 5, 33; cf. Verg. A. 9, 794: “torva,”
id. ib. 6, 467.— (β). With object-clause: “quod multa in terris fieri caeloque
tuentur (homines), etc.,” Lucr. 1, 152; 6, 50; 6, 1163.— II. Pregn., to look
to, care for, keep up, uphold, maintain, support, guard, preserve, defend,
protect, etc. (the predom. class. signif. of the word; cf.: “curo, conservo,
tutor, protego, defendo): videte, ne ... vobis turpissimum sit, id, quod
accepistis, tueri et conservare non posse,” Cic. Imp. Pomp. 5, 12: “ut quisque
eis rebus tuendis conservandisque praefuerat,” Cic. Verr. 2, 4, 63, 140:
“omnia,” id. N. D. 2, 23, 60: “mores et instituta vitae resque domesticas ac
familiares,” id. Tusc. 1, 1, 2: “societatem conjunctionis humanae munifice et
aeque,” id. Fin. 5, 23, 65: “concordiam,” id. Att. 1, 17, 10: rem et gratiam et
auctoritatem suam, id. Fam. 13, 49, 1: “dignitatem,” id. Tusc. 2, 21, 48: “L.
Paulus personam principis civis facile dicendo tuebatur,” id. Brut. 20, 80:
“personam in re publicā,” id. Phil. 8, 10, 29; cf.: tuum munus, Planc. ap. Cic.
Fam. 10, 11, 1: “tueri et sustinere simulacrum pristinae dignitatis,” Cic. Rab.
Post. 15, 41: “aedem Castoris P. Junius habuit tuendam,” to keep in good order,
Cic. Verr. 2, 1, 50, § 130; cf. Plin. Pan. 51, 1: “Bassum ut incustoditum nimis
et incautum,” id. Ep. 6, 29, 10: “libertatem,” Tac. A. 3, 27; 14, 60: “se,
vitam corpusque tueri,” to keep, preserve, Cic. Off. 1, 4, 11: “antea majores
copias alere poterat, nunc exiguas vix tueri potest,” id. Deiot. 8, 22: “se ac
suos tueri,” Liv. 5, 4, 5: “sex legiones (re suā),” Cic. Par. 6, 1, 45:
“armentum paleis,” Col. 6, 3, 3: “se ceteris armis prudentiae tueri atque
defendere,” to guard, protect, Cic. de Or. 1, 38, 172; cf.: “tuemini castra et
defendite diligenter,” Caes. B. C. 3, 94: “suos fines,” id. B. G. 4, 8:
“portus,” id. ib. 5, 8: “oppidum unius legionis praesidio,” id. B. C. 2, 23:
“oram maritimam,” id. ib. 3, 34: “impedimenta,” to cover, protect, Hirt. B. G.
8, 2.—With ab and abl.: “fines suos ab excursionibus et latrociniis,” Cic.
Deiot. 8, 22: “domum a furibus,” Phaedr. 3, 7, 10: mare ab hostibus, Auct. B.
Afr. 8, 2.—With contra: “quos non parsimoniā tueri potuit contra illius
audaciam,” Cic. Prov. Cons. 5, 11: “liberūm nostrorum pueritiam contra
inprobitatem magistratuum,” Cic. Verr. 2, 1, 58, § 153; Quint. 5, 13, 35; Plin.
20, 14, 54, § 152; Tac. A. 6, 47 (41).—With adversus: “tueri se adversus
Romanos,” Liv. 25, 11, 7: “nostra adversus vim atque injuriam,” id. 7, 31, 3:
“adversus Philippum tueri Athenas,” id. 31, 9, 3; 42, 46, 9; 42, 23, 6: “arcem
adversus tres cohortes tueri,” Tac. H. 3, 78; Just. 17, 3, 22; 43, 3, 4.—In
part. perf.: “Verres fortiter et industrie tuitus contra piratas Siciliam
dicitur,” Quint. 5, 13, 35 (al. tutatus): “Numidas in omnibus proeliis magis
pedes quam arma tuta sunt,” Sall. J. 74, 3.!*? 1. Act. form tŭĕo , ēre:
“censores vectigalia tuento,” Cic. Leg. 3, 3, 7: “ROGO PER SVPEROS, QVI ESTIS,
OSSA MEA TVEATIS,” Inscr. Orell. 4788.— 2. tŭĕor , ēri, in pass. signif.:
“majores nostri in pace a rusticis Romanis alebantur et in bello ab his
tuebantur,” Varr. R. R. 3, 1, 4; Lucr. 4, 361: “consilio et operā curatoris tueri
debet non solum patrimonium, sed et corpus et salus furiosi,” Dig. 27, 10, 7:
“voluntas testatoris ex bono et aequo tuebitur,” ib. 28, 3, 17.—Hence, tūtus ,
a, um, P. a. (prop. well seen to or guarded; hence), safe, secure, out of
danger (cf. securus, free from fear). A. Lit. (α). Absol.: “nullius res tuta,
nullius domus clausa, nullius vita saepta ... contra tuam cupiditatem,” Cic.
Verr. 2, 5, 15, § 39: “cum victis nihil tutum arbitrarentur,” Caes. B. G. 2,
28: “nec se satis tutum fore arbitratur,” Hirt. B. G. 8, 27; cf.: “me biremis
praesidio scaphae Tutum per Aegaeos tumultus Aura feret,” Hor. C. 3, 29, 63;
Ov. M. 8, 368: “tutus bos rura perambulat,” Hor. C. 4, 5, 17: “quis locus tam
firmum habuit praesidium, ut tutus esset?” Cic. Imp. Pomp. 11, 31: “mare tutum
praestare,” id. Fl. 13, 31: “sic existimabat tutissimam fore Galliam,” Hirt. B.
G. 8, 54: “nemus,” Hor. C. 1, 17, 5: “via fugae,” Cic. Caecin. 15, 44; cf.:
“commodior ac tutior receptus,” Caes. B. C. 1, 46: “perfugium,” Cic. Rep. 1, 4,
8: “tutum iter et patens,” Hor. C. 3, 16, 7: “tutissima custodia,” Liv. 31, 23,
9: “praesidio nostro pasci genus esseque tutum,” Lucr. 5, 874: “vitam
consistere tutam,” id. 6, 11: “tutiorem et opulentiorem vitam hominum reddere,”
Cic. Rep. 1, 2, 3: est et fideli tuta silentio Merces, secure, sure (diff. from
certa, definite, certain), Hor. C. 3, 2, 25: “tutior at quanto merx est in
classe secundā!” id. S. 1, 2, 47: “non est tua tuta voluntas,” not without
danger, Ov. M. 2, 53: “in audaces non est audacia tuta,” id. ib. 10, 544:
“externā vi non tutus modo rex, sed invictus,” Curt. 6, 7, 1: “vel tutioris
audentiae est,” Quint. 12, prooem. § 4: “ cogitatio tutior,” id. 10, 7, 19:
“fuit brevitas illa tutissima,” id. 10, 1, 39: “regnum et diadema tutum
Deferens uni,” i. e. that cannot be taken away, Hor. C. 2, 2, 21: male tutae
mentis Orestes, i. e. unsound, = male sanae, id. S. 2, 3, 137: quicquid habes,
age, Depone tutis auribus, qs. carefully guarded, i. e. safe, faithful, id. C.
1, 27, 18 (cf. the opp.: auris rimosa, id. S. 2, 6, 46).—Poet., with gen.:
“(pars ratium) tuta fugae,” Luc. 9, 346.— (β). With ab and abl.: tutus ab
insidiis inimici, Asin. ap. Cic. Fam. 10, 31, 2: “ab insidiis,” Hor. S. 2, 6,
117: “a periculo,” Caes. B. G. 7, 14: “ab hoste,” Ov. H. 11, 44: “ab hospite,”
id. M. 1, 144: “a conjuge,” id. ib. 8, 316: “a ferro,” id. ib. 13, 498: “a
bello, id. H. (15) 16, 344: ab omni injuriā,” Phaedr. 1, 31, 9.— (γ). With ad
and acc.: “turrim tuendam ad omnis repentinos casus tradidit,” Caes. B. C. 3,
39: “ad id, quod ne timeatur fortuna facit, minime tuti sunt homines,” Liv. 25,
38, 14: “testudinem tutam ad omnes ictus video esse,” id. 36, 32, 6.— (δ). With
adversus: “adversus venenorum pericula tutum corpus suum reddere,” Cels. 5, 23,
3: “quo tutiores essent adversus ictus sagittarum,” Curt. 7, 9, 2: “loci
beneficio adversus intemperiem anni tutus est,” Sen. Ira, 2, 12, 1: “per quem
tutior adversus casus steti,” Val. Max. 4, 7, ext. 2: “quorum praesidio tutus
adversus hostes esse debuerat,” Just. 10, 1, 7.—(ε) With abl.: incendio fere tuta
est Alexandria, Auct. B. Alex. 1, 3.— b. Tutum est, with a subj. -clause, it is
prudent or safe, it is the part of a prudent man: “si dicere palam parum tutum
est,” Quint. 9, 2, 66; 8, 3, 47; 10, 3, 33: “o nullis tutum credere blanditiis,”
Prop. 1, 15, 42: “tutius esse arbitrabantur, obsessis viis, commeatu intercluso
sine ullo vulnere victoriā potiri,” Caes. B. G. 3, 24; Quint. 7, 1, 36; 11, 2,
48: “nobis tutissimum est, auctores plurimos sequi,” id. 3, 4, 11; 3, 6, 63.—
2. As subst.: tūtum , i, n., a place of safety, a shelter, safety, security:
Tr. Circumspice dum, numquis est, Sermonem nostrum qui aucupet. Th. Tutum probe
est, Plaut. Most. 2, 2, 42: “tuta et parvula laudo,” Hor. Ep. 1, 15, 42:
“trepidum et tuta petentem Trux aper insequitur,” Ov. M. 10, 714: “in tuto ut
collocetur,” Ter. Heaut. 4, 3, 11: “esse in tuto,” id. ib. 4, 3, 30: “ut sitis
in tuto,” Cic. Fam. 12, 2, 3: “in tutum eduxi manipulares meos,” Plaut. Most.
5, 1, 7: “in tutum receptus est,” Liv. 2, 19, 6.— B. Transf., watchful,
careful, cautious, prudent (rare and not ante-Aug.; “syn.: cautus, prudens):
serpit humi tutus nimium timidusque procellae,” Hor. A. P. 28: “tutus et intra
Spem veniae cautus,” id. ib. 266: “non nisi vicinas tutus ararit aquas,” Ov.
Tr. 3, 12, 36: “id suā sponte, apparebat, tuta celeribus consiliis
praepositurum,” Liv. 22, 38, 13: “celeriora quam tutiora consilia magis
placuere ducibus,” id. 9, 32, 3.—Hence, adv. in two forms, tūtē and tūtō ,
safely, securely, in safety, without danger. a. Posit. (α). Form tute (very
rare): “crede huic tute,” Plaut. Trin. 1, 2, 102: “eum tute vivere, qui honeste
vivat,” Auct. Her. 3, 5, 9: “tute cauteque agere,” id. ib. 3, 7, 13.— (β). Form
tuto (class. in prose and poetry): “pervenire,” Plaut. Mil. 2, 2, 70; Lucr. 1,
179: “dimicare,” Caes. B. G. 3, 24: “tuto et libere decernere,” id. B. C. 1, 2:
“ut tuto sim,” in security, Cic. Fam. 14, 3, 3: “ut tuto ab repentino hostium
incursu etiam singuli commeare possent,” Caes. B. G. 7, 36. — b. Comp.: “ut in
vadis consisterent tutius,” Caes. B. G. 3, 13: “tutius et facilius receptus
daretur,” id. B. C. 2, 30: “tutius ac facilius id tractatur,” Quint. 5, 5, 1:
“usitatis tutius utimur,” id. 1, 5, 71: “ut ubivis tutius quam in meo regno
essem,” Sall. J. 14, 11.— c. Sup. (α). Form tutissime: nam te hic tutissime
puto fore, Pomp. ap. Cic. Att. 8, 11, A.— (β). Form tutissimo: “quaerere, ubi
tutissimo essem,” Cic. Att. 8, 1, 2; cf. Charis. p. 173 P.: “tutissimo
infunduntur oboli quattuor,” Plin. 20, 3, 8, § 14. Grice was especially
interested in the misuses of intuition. He found that J. L. Austin (born in
Lancaster) had “Northern intuitions.” “I myself have proper heart-of-England
intuitions.” “Strawson has Cockney intuitions.” “I wonder how we conducted
those conversations on Saturday mornings!” “Strictly, an intuition is a
non-inferential knowledge or grasp, as of a proposition, concept, or entity,
that is not based on perception, memory, or introspection; also, the capacity
in virtue of which such cognition is possible. A person might know that 1 ! 1 %
2 intuitively, i.e., not on the basis of inferring it from other propositions.
And one might know intuitively what yellow is, i.e., might understand the
concept, even though ‘yellow’ is not definable. Or one might have intuitive awareness
of God or some other entity. Certain mystics hold that there can be intuitive,
or immediate, apprehension of God. Ethical intuitionists hold both that we can
have intuitive knowledge of certain moral concepts that are indefinable, and
that certain propositions, such as that pleasure is intrinsically good, are
knowable through intuition. Self-evident propositions are those that can be
seen (non-inferentially) to be true once one fully understands them. It is
often held that all and only self-evident propositions are knowable through
intuition, which is here identified with a certain kind of intellectual or
rational insight. Intuitive knowledge of moral or other philosophical
propositions or concepts has been compared to the intuitive knowledge of grammaticality
possessed by competent users of a language. Such language users can know
immediately whether certain sentences are grammatical or not without recourse
to any conscious reasoning. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “My intutions.” BANC.
Ionian-sea-coast philosophy: Grice, “Or
mar ionio, as the Italians have it!” -- the characteristically naturalist and
rationalist thought of Grecian philosophers of the sixth and fifth centuries
B.C. who were active in Ionia, the region of ancient Greek colonies on the
coast of Asia Minor and adjacent islands. First of the Ionian philosophers were
the three Milesians. Grice: “It always amused me that they called themselves
Ionians, but then Williams, who founded Providence in the New World, called
himself an Englishman!”. Refs.: H. P. Grice: “The relevance of Ionian
philosophy today.”
Irigaray: philosopher and psychoanalyst.
Her earliest work was in psychoanalysis and linguistics, focusing on the role
of negation in the language of schizophrenics (Languages, 1966). A trained analyst
with a private practice, she attended Lacan’s seminars at the École Normale
Supérieure and for several years taught a course in the psychoanalysis
department at Vincennes. With the publication of Speculum, De l’autre
femme(Speculum of the Other Woman) in 1974 she was dismissed from Vincennes.
She argues that psychoanalysis, specifically its attitude toward women, is
historically and culturally determined and that its phallocentric bias is
treated as universal truth. With the publication of Speculum and Ce Sexe qui
n’en est pas un (This Sex Which Is Not One) in 1977, her work extends beyond
psychoanalysis and begins a critical examination of philosophy. Influenced
primarily by Hegel, Nietzsche, and Heidegger, her work is a critique of the
fundamental categories of philosophical thought: one/many, identity/difference,
being/non-being, rational/irrational, mind/body, form/matter,
transcendental/sensible. She sets out to show the concealed aspect of
metaphysical constructions and what they depend on, namely, the unacknowledged
mother. In Speculum, the mirror figures as interpretation and criticism of the
enclosure of the Western subject within the mirror’s frame, constituted solely
through the masculine imaginary. Her project is one of constituting the world –
and not only the specular world – of the other as woman. This engagement with
the history of philosophy emphasizes the historical and sexual determinants of
philosophical discourse, and insists on bringing the transcendental back to the
elements of the earth and embodiment. Her major contribution to philosophy is
the notion of sexual difference. An Ethics of Sexual Difference (1984) claims
that the central contemporary philosophical task is to think through sexual
difference. Although her notion of sexual difference is sometimes taken to be
an essentialist view of the feminine, in fact it is an articulation of the
difference between the sexes that calls into question an understanding of
either the feminine or masculine as possessing a rigid gender identity.
Instead, sexual difference is the erotic desire for otherness. Insofar as it is
an origin that is continuously differentiating itself from itself, it
challenges Aristotle’s understanding of the arche as solid ground or
hypokeimenon. As aition or first cause, sexual difference is responsible for
something coming into being and is that to which things are indebted for their
being. This indebtedness allows Irigaray to formulate an ethics of sexual
difference. Her latest work continues to rethink the foundations of ethics.
Both Towards a Culture of Difference (1990) and I Love To You (1995) claim that
there is no civil identity proper to women and therefore no possibility of
equivalent social and political status for men and women. She argues for a
legal basis to ground the reciprocity between the sexes; that there is no
living universal, that is, a universal that reflects sexual difference; and
that this lack of a living universal leads to an absence of rights and
responsibilities which reflects both men and women. She claims, therefore, that
it is necessary to “sexuate” rights. These latest works continue to make
explicit the erotic and ethical project that informs all her work: to think
through the dimension of sexual difference that opens up access to the alliances
between living beings who are engendered and not fabricated, and who refuse to
sacrifice desire for death, power, or money.
iron-age
metaphysics:
Euclidean geometry, the version of geometry that includes among its axioms the
parallel axiom, which asserts that, given a line L in a plane, there exists
just one line in the plane that passes through a point not on L but never meets
L. The phrase ‘Euclidean geometry’ refers both to the doctrine of geometry to
be found in Euclid’s Elements fourth century B.C. and to the mathematical
discipline that was built on this basis afterward. In order to present
properties of rectilinear and curvilinear curves in the plane and solids in
space, Euclid sought definitions, axioms, ethics, divine command Euclidean geometry
290 290 and postulates to ground the
reasoning. Some of his assumptions belonged more to the underlying logic than
to the geometry itself. Of the specifically geometrical axioms, the least
self-evident stated that only one line passes through a point in a plane
parallel to a non-coincident line within it, and many efforts were made to
prove it from the other axioms. Notable forays were made by G. Saccheri, J.
Playfair, and A. M. Legendre, among others, to put forward results logically
contradictory to the parallel axiom e.g., that the sum of the angles between
the sides of a triangle is greater than 180° and thus standing as candidates
for falsehood; however, none of them led to paradox. Nor did logically
equivalent axioms such as that the angle sum equals 180° seem to be more or
less evident than the axiom itself. The next stages of this line of reasoning
led to non-Euclidean geometry. From the point of view of logic and rigor,
Euclid was thought to be an apotheosis of certainty in human knowledge; indeed,
‘Euclidean’ was also used to suggest certainty, without any particular concern
with geometry. Ironically, investigations undertaken in the late nineteenth
century showed that, quite apart from the question of the parallel axiom,
Euclid’s system actually depended on more axioms than he had realized, and that
filling all the gaps would be a formidable task. Pioneering work done
especially by M. Pasch and G. Peano was brought to a climax in 9 by Hilbert,
who produced what was hoped to be a complete axiom system. Even then the axiom
of continuity had to wait for the second edition! The endeavor had consequences
beyond the Euclidean remit; it was an important example of the growth of
axiomatization in mathematics as a whole, and it led Hilbert himself to see
that questions like the consistency and completeness of a mathematical theory
must be asked at another level, which he called metamathematics. It also gave
his work a formalist character; he said that his axiomatic talk of points,
lines, and planes could be of other objects. Within the Euclidean realm,
attention has fallen in recent decades upon “neo-Euclidean” geometries, in
which the parallel axiom is upheld but a different metric is proposed. For
example, given a planar triangle ABC, the Euclidean distance between A and B is
the hypotenuse AB; but the “rectangular distance” AC ! CB also satisfies the
properties of a metric, and a geometry working with it is very useful in, e.g.,
economic geography, as anyone who drives around a city will readily understand. Grice: "Much
the most significant opposition to my type of philosophising comes from those
like Baron Russell who feel that ‘ “ordinary-language” philosophy’ is an
affront to science and to intellectual progress, and who regard exponents like
me as wantonly dedicating themselves to what the Baron calls 'stone-age metaphysics',
"The Baron claims that 'stone-age metaphysics' is the best that can be
dredged up from a ‘philosophical’ study of an ‘ordinary’ language, such as
Oxonian, as it ain't. "The use made of Russell’s phrase ‘stone-age
metaphysics’ has more rhetorical appeal than argumentative
force."“Certainly ‘stone-age’ *physics*, if by that we mean a
'primitive' (as the Baron puts it -- in contrast to 'iron-age physics') set of
hypotheses about how the world goes which might conceivably be embedded somehow
or other in an ‘ordinary’ language such as Oxonian, does not seem to be a
proper object for first-order devotion -- I'll grant the Baron that!"“But
this fact should *not* prevent something derivable or extractable
from ‘stone-age’ (if not 'iron-age') *physics*, perhaps some very
general characterization of the nature of reality, from being a proper target
for serious research.”"I would not be surprised if an extractable
characterization of this may not be the same as that which is extractable from,
or that which underlies, the Baron's favoured iron-age physics!"
non
sequitur
--: irrationality, unreasonableness. Whatever it entails, irrationality can
characterize belief, desire, intention, and action. intuitions irrationality
443 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 443 Irrationality is often explained in
instrumental, or goal-oriented, terms. You are irrational if you (knowingly)
fail to do your best, or at least to do what you appropriately think adequate,
to achieve your goals. If ultimate goals are rationally assessable, as
Aristotelian and Kantian traditions hold, then rationality and irrationality
are not purely instrumental. The latter traditions regard certain specific
(kinds of) goals, such as human well-being, as essential to rationality. This
substantialist approach lost popularity with the rise of modern decision
theory, which implies that, in satisfying certain consistency and completeness
requirements, one’s preferences toward the possible outcomes of available
actions determine what actions are rational and irrational for one by
determining the personal utility of their outcomes. Various theorists have
faulted modern decision theory on two grounds: human beings typically lack the
consistent preferences and reasoning power required by standard decision theory
but are not thereby irrational, and rationality requires goods exceeding
maximally efficient goal satisfaction. When relevant goals concern the
acquisition of truth and the avoidance of falsehood, epistemic rationality and
irrationality are at issue. Otherwise, some species of non-epistemic
rationality or irrationality is under consideration. Species of non-epistemic
rationality and irrationality correspond to the kind of relevant goal: moral,
prudential, political, economic, aesthetic, or some other. A comprehensive
account of irrationality will elucidate epistemic and non-epistemic
irrationality as well as such sources of irrationality as weakness of will and
ungrounded belief.
esse:“est” (“Homo
animale rationalis est” – Aristotle, cited by Grice in “Aristotle on the
multiplicity of being”) – “is” is the third person singular form of the verb
‘be’, with at least three fundamental usages that philosophers distinguish
according to the resources required for a proper semantic representation. First,
there is the ‘is’ of existence, which Grice finds otiose – “Marmaduke Bloggs is
a journalist who climbed Mt Everest on hands and knees – a typical invention by
journalists”. (There is a unicorn in the garden: Dx (Ux8Gx)) uses the
existential quantifier. Bellerophon’s dad: “There is a flying horse in the
stable.” “That’s mine, dad.” – Then, second, there is the ‘is’ of identity
(Hesperus is Phosphorus: j % k) employs the predicate of identity, or dyadic
relation of “=,” as per Leibniz’s problem – “The king of France” – Kx = Ky.
Then third there is the ‘is’ of predication, which can be essential (izzing) or
accidentail (hazzing). (Samson is strong: Sj) merely juxtaposes predicate
symbol and proper name. Some controversy attends the first usage. Some (notably
that eccentric philosopher that went by the name of Meinong) maintain that ‘is’
applies more broadly than ‘exists.’ “Is” produces truths when combined with
‘deer’ and ‘unicorn.’ ‘Exists,’ rather than ‘is’, produces a truth when
combined with ‘deer’ -- but not ‘unicorn’. Aquinas takes “esse” to denote some
special activity that every existing thing necessarily performs, which would seem
to imply that with ‘est’ they attribute more to an object than we do with
‘exists’. Other issues arise in connection with the second usage. Does, e.g. “Hesperus
is Phosphorus,” attribute anything more to the heavenly body than its identity
with itself? Consideration of such a question leads Frege, wrongly to conclude,
in what Ryle calls the “Fido”-Fido theory of meaning that names (and other
meaningful expressions) of ordinary language have a “sense” or “mode of
presenting” the thing to which they refer that representations within our
standard, extensional logical systems fail to expose. The distinction between
the ‘is’ of identity and the ‘is’ of predication parallels Frege’s distinction
between ‘objekt” and concept: words signifying objects stand to the right of
the ‘is’ of identity and those signifying concepts stand to the right of the
‘is’ of predication. Although it seems remarkable that so many deep and
difficult philosophical concepts should link to a single short and commonplace
word, we should perhaps not read too much into that observation. Grecian and
Roman indeed divide the various roles played by English’s compact copula among
several constructions, but there are dialects, even within Oxford, that use the
expression “is” for other purposes. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Aristotle on the
multiplicity of being.”
-ism: used by Grice
derogatorily. In his ascent to the City of the Eternal Truth, he meets twelve
–isms, which he orders alphabetically. These are: Empiricism. Extensionalism.
Functionalism. MaterialismMechanism. Naturalism. Nominalism. Phenomenalism.
Positivism. Physicalism. Reductionism. Scepticism. Grice’s implicaturum is that
each is a form of, er, minimalism, as opposed to maximalism. He also seems to
implicate that, while embracing one of those –isms is a reductionist vice,
embracing their opposites is a Christian virtue – He explicitly refers to the
name of Bunyan’s protagonist, “Christian” – “in a much more publicized journey,
I grant.” So let’s see how we can correlate each vicious heathen ism with the
Griceian Christian virtuous ism. Empiricism. “Surely not all is experience. My
bones are not.” Opposite: Rationalism. Extensionalism. Surely the empty set
cannot end up being the fullest! Opposite Intensionalism. Functionalism. What
is the function of love? We have to extend functionalism to cover one’s concern
for the other – And also there’s otiosity. Opposite: Mentalism. Materialism –
My bones are ‘hyle,’ but my eternal soul isn’t. Opposite Spiritualism. Mechanism – Surely there is finality in
nature, and God designed it. Opposite Vitalism. Naturalism – Surely Aristotle
meant something by ‘ta meta ta physica,’ There is a transnatural realm.
Opposite: Transnaturalism. Nominalism.
Occam was good, except with his ‘sermo mentalis.’ Opposite: Realism.
Phenomenalism – Austin and Grice soon realised that Berlin was wrong. Opposite
‘thing’-language-ism. Positivism – And then there’s not. Opposite: Negativism. Physicalism – Surely my soul is not a brain
state. Opposite: Transnaturalism, since Physicalismm and Naturalism mean the
same thing, ony in Greek, the other in Latin. Reductionism – Julie is wrong when she thinks
I’m a reductionist. Opposite: Reductivism. Scepticism: Surely there’s common sense.
Opposite: Common-Sensism. Refs: H. P. Grice, “Prejudices and predilections;
which become, the life and opinions of H. P. Grice,” The Grice Papers, BANC.
isocrates – Grice: “the
chief rival of Plato.” A pupil of Socrates and also of Gorgias, Isocrates founds
a play group or club in Athens – vide H. P. Grice, “Athenian dialectic” -- that
attracts many aristocrats. Many of Isocrates’s philosophy touches on
‘dialectic.’ “Against the Sophists and On the Antidosis are most important in
this respect. “On the antidosis” stands to Isocrates as the “Apology” of Plato
stands to Socrates, a defense of Socrates against an attack not on his life,
but on his property. The aim of Isocrates’s philosophy is good judgment in practical
affairs, and he believes his contribution to Greece through education more
valuable than legislation could possibly be. Isocrates repudiates instruction
in theoretical (what he called ‘otiose’) philosophy, and insisted on
distinguishing his teaching of rhetoric from the sophistry that gives clever
speakers an unfair advantage. In politics Isocrates is a Panhellenic patriot,
and urges the warring Greek city-states to unite under strong leadership and
take arms against the Persian Empire. His most famous work, and the one in
which he took the greatest pride, is the “Panegyricus,” a speech in praise of
Athens. In general, Isocrates supports democracy in Athens, but toward the end
of his life complained bitterly of abuses of the system.
descriptum
– definite
(“the”) and “indefinite” (“some at least one”). Analysed by Grice in terms of
/\x. “The king of France is bald” There is at least a king of France, there is
at most a king of France, and anything that is a king of France is bald. For
indefinite descriptum he holds the equivalence with \/x, “some (at least one).
– Grice follows Peano in finding the ‘iota’ operator a good abbreviatory device
to avoid the boring ‘Russellian expansion.” “We should forgive Russell – his
background was mathematics not the belles letters as with Bradley and me, and
anyone at Oxford, really.” – Grice. iota
– iota operator used by Grice. Peano uses iota as short for “isos,” Grecian for
‘Same”. Peano defines “ix” as “the class of whatever is the same as x”. Peano
then looked for a symbol for the inverse for this. He first uses a negated
iota, and then an inverted iota, so that inverted iota x reads “the sole
[unique] member of x” “ι” read as “the” -- s the inverted iota or description
operator and is used in expressions for definite descriptions, such as “(ιx)ϕx(ιx)ϕx,”
which is read: the x such that ϕxϕx). [(ιx)ϕx(ιx)ϕx] -- a definite description
in brackets. This is a scope indicator for definite descriptions. The topic of
‘description’ is crucial for Grice, and he regrets Russell focused on the
definite rather than the indefinite descriptor. As a matter of fact, while
Grice follows the custom of referring to the “Russellian expansion” of iota, he
knows it’s ultimately the “Peanoian” expansion. Indeed, Peano uses the
non-inverted iota “i” for the unit class. For the ONLY or UNIQUE member of this
class, i. e. the definite article “the,” Peano uses the inverted iota (cf.
*THE* Twelve Apostles). (On occasion Peano uses the denied iota for that). Peano’s approach to ‘the’ evolve in at least
three stages towards a greater precision in the treatment of the description,
both definite and indefinite. Peano introducesin 1897 the fundamental definition of the unit class
as the class such that ALL of its members are IDENTICAL. In Peanoian symbols, ix
= ye (y = x). Peano approaches the UNIQUE OR ONLY member of such a class, by
way of an indirect definition: “x = ia • = • a = ix.” Regarding the analysis of
the definite article “the,” Peano makes the crucial point that every ‘proposition’
or ‘sentence’ containing “the” (“The apostles were twelve”) can be offered a
reductive AND REDUCTIONIST analysis, first, to. the for,? ia E b, and, second, to
the inclusion of the class in the class (a b), which already supposes the
elimination of “i.” Peano notes he can avoid an identity whose first member
contains “I” (1897:215). One difference between Peano’s and Russell's treatment
of classes in the context of the theory of description is that, while, for
Peano, a description combines a class abstract with the inverse of the unit
class operator, Russell restricts the free use of a class abstract due the risk
of paradox generation. For Peano, it is necessary that there EXIST the class
(‘apostle’), and he uses for this the symbol ‘I,’ which indicates that the
class is not vacuous, void, or empty, and that it have a unique member, the set
of twelve apostles. If either of these two conditions – existence and uniqueness
-- are not met, the symbol is meaningless, or pointless. Peano offers various
instances for handling the symbol of the inverted iota, and the way in which --
starting from that ‘indirect’ or implicit definition, it can be eliminated
altogether. One example is of particular interest, as it states a link between
the reductionist analysis of the inverted iota and the problem of what Peano
calls ‘doubtful’ existence (rather than vacuous, void, or empty). Peano starts
by defining the superlative ‘THE greatEST number of a class of real numbers’ as
‘THE number n such that there is no number of this class being greater than n.’
Peano warns that one should not infer from this definition the ‘existence’ of the
aforementioned greatEST number. Grice does not quite consider this in the
‘definite description’ section of “Vacuous name” but gives a similar example:
“The climber on hands and knees of Mt. Everest does not exist. He was invented
by the journalists.” And in other cases where there is a NON-IDENTIFICATORY use
of ‘the’, which Grice symbolises as ‘the,’ rather than ‘THE’: “The butler
certainly made a mess with our hats and coats – whoever he is --.” As it
happens Strawson mistook the haberdasher to be the butler. So that Strawson is
MIS-IDENTIFYING the denotatum as being ‘the butler’ when it is ‘the
haberdasher.’ The butler doesn’t really exist. Smith dressed the haberdasher as
a butler and made him act as one just to impress. Similarly, as per Russell’s
‘Prince George soon found out that ‘the author of Waverley’ did not exist,”
(variant of his example). Similarly, Peano proves that we can speak
legitimately of “THE GREATEST real number” even if we have doubts it ‘exists.
He just tweaks the original definition to obtain a different expression where
“I” is dropped out. For Peano, then, the reductionist analysis of the definite
article “the” is feasible and indeed advisable for a case of ‘doubtful’ existence.
Grice does not consider ‘doubtful’ but he may. “The climber on hands and knees
of Mt Everest may, but then again may not, attend the party the Merseyside
Geographical Society is giving in his honour. He will attend if he exists; he
will not attend if he doesn’t.” Initially, Peano thinks “I” need not be
equivalent to, in the sense of systematically replaced by, the two clauses
(indeed three) in the expansion which are supposed to give the import of ‘the,’
viz. existence and uniqueness (subdivided in ‘at least’ and ‘at most’). His
reductionism proves later to be absolute. He starts from the definition in terms
of the unit class. He goes on to add a series of "possible"
definitions -- allowing for alternative logical orders. One of this alternative
definitions is stipulated to be a strict equivalence, about which he had
previously been sceptical. Peano asserts that the only unque individual belongs
to a unit. Peano does not put it in so
many words that this expression is meaningless. In the French translation, what
he said is Gallic: “Nous ne donnons pas de signification a ce symbole si la
classe a est nulle, ou si elle contient plusieurs individus.” “We don’t give
signification to this symbol IF the class is void, or if the class contains
more than one individual.” – where we can see that he used ‘iota’ to represent
‘individus,’ from Latin ‘individuum,’ translating Greek ‘a-tomos.’ So it is not
meant to stand for Greek ‘idion,’ as in ‘idiosyncratic.’ But why did he choose
the iota, which is a Grecian letter. Idion is in the air (if not ‘idiot.’).
Thus, one may take the equivalence in practice, given that if the three conditions
in the expansion are met, the symbol cannot be used at all. There are other ways
of providing a reductionist analysis of the same symbols according to Peano, e.
g., laE b. = : a = tx. :Jx • Xc b class (a) such that it belongs to another class
(b) is equal to the EXISTENCE of exactly one (at least one and at most one)
idiosyncratic individual or element such that this idiosyncratic individual is
a member of that class (b), i. e. "the only or unique (the one member)
member of a belongs to b" is to be held equivalent to ‘There is at least
one x such that, first, the unit class a is equal to the class constituted by
x, and, second, x belongs to b.’ Or, ‘The class of x such that a is the class
constituted by x, and that x belongs to b, is not an empty class, and that it
have a unique member.” This is exactly Russell's tri-partite expansion referred
to Russell (‘on whom Grice heaped all the praise,’ to echo Quine). Grice was
not interested in history, only in rebutting Strawson. Of course, Peano
provides his conceptualisations in terms of ‘class’ rather than, as Russell,
Sluga [or ‘Shuga,’ as Cole reprints him] and Grice do, in terms of the ‘propositional
function,’ i. e. Peano reduces ‘the’ in
terms of a property or a predicate, which defins a class. Peano reads the
membership symbol as "is,” which opens a new can of worms for Grice:
“izzing” – and flies out of the fly bottle. Peano is well aware of the
importance of his device to eliminate the definite article “the” to more
‘primitive’ terms. That is why Peano qualifies his definition as an "expriment
la P[proposition] 1 a E b sous une autre forme, OU ne figure plus le signe i;
puisque toute P contenant le signe i a est REDUCTIBLE ala forme ia E b, OU best
une CIs, on pourra ELIMINER le signe i dans toute P.” The once received view that
the symbol "i" is for Peano undefinable and primitive has now been
corrected. Before making more explicit
the parallelism with Whitehead’s and Russell's and Grice’s theory of
description (vide Quine, “Reply to H. P. Grice”) we may consider a few
potential problems. First, while it is true that the symbol ‘i’ has been given
a ‘reductionist analysis’, in the definiens we still see the symbol of the unit
class, which would refer somehow to the idea that is symbolized by ''ix’. Is
this a sign of circularity, and evidence that the descriptor has not been
eliminated? For Peano, there are at least two ways of defining a symbol of the
unit class without using ‘iota’ – straight, inverted, or negated. One way is
directly replacing ix by its value: y 3(y = x). We have: la E b • =: 3x 3{a =y
3(y =x) • X E b}, which expresses the
same idea in a way where a reference to iota has disappeared. We can read now
"the only member of a belongs to b" as "there is at least one x
such that (i) the unit class a is equal to all the y such that y =x, and (ii) x
belongs to b" (or "the class of x such that they constitute the class
of y, and that they constitute the class a, and that in addition they belong to
the class b, is not an empty class"). The complete elimination underlies
the mentioned definition. Peano is just not interested in making the point
explicit. A second way is subtler. By pointing out that, in the
"hypothesis" preceding the quoted definition, it is clearly stated
that the class "a" is defined as the unit class in terms of the
existence and identity of all of their members (i.e. uniqueness): a E Cis. 3a:
x, yEa. X = y: bE CIs • : This is why "a" is equal to the expression
''tx'' (in the second member). One may still object that since "a"
can be read as "the unit class", Peano does not quite provide a
‘reductionist’ analysis as it is shown through the occurrence of these words in
some of the readings proposed above. However, the hypothesis preceding the
definition only states that the meaning of the symbols which are used in the
second member is to be. Thus, "a" is stated as "an existing unit
class", which has to be understood in the following way: 'a' stands for a
non-empty class that all of its members are identical. We can thus can "a",
wherever it occurs, by its meaning, given that this interpretation works as
only a purely ‘nominal’ definition, i.e. a convenient abbreviation. However,
the actual substitution would lead us to rather complicated prolixic expressions
that would infringe Grice’s desideratum of conversational clarity. Peano's
usual way of working can be odd. Starting from this idea, we can interpret the
definition as stating that "ia Eb" is an abbreviation of the
definiens and dispensing with the conditions stating existence and uniqueness
in the hypothesis, which have been incorporated to their new place. The
hypothesis contains only the statement
of "a" and" b" as being classes, and the definition amounts
to: a, bECls.::J :. ME b. =:3XE([{3aE[w, zEa. ::Jw•z' w= z]} ={ye (y= x)}] • XE
b). Peano’s way is characterized as the constant search for SHORTER, briefer,
and more conveniente expressions – which is Grice’s solution to Strawson’s
misconception – there is a principle of conversational tailoring. It is quite
understandable that Peano prefers to avoid long expansions. The important thing
is not the intuitive and superficial similarity between the symbols
"ia" and ''ix'', caused simply by the appearance of the Greek letter iota
in both cases, or the intuitive meaning of
"the unit class.” What is key are the conditions under which these
expressions have been introduced in Peano’s system, which are completely clear
and quite explicit in the first definition. It may still be objected that
Peano’s elimination of ‘the’ is a failure in that it derives from Peano's confusion
between class membership and class inclusion -- a singleton class would be its
sole member – but these are not clearly distinct notions. It follows that (iii)
"a" is both a class and, according to the interpretation of the
definition, an individual (iv), as is shown by joining the hypothesis preceding
the definition and the definition itself. The objection derives from the received
view on Peano, according to which his logic is, compared to Whitehead’s and
Russell’s, not strict or formal enough, but also contains some important confusions
here and there. And certainly Russell
would be more than happy to correct a minor point. Russell always thinks of
Peano and his school as being strangely free of confusions or mistakes. It may
be said that Peano indeed ‘confuses’ membership with inclusion (cf. Grice ‘not
confused, but mistaken’) given that it was he himself who, predating Frege, introduces
the distinction with the symbol "e.” If the objection amounts to Peano admitting
that the symbol for membership holds between class A and class B, it is true
that this is the case when Peano uses it to indicate the meaning of some
symbols, but only through the reading of "is,” which could be" 'a and
b being classes, "the only member of a belongs to b,” to be the same as
"there is at least one x such that (i) 'there is at least one a such that
for ,': and z belonging to a,. w = z' is equal to y such that y =. x' , and
(ii) x belongs to b ,where both the iota and the unit class are eliminated in
the definiens. There is a similar apparent vicious circularity in Frege's definition
of number. "k e K" as "k is a class"; see also the
hypothesis from above for another example). This by no means involves confusion, and is shown
by the fact that Peano soon adds four definite properties distinguishing precisely
both class inclusion and class membership,, which has Russell himself
preserving the useful and convenient reading. "ia" does not stand for the
singleton class. Peano states pretty clearly that" 1" (T) makes sense only when applied to this or that
individual, and ''t'' as applied to this or that class, no matter what symbols
is used for these notions. Thus, ''ta'', like "tx" have to be read as
"the class constituted by ...", and" la" as "the only
member of a". Thus, although Peano never uses "ix" (because he
is thinking in terms of this or that class), had he done so its meaning, of
course, would have been exactly the same as "la", with no confusion
at all. "a" stands for a class because it is so stated in the
hypothesis, although it can represent an individual when preceded by the
descriptor, and together with it, i.e. when both constitute a new symbol as a. Peano's
habit is better understood by interpreting what he is saying it in terms of a
propositional function, and then by seeing" la" as being somewhat
similar to x, no matter what reasons of convenience led him to prefer symbols
generally used for classes ("a" instead of"x"). There is
little doubt that this makes the world of a difference for Russell and Sluga (or
Shuga) but not Strawson or Grice, or Quine (“I’m sad all the praise was heaped
by Grice on Russell, not Peano”). For Peano the inverted iota is the symbol for
an operator on a class, it leads us to a different ‘concept’ when it flanks a
term, and this is precisely the point Shuga (or Sluga) makes to Grice –
‘Presupposition and conversational implicaturum” – the reference to Shuga was
omitted in the reprint in Way of Words). In contrast, for Russell, the iota
operator is only a part of what Whitehead and Russell call an ‘incomplete’
symbol. In fact, Grice borrows the complete-incomplete distinction from
Whitehead and Russell. For Peano, the descriptor can obviously be given a
reductionist eliminationist analysis only in conjunction with the rest of the
‘complete’ symbol, "ia e b.’ Whitehead’s and Russell’s point, again, seems
drawn from Peano. And there is no problem when we join the original hypothesis
with the definition, “a eCis. 3a: x, yea. -::Jx,y. x =y: be CIs • :. . la e b.
=: 3x 3(a =tx. x e b). If it falls within the scope of the quantifier in the
hypothesis, “a” is a variable which occurs both free and bound in the formula –
And it has to be a variable, since qua constant, no quantifier is needed. It is
not clear what Peano’s position would have been. Admittedly, Peano – living
always in a rush in Paris -- does not always display the highest standards of Oxonian
clarity between the several uses of, say, "existence" involved in his
various uses of this or that quantifier. In principle, there would be no problem
when a variable appears both bound and free in the same expression. And this is
so because the variable appears bound in one occurrence and free in another.
And one cannot see how this could affect the main claim. The point Grice is
making here (which he owes to ‘Shuga’) is to recognise the fundamental
similarities in the reductionist analysis of “the” in Peano and Russell. It is
true that Russell objects to an ‘implicit’ or indirect definition under a
hypothesis. He would thus have rejected the Peanoian reductionist analysis of
“the.” However, Whitehead and Russell rejects an ‘implicit’ definition under a
hypothesis in the specific context of the “unrestricted’ variable of “Principia.”
Indeed, Russell had been using, before Whitehead’s warning, this type of
‘implicit’ definition under a hypothesis for a long period the minute he
mastered Peano's system. It is because Russell interprets a definition under a
hypothesis as Peano does, i.e. merely as a device for fixing the denotatum of
this or that symbol in an interpreted formula. When one reads after some symbolic
definition, things like "'x' being ... " or" 'y' being ...
", this counts as a definition under a hypothesis, if only because the
denotatum of the symbol has to be determined. Even if Peano's reductionist
analysis of “the” fails because it within the framework of a merely conditional
definition, the implicaturum of his original insight (“the” is not primitive)
surely influences Whitehead and Russell. Peano is the first who introduces the
the distinction between a free (or ‘real’) and a bound (or ‘apparent’)
variable, and, predating, Frege -- existential and universal quantification,
with an attempt at a substitutional theory based the concept of a ‘proposition,’
without relying on the concepts of ‘class’ or ‘propositional function.’ It may
be argued that Peano could hardly may have thought that he eliminated “the.” Peano
continues to use “the” and his whole system depends on it. Here, a Griceian
practica reason can easily explain Peano’s retaining “the” in a system in cases
where the symbol is merely the abbreviation of something that is in principle
totally eliminable.In the same vein, Whitehead and Russell do continue to use
“the” after the tripartite expansion. Peano, like Whitehead and Russell after
him, undoubtedly thinks, and rightly, too, that the descriptor IS eliminable.If
he does not flourish this elimination with by full atomistic philosophic
paraphernalia which makes Russell's theory of description one of the most
important logical successes of Cambridge philosopher – that was admired even at
Oxford, if by Grice if not by Strawson, that is another thing. Peano somewhat understated
the importance of his reductionist analysis, but then again, his goal is very
different from Whitehead’s and Russell's logicism. And different goals for
different strokes. In any case, the reductionist analysis of “the” is worked
out by Peano with essentially the same symbolic resources that Whitehead
and Russell employ. In a pretty clear
fashion, coming from him, Peano states two of the three conditions -- existence
and uniqueness – subdivided into ‘at least and at most --, as being what it is
explicitly conveyed by “the.” That is why in a negation of a vacuous
description, being true, the existence claim, within the scope of the negation,
is an annullable implicaturum, while in an affirmation, the existence claim is
an entailment rendering the affirmation that predicates a feature of a vacuous definite
description is FALSE. Peano has enough symbolic techniques for dispensing with
‘the’, including those required for constructing a definition in use. If he once
rather cursorily noted that for Peano, “i” (‘the’) is primitive and indefinable,
Quine later recognised Peano’s achievement, and he was “happy to get straight
on Peano” on descriptions, having checked all the relevant references and I
fully realising that he was wrong when he previously stated that the iota
descriptor was for Peano primitive and indefinable. Peano deserves all the
credit for the reductionist analysis that has been heaped on Whitehead and Russell,
except perhaps for Whitehead’s and Russell’s elaboration on the philosophical
lesson of a ‘contextual’ definition.For Peano, “the” cannot be defined in
isolation; only in the context of the class (a) from which it is the UNIQUE member
(la), and also in the context of the (b) from which that class is a member, at
least to the extent that the class a is included in the class b. This carries no
conflation of membership and inclusion. It is just a reasonable reading of "
1a Eb". "Ta" is just meaningless if the conditions of existence
and uniqueness (at least and at most) are not fulfilled. Surely it may be
argued that Peano’s reductionist analysis of “the” is not exactly the same as
Whitehead’s and Russell's. Still, in his own version, it surely influenced
Whitehead and Russell. In his "On Fundamentals,” Russell includes a
definition in terms analogous to Peano's, and with almost the same symbols. The
alleged improvement of Whitehead’s and Russell’s definition is in clarity. The
concept of a ‘propositional function’ is indeed preferable to that of class
membership. Other than that, the symbolic expression of the the three-prong
expansive conditions -- existence and uniqueness (at least and at most) -- is preserved.
Russell develops Peano’s claim to the effect that “ia” cannot be defined alone,
but always in the context of a class, which Russell translates as ‘the context
of a propositional function.’ His version in "On Denoting” is well known.
In an earlier letter to Jourdain, dated,
Jan. 3, 1906 we read: “'JI( lX) (x) • =•(:3b) : x. =x. X = b: 'JIb.” (They
never corresponded about the things Strawson corresponded with Grice –
cricket). As G. Landini has pointed out, there is even an earlier occurrence of
this definition in Russell’s "On Substitution" with only very slight
symbolic differences. We can see the heritage from Peano in a clear way if we
compare the definition with the version for classes in the letter to Jourdain:
'JI(t'u) • = : (:3b) : xEU. =x. X = b: 'JIb. Russell can hardly be accused of
plagiarizing Peano; yet all the ideas and the formal devices which are
important for the reductionist analysis of “the” were developed by in Peano,
complete with conceptual and symbolic resources, and which Russell acknowledged
that he studied in detail before formulating his own theory in “On denoting.”
Regarding Meinong’s ontological jungle, for Russell, the principle of
‘subsistence disappears as a consequence of the reductionist analysis of “the,”
which is an outcome of Russell’s semantic monism. Russell's later attitude to
Meinong as his main enemy is a comfortable recourse (Griffin I977a). As for Bocher, Russell himself admits some
influence from his nominalism. Bacher describes mathematical objects as
"mere symbols" and advises
Russell to follow this line of work in a letter, two months before Russell's
key idea. The 'class as one' is merely a symbol or name which we choose at
pleasure.” It is important to mention MacColl who he speaks of "symbolic
universes", with things like a ‘round square.’MacColl also speaks of
"symbolic ‘existence’". Indeed, Russell publishes “On denoting” as a
direct response to MacColl. Refs.: P. Benacerraf and H. Putnam, “Philosophy of Mathematics,
2nd ed.Cambridge.; M. Bocher, 1904a. "The Fundamental Conceptions and
Methods of Mathematics", Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society; M.
A. E. Dummett, The Interpretation of Frege's Philosophy; Duckworth), G. Frege,
G., Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik (Breslau: Koebner), tr. J. L. Austin, The Foundations of Arithmetic,
Blackwell, Partial English trans. (§§55-91, 106-1O7) by M. S. Mahoney in
Benacerraf and Putnam; "Uber Sinn und Bedeutung". Trans. as "On
Sense and Reference" in Frege 1952a, pp. 56-78. --, I892b. "Uber
Begriff und Gegenstand". Trans. as "On Concept and Object" in
Frege I952a, pp. 42-55. --, I893a. Grungesetze der Arithmetik, Vol. I Gena:
Pohle). Partial English trans. by M. Furth, The Basic Laws ofArithmetic
(Berkeley: U. California P., 1964). --, I906a. "Uber die Grundlagen der
Geometrie", Jahresbericht der deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung, 15
(1906): 293-309, 377-403, 423-30. English trans. by Eike-Henner WKluge as
"On the Foundations of Geometry", in On the Foundations of Geometry
and Formal Theories of Arithmetic (New Haven and London, Yale U. P., 1971). --,
I952a. Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, tr. by P.
T. Geach and M. Black (Oxford: Blackwell). Grattan-Guinness, L, I977a. Dear
Russell-Dear Jourdain (London: Duckworth). Griffin, N., I977a. "Russell's
'Horrible Travesty' of Meinong", Russell, nos. 25- 28: 39-51. E. D.
Klemke, ed., I970a. Essays on Bertrand Russell (Urbana: U. Illinois P.).
Largeault, ]., I97oa. Logique et philosophie chez Frege (Paris: Nauwelaerts).
MacColl, H., I905a. "Symbolic Reasoning". Repr. in Russell I973a, pp.
308-16. Mosterfn, ]., I968a. "Teoria de las descripciones"
(unpublished PH.D. thesis, U. of Barcelona). Peano, G., as. Opere Scelte, ed.
U. Cassina, 3 vols. (Roma: Cremonese, 1957- 59)· --, I897a. "Studii di
logica matematica". Repr. in 05,2: 201-17. --, I897b. "Logique
mathematique". Repr. in 05,2: 218-81. --, I898a. "Analisi della
teoria dei vettori". Repr. in 05,3: 187-2°7. --, I90oa. "Formules de
logique mathematique". Repr. in 05,2: 304-61. W. V. O. Quine, 1966a.
"Russell's Ontological Development", Journal of Philosophy, 63:
657-67. Repr. in R. Schoenman, ed., Bertrand Russell: Philosopher of the
Century (London: Allen and Unwin,1967). Resnik, M., I965a. "Frege's Theory
of Incomplete Entities", Philosophy of Science, 32: 329-41. E. A.
Rodriguez-Consuegra, 1987a. "Russell's Logicist Definitions of Numbers
1899-1913: Chronology and Significance", History and Philosophy of Logic,
8:141- 69. --, I988a. "Elementos logicistas en la obra de Peano y su
escuela", Mathesis, 4: 221-99· --, I989a. "Russell's Theory ofTypes,
1901-1910: Its Complex Origins in the Unpublished Manuscripts", History
and Philosophy ofLogic, 10: 131-64. --, I990a. "The Origins of Russell's
Theory of Descriptions according to the Unpublished Manuscripts", Russell,
n.s. 9: 99-132. --, I99Ia. The Mathematical Philosophy of BertrandRussell:
Origins and Development (Basel, Boston and Berlin: Birkhauser). --, I992a.
"A New Angle on Russell's 'Inextricable Tangle' over Meaning and
Denotation", Russell, n.s. 12 (1992): 197-207. Russell, B., I903a.
"On the Meaning and Denotation ofPhrases", Papers 4: 283- 96. --,
I905a. "The Existential Import of Propositions", Mind, 14: 398-401.
Repr. in I973a, pp. 98-103. --, I905b. "On Fundamentals", Papers 4:
359....,.413. --, I905c. "On Denoting", Mind, 14: 479-93. Repr. in
LK, pp. 41-56; Papers 4: 415-27. --, I905d "On Substitution".
Unpublished ms. (McMaster U., RAl 220.010940b). --, I906a. "On the
Substitutional Theory of Classes and Relations". In I973a, PP· 165-89· --,
I908a. "Mathematical Logic as Based on the Theory ofTypes", American
Journal of Mathematics, 30: 222-62. Repr. in LK, pp. 59-102. --, I973a. Essays
in Analysis, ed. D. Lackey (London: Allen & Unwin). Skosnik, 1972a.
"Russell's Unpublished Writings on Truth and Denoting", Russell, no.
7: 12-13. P. F. Strawson, 1950a. "On Referring". Repr. in Klemke
I970a, pp. 147-72. Tichy, P., I988a. The Foundations of Frege's Logic (Berlin:
de Gruyter). J. Walker, A Study o fFrege (Blackwell).
izzing: Athenian and Oxonian
dialectic.As Grice puts it, "Socrates, like us, was really trying to solve
linguistic puzzles."This is especially true in the longer dialogues of
Plato — the 'Republic' and the Laws'— where we learn quite a lot about
Socrates' method and philosophy, filtered, of course, through his devoted
pupil's mind.Some of the Pre-Socratics, who provide Plato and his master with
many of their problems, were in difficulties about how one thing could be two
things at once — say, a white horse. How could you say 'This is a horse
and this is white' without saying 'This one thing is two things'? Socrates
and Plato together solved this puzzle by saying that what was meant by
saying 'The horse is white' is that the horse partakes of the
eternal, and perfect, Form horseness, which was invisible but really more
horselike than any worldly Dobbin; and ditto about the Form whiteness: it was
whiter than any earthly white. The theory of Form covers our whole world
of ships and shoes and humpty-dumptys, which, taken all in all, are shadows —
approximations of those invisible, perfect Forms. Using the sharp tools in
our new linguistic chest, we can whittle Plato down to size and say that he
invented his metaphysical world of Forms to solve the problem of different
kinds of 'is'es -- what Grice calls the 'izz' proper and the 'izz' improper
('strictly, a 'hazz').You see how Grice, an Oxford counterpart of Plato, uses a
very simple grammatical tool in solving problems like this. Instead of
conjuring up an imaginary edifice of Forms, he simply says there are two
different types of 'is'es — one of predication and one of identity -- 'the izz'
and the 'hazz not.' The first, the 'izz' (which is really a 'hazz' -- it
is a 'hizz' for Socrates being 'rational') asserts a quality: this is
white.' The second 'hazz' points to the object named: 'This is a
horse.' By this simple grammatical analysis we clear away the rubble of
what were Plato's Forms. That's why an Oxford philosopher loves Aristotle
-- and his Athenian dialectic -- (Plato worked in suburbia, The Academy) -- who
often, when defining a thing — for example, 'virtue' — asked himself, 'Does the
definition square with the ordinary views (ta legomena) of men?' But while
Grice does have this or that antecedent, he is surely an innovator in
concentrating MOST (if not all) of his attention on what he calls 'the
conversational implicaturum.'Grice has little patience with past
philosophers.Why bother listening to men whose problems arose from bad grammar?
(He excludes Ariskant here). At present, we are mostly preoccupied with
language and grammar. Grice would never dream of telling his tutee what he
ought to do, the kind of life he ought to lead.That was no longer an aim of
philosophy, he explained, but even though philosophy has changed in its aims
and methods, people have not, and that was the reason for the complaining
tutees -- the few of them -- , for the bitter attacks of Times' correspondents,
and even, perhaps, for his turning his back on philosophy. Grice came to
feel that Oxford philosophy was a minor revolutionary movement — at least when
it is seen through the eyes of past philosophers. I asked him about the
fathers of the revolution. Again he was evasive. Strictly speaking,
the minor revolution is fatherless, except that Bertrand Russell, G. E. Moore,
and Vitters — all of them, as it happened, Cambridge University figures —
"are responsible for the present state of things at Oxford." under
‘conjunctum,’ we see that there is an alternative vocabulary, of ‘copulatum.’
But Grice prefers to narrow the use of ‘copula’ to izzing’ and ‘hazzing.’ Oddly,
Grice sees izzing as a ‘predicate,’ and symbolises it as Ixy. While he prefers
‘x izzes y,’ he also uses ‘x izz y.’ Under izzing comes Grice’s discussion of
essential predicate, essence, and substance qua predicabilia (secondary
substance). As opposed to ‘hazzing,’ which covers all the ‘ta sumbebeka,’ or
‘accidentia.’ Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Aristotle on the multiplicity of ‘being.’”
jacobi: man of letters,
popular novelist, and author of several influential philosophical works. His “Ueber
die Lehre des Spinoza” precipitates a dispute with Mendelssohn on Lessing’s
alleged pantheism. The ensuing Pantheismusstreit (pantheism controversy)
focused attention on the apparent conflict between human freedom and any
systematic, philosophical interpretation of reality. In the appendix to his
David Hume über den Glauben, oder Idealismus und Realismus (“David Hume on
Belief, or Idealism and Realism,” 1787), Jacobi scrutinized the new
transcendental philosophy of Kant, and subjected Kant’s remarks concerning
“things-in-themselves” to devastating criticism, observing that, though one
could not enter the critical philosophy without presupposing the existence of
things-in-themselves, such a belief is incompatible with the tenets of that
philosophy. This criticism deeply influenced the efforts of post-Kantians
(e.g., Fichte) to improve transcendental idealism. In 1799, in an “open letter”
to Fichte, Jacobi criticized philosophy in general and transcendental idealism
in particular as “nihilism.” Jacobi espoused a fideistic variety of direct
realism and characterized his own standpoint as one of “nonknowing.” Employing
the arguments of “Humean skepticism,” he defended the necessity of a “leap of
faith,” not merely in morality and religion, but in every area of human life.
Jacobi’s criticisms of reason and of science profoundly influenced German
Romanticism. Near the end of his career he entered bitter public controversies
with Hegel and Schelling concerning the relationship between faith and
knowledge.
james: w. New-World philosopher,
psychologist, and one of the founders of pragmatism. He was born in New York,
the oldest of five children and elder brother of the novelist Henry James and
diarist Alice James. Their father, Henry James, Sr., was an unorthodox
religious philosopher, deeply influenced by the thought of Swedenborg, some of
which seeped into William’s later fascination with psychical research. The
James family relocated to Cambridge, Massachusetts, but the father insisted on
his children obtaining an Old-World education, and prolonged trips to England
and the Continent were routine, a procedure that made William multilingual and
extraordinarily cosmopolitan. In fact, a pervasive theme in James’s personal
and creative life was his deep split between things New-World and Old-World
Europe: he felt like a bigamist “coquetting with too many countries.” As a
person, James is extraordinarily sensitive to psychological and bodily
experiences. He could be described as “neurasthenic” – afflicted with constant
psychosomatic symptoms such as dyspepsia, vision problems, and clinical
depression. In 1868 he recorded a profound personal experience, a “horrible
fear of my own existence.” In two 1870 diary entries, James first contemplates
suicide and then pronounces his belief in free will and his resolve to act on
that belief in “doing, suffering and creating.” Under the influence of the then
burgeoning work in experimental psychology, James attempted to sustain, on
empirical grounds, his belief in the self as Promethean, as self-making rather
than as a playing out of inheritance or the influence of social context. This
bold and extreme doctrine of individuality is bolstered by his attack on both
the neo-Hegelian and associationist doctrines. He held that both approaches
miss the empirical reality of relations as affectively experienced and the
reality of consciousness as a “stream,” rather than an aspect of an Absolute or
simply a box holding a chain of concepts corresponding to single sense
impressions. In 1890, James published his masterpiece, The Principles of
Psychology, which established him as the premier psychologist of the
Euro-American world. It was a massive compendium and critique of virtually all
of the psychology literature then extant, but it also claimed that the
discipline was in its infancy. James believed that the problems he had
unearthed could only be understood by a philosophical approach. James held only
one academic degree, an M.D. from Harvard, and his early teaching at Harvard
was in anatomy and physiology. He subsequently became a professor of
psychology, but during the writing of the Principles, he began to teach
philosophy as a colleague of Royce and Santayana. From 1890 forward James saw
the fundamental issues as at bottom philosophical and he undertook an intense
inquiry into matters epistemological and metaphysical; in particular, “the
religious question” absorbed him. The Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular
Philosophy was published in 1897. The lead essay, “The Will to Believe,” had
been widely misunderstood, partly because it rested on unpublished metaphysical
assumptions and partly because it ran aggressively counter to the reigning
dogmas of social Darwinism and neo-Hegelian absolutism, both of which
denigrated the personal power of the individual. For James, one cannot draw a
conclusion, fix a belief, or hold to a moral or religious maxim unless all
suggestions of an alternative position are explored. Further, some alternatives
will be revealed only if one steps beyond one’s frame of reference, seeks
novelty, and “wills to believe” in possibilities beyond present sight. The risk
taking in such an approach to human living is further detailed in James’s essays
“The Dilemma of Determinism” and “The Moral Philosopher and the Moral Life,”
both of which stress the irreducibility of ambiguity, the presence of chance,
and the desirability of tentativeness in our judgments. After presenting the
Gifford Lectures in 1901– 02, James published his classic work, The Varieties
of Religious Experience, which coalesced his interest in psychic states both
healthy and sick and afforded him the opportunity to present again his firm
belief that human life is characterized by a vast array of personal, cultural,
and religious approaches that cannot and should not be reduced one to the
other. For James, the “actual peculiarities of the world” must be central to
any philosophical discussion of truth. In his Hibbert Lectures of 1909,
published as A Pluralistic Universe, James was to represent this sense of
plurality, openness, and the variety of human experience on a wider canvas, the
vast reach of consciousness, cosmologically understood. Unknown to all but a
few philosophical correspondents, James had been assiduously filling notebooks
with reflections on the mind–body problem and the relationship between meaning
and truth and with a philosophical exploration and extension of his doctrine of
relations as found earlier in the Principles. In 1904–05 James published a
series of essays, gathered posthumously in 1912, on the meaning of experience
and the problem of knowledge. In a letter to François Pillon in 1904, he
writes: “My philosophy is what I call a radical empiricism, a pluralism, a
‘tychism,’ which represents order as being gradually won and always in the
making.” Following his 1889 essay “On Some Omissions of Introspective
Psychology” and his chapter on “The Stream of Thought” in the Principles, James
takes as given that relations between things are equivalently experienced as
the things themselves. Consequently, “the only meaning of essence is
teleological, and that classification and conception are purely teleological
weapons of the mind.” The description of consciousness as a stream having a
fringe as well as a focus, and being selective all the while, enables him to
take the next step, the formulation of his pragmatic epistemology, one that was
influenced by, but is different from, that of Peirce. Published in 1907,
Pragmatism generated a transatlantic furor, for in it James unabashedly states
that “Truth happens to be an idea. It becomes true, is made true by events.” He
also introduces the philosophically notorious claim that “theories” must be
found that will “work.” Actually, he means that a proposition cannot be judged
as true independently of its consequences as judged by experience. James’s
prose, especially in Pragmatism, alternates between scintillating and limpid.
This quality led to both obfuscation of his intention and a lulling of his
reader into a false sense of simplicity. He does not deny the standard
definition of truth as a propositional claim about an existent, for he writes
“woe to him whose beliefs play fast and loose with the order which realities
follow in his experience; they will lead him nowhere or else make false
connexions.” Yet he regards this structure as but a prologue to the creative
activity of the human mind. Also in Pragmatism, speaking of the world as
“really malleable,” he argues that man engenders truths upon reality. This
tension between James as a radical empiricist with the affirmation of the
blunt, obdurate relational manifold given to us in our experience and James as
a pragmatic idealist holding to the constructing, engendering power of the
Promethean self to create its own personal world, courses throughout all of his
work. James was chagrined and irritated by the quantity, quality, and ferocity
of the criticism leveled at Pragmatism. He attempted to answer those critics in
a book of disparate essays, The Meaning of Truth (1909). The book did little to
persuade his critics; since most of them were unaware of his radically
empirical metaphysics and certainly of his unpublished papers, James’s
pragmatism remained misunderstood until the publication of Perry’s magisterial
two-volume study, The Thought and Character of William James (1935). By 1910,
James’s heart disease had worsened; he traveled to Europe in search of some
remedy, knowing full well that it was a farewell journey. Shortly after
returning to his summer home in Chocorua, New Hampshire, he died. One month
earlier he had said of a manuscript (posthumously published in 1911 as Some
Problems in Philosophy), “say that by it I hoped to round out my system, which
is now too much like an arch only on one side.” Even if he had lived much
longer, it is arguable that the other side of the arch would not have appeared,
for his philosophy was ineluctably geared to seeking out the novel, the
surprise, the tychistic, and the plural, and to denying the finality of all
conclusions. He warned us that “experience itself, taken at large, can grow by
its edges” and no matter how laudable or seductive our personal goal, “life is
in the transitions.” The Works of William James, including his unpublished manuscripts,
have been collected in a massive nineteen-volume critical edition by Harvard
University Press (1975–88). His work can be seen as an imaginative vestibule
into the twentieth century. His ideas resonate in the work of Royce, Unamuno,
Niels Bohr, Husserl, M. Montessori, Dewey, and Wittgenstein. Refs.: H. P.
Grice, “William James’s England and what he learned there!”
James-Lange theory, the theory, put
forward by James and independently by Lange, an anatomist, that an emotion is
the felt awareness of bodily reactions to something perceived or thought
(James) or just the bodily reactions themselves (Lange). According to the more
influential version (James, “What Is an Emotion?” Mind, 1884), “our natural way
of thinking” mistakenly supposes that the perception or thought causes the
emotion, e.g., fear or anger, which in turn causes the bodily reactions, e.g.,
rapid heartbeat, weeping, trembling, grimacing, and actions such as running and
striking. In reality, however, the fear or anger consists in the bodily
sensations caused by these reactions. In support of this theory, James proposed
a thought experiment: Imagine feeling some “strong” emotion, one with a
pronounced “wave of bodily disturbance,” and then subtract in imagination the
felt awareness of this disturbance. All that remains, James found, is “a cold
and neutral state of intellectual perception,” a cognition lacking in emotional
coloration. Consequently, it is our bodily feelings that emotionalize
consciousness, imbuing our perceptions and thoughts with emotional qualities
and endowing each type of emotion, such as fear, anger, and joy, with its
special feeling quality. But this does not warrant James’s radical conclusion
that emotions or emotional states are effects rather than causes of bodily
reactions. That conclusion requires the further assumption, which James shared
with many of his contemporaries, that the various emotions are nothing but
particular feeling qualities. Historically, the James-Lange theory led to
further inquiries into the physiological and cognitive causes of emotional
feelings and helped transform the psychology of emotions from a descriptive
study relying on introspection to a broader naturalistic inquiry.
Jansenism, a set of doctrines advanced by philosophers
in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, characterized by a predestinarianism
that emphasized Adam’s fall (“il pecato originale di Adamo”) irresistible
efficacious grace (“grice”), limited atonement, election, and reprobation.
Addressing the issue of free will and grace left open by the Council of Trent, Cornelius
Jansen crystallized the seventeenth-century Augustinian revival, producing a
compilation of Augustine’s anti-Pelagian teachings (Augustinus). Propagated by
Saint Cyran and Antoine Arnauld (On Frequent Communion, 1643), adopted by the
nuns of Port-Royal, and defended against Jesuit attacks by Pascal (Provincial
Letters, 1656–57), Jansenism pervaded Roman Catholicism from Utrecht to Rome
for over 150 years. Condemned by Pope Innocent X (Cum Occasione, 1653) and
crushed by Louis XIV and the French clergy (the 1661 formulary), it survived
outside France and rearmed for a counteroffensive. Pasquier Quesnel’s
(1634–1719) “second Jansenism,” condemned by Pope Clement XI (Unigenitus,
1713), was less Augustinian, more rigorist, and advocated Presbyterianism and
Gallicanism.
jaspers: philosopher, one
of the main representatives of the existentialist movement (although he
rejected ‘existentialism’ as a distortion of the philosophy of existence). Jaspers
studied law and medicine at Heidelberg, Munich, Berlin, and Göttingen. He
concluded his studies with an M.D. (Homesickness and Crime) from Heidelberg. From
1908 until 1915 he worked as a voluntary assistant in the psychiatric clinic,
and published his first major work (Allgemeine Psychopathologie, 1913; General
Psychopathology, 1965). After his habilitation in psychology (1913) Jaspers
lectured as Privatdocent. In 1919 he published Psychologie der Weltanschauung
(“Psychology of Worldviews”). Two years later he became professor in
philosophy. Because of his personal convictions and marriage with Gertrud Mayer
(who was Jewish) the Nazi government took away his professorship in 1937 and
suppressed all publications. He and his wife were saved from deportation
because the American army liberated Heidelberg a few days before the fixed date
of April 14, 1945. In 1948 he accepted a professorship from the University of
Basel. As a student, Jaspers felt a strong aversion to academic philosophy.
However, as he gained insights in the fields of psychiatry and psychology, he
realized that both the study of human beings and the meaning of scientific
research pointed to questions and problems that demanded their own thoughts and
reflections. Jaspers gave a systematic account of them in his three-volume
Philosophie (1931; with postscript, 1956; Philosophy, 1969–71), and in the
1,100 pages of Von der Wahrheit (On Truth, 1947). In the first volume
(“Philosophical World-orientation”) he discusses the place and meaning of
philosophy with regard to the human situation in general and scientific
disciplines in particular. In the second (“Clarification of Existence”), he
contrasts the compelling modes of objective (scientific) knowledge with the
possible (and in essence non-objective) awareness of being in self-relation,
communication, and historicity, both as being oneself presents itself in
freedom, necessity, and transcendence, and as existence encounters its
unconditionality in limit situations (of death, suffering, struggle, guilt) and
the polar intertwining of subjectivity and objectivity. In the third volume
(“Metaphysics”) he concentrates on the meaning of transcendence as it becomes
translucent in appealing ciphers (of nature, history, consciousness, art, etc.)
to possible existence under and against the impact of stranding. His Von der
Wahrheit is the first volume of a projected work on philosophical logic (cf.
Nachlaß zur philosophischen Logik, ed. H. Saner and M. Hänggi, 1991) in which
he develops the more formal aspects of his philosophy as “periechontology”
(ontology of the encompassing, des Umgreifenden, with its modes of being there,
consciousness, mind, existence, world, transcendence, reason) and clarification
of origins. In both works Jaspers focuses on “existential philosophy” as “that
kind of thinking through which man tries to become himself both as thinking
makes use of all real knowledge and as it transcends this knowledge. This
thinking does not recognize objects, but clarifies and enacts at once the being
of the one who thinks in this way” (Philosophische Autobiographie, 1953). In
his search for authentic existence in connection with the elaboration of
“philosophical faith” in reason and truth, Jaspers had to achieve a thorough
understanding of philosophical, political, and religious history as well as an
adequate assessment of the present situation. His aim became a world philosophy
as a possible contribution to universal peace out of the spirit of free and
limitless communication, unrestricted open-mindedness, and unrelenting
truthfulness. Besides a comprehensive history of philosophy (Die groben
Philosophen I, 1957; II and III, 1981; The Great Philosophers, 2 vols., 1962,
1966) and numerous monographs (on Cusanus, Descartes, Leonardo da Vinci,
Schelling, Nietzsche, Strindberg, van Gogh, Weber) he wrote on subjects such as
the university (Die Idee der Universität, 1946; The Idea of the University,
1959), the spiritual situation of the age (Die geistige Situation der Zeit,
1931; Man in the Modern Age, 1933), the meaning of history (Vom Ursprung und
Ziel der Geschichte, 1949; The Origin and Goal of History, in which he
developed the idea of an “axial period”), the guilt question (Die Schuldfrage,
1946; The Question of German Guilt, 1947), the atomic bomb (Die Atombombe und
die Zukunft des Menschen, 1958; The Future of Mankind, 1961), German politics
(Wohin treibt die Bundesrepublik? 1966; The Future of Germany, 1967). He also
wrote on theology and religious issues (Die Frage der Entymythologisierung.
Eine Diskussion mit Rudolf Bultmann, 1954; Myth and Christianity, 1958; Der
philosophische Glaube angesichts der Offenbarung, 1962; Philosophical Faith and
Revelation, 1967).
jevons: w. s., philosopher
of science. In economics, he clarified the idea of value, arguing that it is a
function of utility. Later theorists imitated his use of the calculus and other
mathematical tools to reach theoretical results. His approach anticipated the
idea of marginal utility, a notion basic in modern economics. Jevons regarded
J. S. Mill’s logic as inadequate, preferring the new symbolic logic of Boole.
One permanent contribution was his introduction of the concept of inclusive
‘or’, with ‘or’ meaning ‘either or, or both’. To aid in teaching the new logic
of classes and propositions, Jevons invented his “logical piano.” In opposition
to the confidence in induction of Mill and Whewell, both of whom thought, for
different reasons, that induction can arrive at exact and necessary truths,
Jevons argued that science yields only approximations, and that any perfect fit
between theory and observation must be grounds for suspicion that we are wrong,
not for confidence that we are right. Jevons introduced probability theory to
show how rival hypotheses are evaluated. He was a subjectivist, holding that
probability is a measure of what a perfectly rational person would believe
given the available evidence. H. P. Grice: “Jevons’s Aristotle.”
da Floris: Italian philosopher, the
founder the order of Ciscercian order of San Giovanni in Fiore (vide, Grice,
“St. John’s and the Cistercians”). He devoted the rest of his life to
meditation and the recording of his prophetic visions. In his major works Liber
concordiae Novi ac Veteri Testamenti (“Book of the Concordances between the New
and the Old Testament,” 1519), Expositio in Apocalypsim (1527), and Psalterium
decem chordarum (1527), Joachim illustrates the deep meaning of history as he
perceived it in his visions. History develops in coexisting patterns of twos
and threes. The two testaments represent history as divided in two phases
ending in the First and Second Advent, respectively. History progresses also
through stages corresponding to the Holy Trinity. The age of the Father is that
of the law; the age of the Son is that of grace, ending approximately in 1260; the
age of the Spirit will produce a spiritualized church. Some monastic orders
like the Franciscans and Dominicans saw themselves as already belonging to this
final era of spirituality and interpreted Joachim’s prophecies as suggesting
the overthrow of the contemporary ecclesiastical institutions. Some of his
views were condemned by the Lateran Council in 1215.
philoponus: Grecian philosopher and
theologian, who worked in Alexandria (“philoponus,” ‘workaholic’, just a
nickname). A Christian from birth, he was a pupil of the Platonist Ammonius,
and is the first Christian Aristotelian. As such, he challenged Aristotle on
many points where he conflicted with Christian doctrine, e.g. the eternity of
the world, the need for an infinite force, the definition of place, the
impossibility of a vacuum, and the necessity for a fifth element to be the
substance of the heavens. Johannes composed commentaries on Aristotle’s
Categories, Prior and Posterior Analytics, Meteorologics, and On the Soul; and
a treatise Against Proclus: On the Eternity of the World. There is dispute as
to whether the commentaries exhibit a change of mind (away from orthodox
Aristotelianism) on these questions.
Damascenus Chrysorrhoas: Greican theologian
and Eastern church doctor. Born of a well-to-do family in Damascus, he was
educated in Greek. He attained a high position in government but resigned under
the antiChristian Caliph Abdul Malek and became a monk about 700, living
outside Jerusalem. He left extensive writings, most little more than compilations
of older texts. The Iconoclastic Synod of 754 condemned his arguments in
support of the veneration of images in the three Discourses against the
Iconoclasts (726–30), but his orthodoxy was confirmed in 787 at the Second
Council of Nicaea. His Sources of Knowledge consists of a Dialectic, a history
of heresies, and an exposition of orthodoxy. Considered a saint from the end of
the eighth century, he was much respected in the East and was regarded as an
important witness to Eastern Orthodox thought by the West in the Middle Ages.
Poinsot: philosopher, studied at Louvain,
entered the Dominican order (1610), and taught at Piacenza. His most important
works are the Cursus philosophicus, a work on logic and natural philosophy; and
the Cursus theologicus (“Course of Theology,” 1637–44), a commentary on
Aquinas’s Summa theologiae. John considered himself a Thomist, but he modified
Aquinas’s views in important ways. The “Ars Logica,” the first part of the
Cursus philosophicus, is the source of much subsequent Catholic teaching in
logic. It is divided into two parts: the first deals with formal logic and
presents a comprehensive theory of terms, propositions, and reasoning; the
second discusses topics in material logic, such as predicables, categories, and
demonstration. An important contribution in the first is a comprehensive theory
of signs that has attracted considerable attention in the twentieth century
among such philosophers as Maritain, Yves Simon, John Wild, and others. An
important contribution in the second part is the division of knowledge
according to physical, mathematical, and metaphysical degrees, which was later
adopted by Maritain. John dealt with metaphysical problems in the second part
of the Cursus philosophicus and in the Cursus theologicus. His views are
modifications of Aquinas’s. For example, Aquinas held that the principle of
individuation is matter designated by quantity; John interpreted this as matter
radically determined by dimensions, where the dimensions are indeterminate. In contrast
to other major figures of the Spanish Scholasticism of the times, John did not
write much in political and legal theory. He considered ethics and political
philosophy to be speculative rather than practical sciences, and adopted a form
of probabilism. Moreover, when in doubt about a course of action, one may
simply adopt any pertinent view proposed by a prudent moralist.
salisbury: Grice: “One
should not confuse Salisbury with Salisbury.” English philosopher, tutored by
Abelard and Gilbert of Poitiers in Paris. It is possible that during this time
he also studied grammar, rhetoric, and part of the quadrivium with Conches at
Chartres. After 1147 he was for a time a member of the Roman Curia, secretary
to Theobald, archbishop of Canterbury, and friend of Thomas Becket. For his
role in Becket’s canonization, Louis VII of France rewarded him with the
bishopric of Chartres. Salisbury is a dedicated student of philosophy. In his
letters, biographies of Anselm and Becket, and Memoirs of the Papal Court, Salisbury
provides, in perhaps the best medieval imitation of classical Latin style, an
account of some of the most important ideas, events, and personalities of his
time. Neither these works nor his Polycraticus and “Metalogicon,” for which he
is most celebrated, are systematic philosophical treatises. The “Polycraticus” is,
however, considered one of the first medieval treatises to take up political
theory in any extended way. Salisbury maintains that if a ruler does not
legislate in accordance with natural moral law, legitimate resistance to him
can include his assassination. In the “Metalogicon,” on the other hand,
Salisbury discusses, in a humanist spirit, the benefits for a civilized world
of philosophical training based on Aristotle’s logic. He also presents current
views on the nature of the universale and, not surprisingly, endorses an
Aristotelian view of them as neither extramental entities nor mere expressum,
but a conceptus that nevertheless has a basis in reality insofar as they are
the result of the mind’s abstracting from extramental entities what those entities
have in common.
johnson: Grice, “Not to be
confused with Dr. Johnson – this one was as a philosopher should just be, an
MA, like me!” -- w. e., very English philosopher who lectured on psychology and
logic at Cambridge University. His Logic was published in three parts: Part I
(1921); Part II, Demonstrative Inference: Deductive and Inductive (1922); and
Part III, The Logical Foundations of Science (1924). He did not complete Part
IV on probability, but in 1932 Mind published three of its intended chapters.
Johnson’s other philosophical publications, all in Mind, were not abundant. The
discussion note “On Feeling as Indifference” (1888) deals with problems of
classification. “The Logical Calculus” (three parts, 1892) anticipates the
“Cambridge” style of logic while continuing the tradition of Jevons and Venn;
the same is true of treatments of formal logic in Logic. “Analysis of Thinking”
(two parts, 1918) advances an adverbial theory of experience. Johnson’s
philosophic influence at Cambridge exceeded the influence of these
publications, as one can see from the references to him by John Neville Keynes
in Studies and Exercises in Formal Logic and by his son John Maynard Keynes in
A Treatise on Probability. Logic contains original and distinctive treatments
of induction, metaphysics, the philosophy of mind, and philosophical logic.
Johnson’s theory of inference proposes a treatment of implication that is an
alternative to the view of Russell and Whitehead in Principia Mathematica. He
coined the term ‘ostensive definition’ and introduced the distinction between
determinates and determinables.
jung: founder of
analytical psychology, a form of psychoanalysis that differs from Freud’s
chiefly by an emphasis on the collective character of the unconscious and on
archetypes as its privileged contents. Jung, like Freud, was deeply influenced
by philosophy in his early years. Before his immersion in psychiatry, he wrote
several essays of explicitly philosophical purport. Kant was doubtless the
philosopher who mattered most to Jung, for whom archetypes were conceived as a
priori structures of the human psyche. Plato and Neoplatonists, Schopenhauer
and especially Nietzsche (to whose Zarathustra he devoted a seminar of several
years’ duration) were also of critical importance. Oddly, Jung was a close
reader of James (in German translation, of course), and his Psychological Types
(1921) – in addition to an extended discussion of nominalism versus realism – contains
a detailed treatment of Jamesian typologies of the self. Jung considered the
self to be an amalgamation of an “ectopsyche” – consisting of four functions
(intuition, sensation, feeling, and thinking) that surround an ego construed
not as a singular entity but as a “complex” of ideas and emotions – and an
“endosphere” (i.e., consciousness turned inward in memory, affect, etc.). The
personal unconscious, which preoccupied Freud, underlies the endosphere and its
“invasions,” but it is in turn grounded in the collective unconscious shared by
all humankind. The collective unconscious was induced by Jung from his analysis
of dream symbols and psychopathological symptoms. It is an inherited archive of
archaic-mythic forms and figures that appear repeatedly in the most diverse
cultures and historical epochs. Such forms and figures – also called archetypes
– are considered “primordial images” preceding the “ideas” that articulate
rational thought. As a consequence, the self, rather than being autonomous, is embedded
in a prepersonal and prehistoric background from which there is no effective
escape. However, through prolonged psychotherapeutically guided
“individuation,” a slow assimilation of the collective unconscious into daily
living can occur, leading to an enriched and expanded sense of experience and
selfhood.
jurisprudence: McEvoy.
Hart,
Grice’s favourite prudens, iurisprudens: jurisprudence, the science or “knowledge”
of law; thus, in its widest usage, the study of the legal doctrines, rules, and
principles of any legal system, especially that which is valid at Oxford. More
commonly, however, ‘prudens,’ or ‘iurisprudens’ designates the study not of the
actual laws of particular legal systems, but of the general concepts and
principles that underlie a legal system or that are common to every such system
(general jurisprudence). Jurisprudence in this usage, sometimes also called the
philosophy of law – but Grice preferred, “philosophical jurisprudence”) may be
further subdivided according to the major focus of a particular study. Examples
include Roman and English historical jurisprudence (a study of the development
of legal principles over time, often emphasizing the origin of law in custom or
tradition rather than in enacted rules), sociological jurisprudence (an
examination of the relationship between legal rules and the behavior of
individuals, groups, or institutions), functional jurisprudence (an inquiry
into the relationship between legal norms and underlying social interests or
needs), and analytical jurisprudence (an investigation into the connections
among legal concepts). Within analytical jurisprudence the most substantial
body of thought focuses on the meaning of the concept of law itself (legal
theory) and the relationship between that concept and the concept of the moral.
Legal positivism, the view that there is no necessary connection between legal (a
legal right) and the moral (a moral right), opposes the natural law view that
no sharp distinction between these concepts can be drawn. Legal positivism is
sometimes thought to be a consequence of positivism’s insistence that legal
validity is determined ultimately by reference to certain basic social facts:
“the command of the sovereign” (Austin – “the other Austin, the benevolent
one!” -- Grice), the Grundnorm (Kelsen), or “the rule of re-cognition” (Hart).
These different positivist characterizations of the basic, law-determining FACT
yield different claims about the normative character of law, with classical
positivists (e.g., John Austin) insisting that legal systems are essentially
coercive, whereas modern positivists (e.g., Hans Kelsen) maintain that they are
normative. Disputes within legal theory often generate or arise out of disputes
about theories of adjudication, or how a judge does or should decide a case.
Mechanical jurisprudence, or formalism, the theory that all cases can be
decided solely by analyzing a legal concept, is thought by many to have
characterized judicial decisions and legal reasoning in the nineteenth century;
that theory became an easy target in the twentieth century for various forms of
legal ‘realism,’ the view (which Grice found pretentious) that law is better
determined by observing what a court and a citizen actually does than by
analyzing stated legal rules and concepts. Recent developments in the natural
law tradition also focus on the process of adjudication and the normative claim
that accompany the judicial declaration of legal rights and obligations. These
normative claim, the natural law theorist argues, show a legal right is a
species of a political right or a moral right. In consequence, one must either
revise prevailing theories of adjudication and abandon the social-fact theory
of law (New-World Dworkin), or explore the connection between legal theory and
the classical question of political theory. Under what condition does a legal
obligation, even if determined by an inter-subjetctive fact, create a genuine
political obligation (e.g., the meta-obligation to obey the law)? Other
jurisprudential notions that overlap topics in political theory include rule of
law, legal moralism, and civil disobedience. The disputes within legal theory
about the connection between law and morality should not be confused with
discussions of “natural law” within moral theory. In Grice’s meta-ethics,
so-called “natural law” denotes a particular view about the objective status of
a moral norm that has produced a considerable literature, extending from
ancient Grecian and Roman thought, through medieval theological writings, to
contemporary Oxonian ethical thought. Though the claim that one cannot sharply
separate law and morality is often made as part of a general natural law moral
theory, the referents of ‘natural law’ in legal and moral theory do not share
any obvious logical relationship. A moral theorist may conclude that there is
NO necessary connection between law and morality, thus endorsing a positivist
view of law, while consistently advocating a natural law view of morality
itself. Conversely, as Grice notes, a natural law legal theorist, in accepting
the view that there IS a connection (or priority) between law and morality (a
moral right being evaluational prior than a legal right, even if not
epistemically prior), might nonetheless endorse a substantive moral theory different
from that implied by a natural law moral theory. Refs.: G. P. Baker, “Meaning
and defeasibility,” in Festschrift for H. L. A. Hart, G. P. Baker, “Alternative mind styles,” in
Festschrift for H. P. Grice, H. L. A. Hart, “Grice” in “The nightmare,” H. P.
Grice, “Moral right and legal right: three types of conceptual priority.”
jury nullification, a jury’s ability, or
the exercise of that ability, to acquit a criminal defendant despite finding
facts that leave no reasonable doubt about violation of a criminal statute.
This ability is not a right, but an artifact of criminal procedure. In the
common law, the jury has sole authority to determine the facts, and the judge
to determine the law. The jury’s findings of fact cannot be reviewed. The term
‘nullification’ suggests that jury nullification is opposed to the rule of law.
This thought would be sound only if an extreme legal positivism were true –
that the law is nothing but the written law and the written law covers every
possible fact situation. Jury nullification is better conceived as a form of
equity, a rectification of the inherent limits of written law. In nullifying,
juries make law. To make jury nullification a right, then, raises problems of
democratic legitimacy, such as whether a small, randomly chosen group of
citizens has authority to make law.
de
jure:
Or titular, as opposed to ‘de facto.’ Each getting what he is due. Formal
justice is the impartial and consistent application of a Kantian principle,
whether or not the principle itself is just. Substantive justice is closely
associated with rights, i.e., with what individuals can legitimately demand of
one another or what they can legitimately demand of their government (e.g.,
with respect to the protection of liberty or the promotion of equality).
Retributive justice concerns when and why punishment is justified. Debate
continues over whether punishment is justified as retribution for past
wrongdoing or because it deters future wrongdoing. Those who stress retribution
as the justification for punishment usually believe human beings have
libertarian free will, while those who stress deterrence usually accept
determinism. At least since Aristotle, justice has commonly been identified
both with obeying law and with treating everyone with fairness. But if law is,
and justice is not, entirely a matter of convention, then justice cannot be
identified with obeying law. The literature on legal positivism and natural law
theory contains much debate about whether there are moral limits on what
conventions could count as law. Corrective justice concerns the fairness of
demands for civil damages. Commutative justice concerns the fairness of wages,
prices, and exchanges. Distributive justice concerns the fairness of the
distribution of resources. Commutative justice and distributive justice are
related, since people’s wages influence how much resources they have. But the
distinction is important because it may be just to pay A more than B (because A
is more productive than B) but just that B is left with more after-tax
resources (because B has more children to feed than A does). In modern
philosophy, however, the debate about just wages and prices has been
overshadowed by the larger question of what constitutes a just distribution of
resources. Some (e.g., Marx) have advocated distributing resources in
accordance with needs. Others have advocated their distribution in whatever way
maximizes utility in the long run. Others have argued that the fair
distribution is one that, in some sense, is to everyone’s advantage. Still
others have maintained that a just distribution is whatever results from the
free market. Some theorists combine these and other approaches.
iustificatum: “Late Latin; apparently
neither the Grecians nor Cicero saw the need for it!”– Grice. justification, a
concept of broad scope that spans epistemology and ethics and has as special
cases the concepts of apt belief and right action. The concept has, however,
highly varied application. Many things, of many different sorts, can be
justified. Prominent among them are beliefs and actions. To say that X is
justified is to say something positive about X. Other things being equal, it is
better that X be justified than otherwise. However, not all good entities are
justified. The storm’s abating may be good since it spares some lives, but it
is not thereby justified. What we can view as justified or unjustified is what
we can relate appropriately to someone’s faculties or choice. (Believers might
hence view the storm’s abating as justified after all, if they were inclined to
judge divine providence.) Just as in epistemology we need to distinguish
justification from truth, since either of these might apply to a belief in the
absence of the other, so in ethics we must distinguish justification from utility:
an action might be optimific but not justified, and justified but not
optimific. What is distinctive of justification is then the implied evaluation
of an agent (thus the connection, however remote, with faculties of choice). To
say that a belief is (epistemically) justified (apt) or to say that an action
is (ethically) justified (“right” – in one sense) is to make or imply a
judgment on the subject and how he or she has arrived at that action or belief.
Often a much narrower concept of justification is used, one according to which
X is justified only if X has been or at least can be justified through adducing
reasons. Such adducing of reasons can be viewed as the giving of an argument of
any of several sorts: e.g., conclusive, prima facie, inductive, or deductive. A
conclusive justification or argument adduces conclusive reasons for the
possible (object of) action or belief that figures in the conclusion. In turn,
such reasons are conclusive if and only if they raise the status of the
conclusion action or belief so high that the subject concerned would be well
advised to conclude deliberation or inquiry. A prima facie justification or
argument adduces a prima facie reason R (or more than one) in favor of the
possible (object of) action or belief O that figures in the conclusion. In
turn, R is a prima facie reason for O if and only if R specifies an advantage
or positive consideration in favor of O, one that puts O in a better light than
otherwise. Even if R is a prima facie reason for O, however, R can be outweighed,
overridden, or defeated by contrary considerations RH. Thus my returning a
knife that I promised to return to its rightful owner has in its favor the
prima facie reason that it is my legal obligation and the fulfillment of a
promise, but if the owner has gone raving mad, then there may be reasons
against returning the knife that override, outweigh, or defeat. (And there may
also be reasons that defeat a positive prima facie reason without amounting to
reasons for the opposite course. Thus it may emerge that the promise to return
the knife was extracted under duress.) A (valid) deductive argument for a
certain conclusion C is a sequence of thoughts or statements whose last member
is C (not necessarily last temporally, but last in the sequence) and each
member of which is either an assumption or premise of the argument or is based
on earlier members of the sequence in accordance with a sound principle of
necessary inference, such as simplification: from (P & Q) to P; or
addition: from P to (P or Q); or modus ponens: from P and (P only if Q) to Q.
Whereas the premises of a deductive argument necessarily entail the conclusion,
which cannot possibly fail to be true when the justice as fairness
justification 457 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 457 premises are all
true, the premises of an inductive argument do not thus entail its conclusion
but offer considerations that only make the conclusion in some sense more
probable than it would be otherwise. From the premises that it rains and that
if it rains the streets are wet, one may deductively derive the conclusion that
the streets are wet. However, the premise that I have tried to start my car on
many, many winter mornings during the two years since I bought it and that it
has always started, right up to and including yesterday, does not deductively
imply that it will start when I try today. Here the conclusion does not follow
deductively. Though here the reason provided by the premise is only an
inductive reason for believing the conclusion, and indeed a prima facie and
defeasible reason, nevertheless it might well be in our sense a conclusive
reason. For it might enable us rightfully to conclude inquiry and/or
deliberation and proceed to (action or, in this case) belief, while turning our
attention to other matters (such as driving to our destination).
Fides: -- justification by faith, the
characteristic doctrine of the Protestant Reformation that sinful human beings
can be justified before God through faith in Jesus Christ. ‘Being justified’ is
understood in forensic terms: before the court of divine justice humans are not
considered guilty because of their sins, but rather are declared by God to be
holy and righteous in virtue of the righteousness of Christ, which God counts
on their behalf. Justification is received by faith, which is not merely belief
in Christian doctrine but includes a sincere and heartfelt trust and commitment
to God in Christ for one’s salvation. Such faith, if genuine, leads to the
reception of the transforming influences of God’s grace and to a life of love,
obedience, and service to God. These consequences of faith, however, are
considered under the heading of sanctification rather than justification. The
rival Roman Catholic doctrine of justification – often mislabeled by Protestants
as “justification by works” – understands key terms differently. ‘Being just’
is understood not primarily in forensic terms but rather as a comprehensive
state of being rightly related to God, including the forgiveness of sins, the
reception of divine grace, and inner transformation. Justification is a work of
God initially accomplished at baptism; among the human “predispositions” for
justification are faith (understood as believing the truths God has revealed),
awareness of one’s sinfulness, hope in God’s mercy, and a resolve to do what
God requires. Salvation is a gift of God that is not deserved by human beings,
but the measure of grace bestowed depends to some extent on the sincere efforts
of the sinner who is seeking salvation. The Protestant and Catholic doctrines
are not fully consistent with each other, but neither are they the polar
opposites they are often made to appear by the caricatures each side offers of
the other.
Jus ad bellum, jus in bello: a set of
conditions justifying the resort to war (jus ad bellum) and prescribing how war
may permissibly be conducted (jus in bello). The theory is a Western approach
to the moral assessment of war that grew out of the Christian tradition
beginning with Augustine, later taking both religious and secular (including
legalist) forms. Proposed conditions for a just war vary in both number and
interpretation. Accounts of jus ad bellum typically require: (1) just cause: an
actual or imminent wrong against the state, usually a violation of rights, but
sometimes provided by the need to protect innocents, defend human rights, or
safeguard the way of life of one’s own or other peoples; (2) competent
authority: limiting the undertaking of war to a state’s legitimate rulers; (3)
right intention: aiming only at peace and the ends of the just cause (and not
war’s attendant suffering, death, and destruction); (4) proportionality:
ensuring that anticipated good not be outweighed by bad; (5) last resort:
exhausting peaceful alternatives before going to war; and (6) probability of
success: a reasonable prospect that war will succeed. Jus in bellorequires: (7)
proportionality: ensuring that the means used in war befit the ends of the just
cause and that their resultant good and bad, when individuated, be
proportionate in the sense of (4); and (8) discrimination: prohibiting the
killing of noncombatants and/or innocents. Sometimes conditions (4), (5), and
(6) are included in (1). The conditions are usually considered individually
necessary and jointly sufficient for a fully just war. But sometimes strength
of just cause is taken to offset some lack of proportion in means, and
sometimes absence of right intention is taken to render a war evil though not
necessarily unjust. Most just war theorists take jus ad bellum to warrant only
defensive wars. But some follow earlier literature and allow for just offensive
wars. Early theorists deal primarily with jus ad bellum, later writers with
both jus ad bellum and jus in bello. Recent writers stress jus in bello, with
particular attention to deterrence: the attempt, by instilling fear of
retaliation, to induce an adversary to refrain from attack. Some believe that
even though large-scale use of nuclear weapons would violate requirements of
proportionality and discrimination, the threatened use of such weapons can
maintain peace, and hence justify a system of nuclear deterrence.
Kabala
ariskant: “Today I’ll
lecture on Aristkant, or rather his second part,” – Grice. Kant (which Grice
spelt ‘cant,’ seeing that it was Scots) Immanuel, preeminent Scots philosopher
whose distinctive concern was to vindicate the authority of reason. He believed
that by a critical examination of its own powers, reason can distinguish
unjustifiable traditional metaphysical claims from the principles that are required
by our theoretical need to determine ourselves within spatiotemporal experience
and by our practical need to legislate consistently with all other rational
wills. Because these principles are necessary and discoverable, they defeat
empiricism and skepticism, and because they are disclosed as simply the
conditions of orienting ourselves coherently within experience, they contrast
with traditional rationalism and dogmatism. Kant was born and raised in the
eastern Prussian university town of Königsberg (today Kaliningrad), where,
except for a short period during which he worked as a tutor in the nearby
countryside, he spent his life as student and teacher. He was trained by
Pietists and followers of Leibniz and Wolff, but he was also heavily influenced
by Newton and Rousseau. In the 1750s his theoretical philosophy began
attempting to show how metaphysics must accommodate as certain the fundamental
principles underlying modern science; in the 1760s his 460 K 4065h-l.qxd
08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 460 practical philosophy began attempting to show (in
unpublished form) how our moral life must be based on a rational and
universally accessible self-legislation analogous to Rousseau’s political
principles. The breakthrough to his own distinctive philosophy came in the
1770s, when he insisted on treating epistemology as first philosophy. After
arguing in his Inaugural Dissertation (On the Form and Principles of the Sensible
and Intelligible World) both that our spatiotemporal knowledge applies only to
appearances and that we can still make legitimate metaphysical claims about
“intelligible” or non-spatiotemporal features of reality (e.g., that there is
one world of substances interconnected by the action of God), there followed a
“silent decade” of preparation for his major work, the epoch-making Critique of
Pure Reason (first or “A” edition, 1781; second or “B” edition, with many
revisions, 1787; Kant’s initial reaction to objections to the first edition
dominate his short review, Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics, 1783; the
full title of which means ‘preliminary investigations for any future
metaphysics that will be able to present itself as a science’, i.e., as a body
of certain truths). This work resulted in his mature doctrine of transcendental
idealism, namely, that all our theoretical knowledge is restricted to the
systematization of what are mere spatiotemporal appearances. This position is
also called formal or Critical idealism, because it criticizes theories and
claims beyond the realm of experience, while it also insists that although the
form of experience is ideal, or relative to us, this is not to deny the reality
of something independent of this form. Kant’s earlier works are usually called
pre-Critical not just because they precede his Critique but also because they
do not include a full commitment to this idealism. Kant supplemented his “first
Critique” (often cited just as “the” Critique) with several equally influential
works in practical philosophy – Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, Critique
of Practical Reason (the “second Critique,” 1788), and Metaphysics of Morals
(consisting of “Doctrine of Justice” and “Doctrine of Virtue,” 1797). Kant’s
philosophy culminated in arguments advancing a purely moral foundation for
traditional theological claims (the existence of God, immortality, and a
transcendent reward or penalty proportionate to our goodness), and thus was
characterized as “denying knowledge in order to make room for faith.” To be
more precise, Kant’s Critical project was to restrict theoretical knowledge in
such a way as to make it possible for practical knowledge to reveal how pure
rational faith has an absolute claim on us. This position was reiterated in the
Critique of Judgment (the “third Critique,” 1790), which also extended Kant’s
philosophy to aesthetics and scientific methodology by arguing for a priori but
limited principles in each of these domains. Kant was followed by radical
idealists (Fichte, Schelling), but he regarded himself as a philosopher of the
Enlightenment, and in numerous shorter works he elaborated his belief that
everything must submit to the “test of criticism,” that human reason must face
the responsibility of determining the sources, extent, and bounds of its own
principles. The Critique concerns pure reason because Kant believes all these
determinations can be made a priori, i.e., such that their justification does
not depend on any particular course of experience (‘pure’ and ‘a priori’ are
thus usually interchangeable). For Kant ‘pure reason’ often signifies just pure
theoretical reason, which determines the realm of nature and of what is, but
Kant also believes there is pure practical reason (or Wille), which determines
a priori and independently of sensibility the realm of freedom and of what
ought to be. Practical reason in general is defined as that which determines
rules for the faculty of desire and will, as opposed to the faculties of
cognition and of feeling. On Kant’s mature view, however, the practical realm
is necessarily understood in relation to moral considerations, and these in
turn in terms of laws taken to have an unconditional imperative force whose
validity requires presuming that they are addressed to a being with absolute
freedom, the faculty to choose (Willkür) to will or not to will to act for
their sake. Kant also argues that no evidence of human freedom is forthcoming
from empirical knowledge of the self as part of spatiotemporal nature, and that
the belief in our freedom, and thus the moral laws that presuppose it, would
have to be given up if we thought that our reality is determined by the laws of
spatiotemporal appearances alone. Hence, to maintain the crucial practical
component of his philosophy it was necessary for Kant first to employ his
theoretical philosophy to show that it is at least possible that the
spatiotemporal realm does not exhaust reality, so that there can be a
non-empirical and free side to the self. Therefore Kant’s first Critique is a
theoretical foundation for his entire system, which is devoted to establishing
not just (i) what the most general necessary principles for the spatio-temporal
domain are – a project that has been called his “metaphysics of experience” –
but also (ii) that this domain cannot without contradiction define ultimate
reality (hence his transcendental idealism). The first of these claims involves
Kant’s primary use of the term ‘transcendental’, namely in the context of what
he calls a transcendental deduction, which is an argument or “exposition” that
establishes a necessary role for an a priori principle in our experience. As
Kant explains, while mathematical principles are a priori and are necessary for
experience, the mathematical proof of these principles is not itself
transcendental; what is transcendental is rather the philosophical argument
that these principles necessarily apply in experience. While in this way some
transcendental arguments may presume propositions from an established science
(e.g., geometry), others can begin with more modest assumptions – typically the
proposition that there is experience or empirical knowledge at all – and then
move on from there to uncover a priori principles that appear required for
specific features of that knowledge. Kant begins by connecting metaphysics with
the problem of synthetic a priori judgment. As necessary, metaphysical claims
must have an a priori status, for we cannot determine that they are necessary
by mere a posteriori means. As objective rather than merely formal,
metaphysical judgments (unlike those of logic) are also said to be synthetic.
This synthetic a priori character is claimed by Kant to be mysterious and yet
shared by a large number of propositions that were undisputed in his time. The
mystery is how a proposition can be known as necessary and yet be objective or
“ampliative” or not merely “analytic.” For Kant an analytic proposition is one
whose predicate is “contained in the subject.” He does not mean this
“containment” relation to be understood psychologically, for he stresses that
we can be psychologically and even epistemically bound to affirm non-analytic
propositions. The containment is rather determined simply by what is contained
in the concepts of the subject term and the predicate term. However, Kant also
denies that we have ready real definitions for empirical or a priori concepts,
so it is unclear how one determines what is really contained in a subject or
predicate term. He seems to rely on intuitive procedures for saying when it is
that one necessarily connects a subject and predicate without relying on a hidden
conceptual relation. Thus he proposes that mathematical constructions, and not
mere conceptual elucidations, are what warrant necessary judgments about
triangles. In calling such judgments ampliative, Kant does not mean that they
merely add to what we may have explicitly seen or implicitly known about the
subject, for he also grants that complex analytic judgments may be quite
informative, and thus “new” in a psychological or epistemic sense. While Kant
stresses that non-analytic or synthetic judgments rest on “intuition”
(Anschauung), this is not part of their definition. If a proposition could be
known through its concepts alone, it must be analytic, but if it is not
knowable in this way it follows only that we need something other than
concepts. Kant presumed that this something must be intuition, but others have
suggested other possibilities, such as postulation. Intuition is a technical
notion of Kant, meant for those representations that have an immediate relation
to their object. Human intuitions are also all sensible (or sensuous) or
passive, and have a singular rather than general object, but these are less
basic features of intuition, since Kant stresses the possibility of (nonhuman)
non-sensible or “intellectual” intuition, and he implies that singularity of
reference can be achieved by non-intuitive means (e.g., in the definition of
God). The immediacy of intuition is crucial because it is what sets them off
from concepts, which are essentially representations of representations, i.e.,
rules expressing what is common to a set of representations. Kant claims that
mathematics, and metaphysical expositions of our notions of space and time, can
reveal several evident synthetic a priori propositions, e.g., that there is one
infinite space. In asking what could underlie the belief that propositions like
this are certain, Kant came to his Copernican revolution. This consists in
considering not how our representations may necessarily conform to objects as
such, but rather how objects may necessarily conform to our representations. On
a “pre-Copernican” view, objects are considered just by themselves, i.e., as
“things-in-themselves” (Dinge an sich) totally apart from any intrinsic
cognitive relation to our representations, and thus it is mysterious how we could
ever determine them a priori. If we begin, however, with our own faculties of
representation we might find something in them that determines how objects must
be – at least when considered just as phenomena (singular: phenomenon), i.e.,
as objects of experience rather than as noumena (singular: noumenon), i.e.,
things-inthemselves specified negatively as unknown and beyond our experience,
or positively as knowable in some absolute non-sensible way – which Kant
insists is theoretically impossible for sensible beings like us. For example,
Kant claims that when we consider our faculty for receiving impressions, or
sensibility, we can find not only contingent contents but also two necessary
forms or “pure forms of intuition”: space, which structures all outer representations
given us, and time, which structures all inner representations. These forms can
explain how the synthetic a priori propositions of mathematics will apply with
certainty to all the objects of our experience. That is, if we suppose that in
intuiting these propositions we are gaining a priori insight into the forms of
our representation that must govern all that can come to our sensible
awareness, it becomes understandable that all objects in our experience will
have to conform with these propositions. Kant presented his transcendental
idealism as preferable to all the alternative explanations that he knew for the
possibility of mathematical knowledge and the metaphysical status of space and
time. Unlike empiricism, it allowed necessary claims in this domain; unlike
rationalism, it freed the development of this knowledge from the procedures of
mere conceptual analysis; and unlike the Newtonians it did all this without
giving space and time a mysterious status as an absolute thing or predicate of
God. With proper qualifications, Kant’s doctrine of the transcendental ideality
of space and time can be understood as a radicalization of the modern idea of
primary and secondary qualities. Just as others had contended that sensible
color and sound qualities, e.g., can be intersubjectively valid and even
objectively based while existing only as relative to our sensibility and not as
ascribable to objects in themselves, so Kant proposed that the same should be
said of spatiotemporal predicates. Kant’s doctrine, however, is distinctive in
that it is not an empirical hypothesis that leaves accessible to us other
theoretical and non-ideal predicates for explaining particular experiences. It
is rather a metaphysical thesis that enriches empirical explanations with an a
priori framework, but begs off any explanation for that framework itself other
than the statement that it lies in the “constitution” of human sensibility as
such. This “Copernican” hypothesis is not a clear proof that spatiotemporal
features could not apply to objects apart from our forms of intuition, but more
support for this stronger claim is given in Kant’s discussion of the
“antinomies” of rational cosmology. An antinomy is a conflict between two a
priori arguments arising from reason when, in its distinctive work as a higher
logical faculty connecting strings of judgments, it posits a real unconditioned
item at the origin of various hypothetical syllogisms. There are antinomies of
quantity, quality, relation, and modality, and they each proceed by pairs of
dogmatic arguments which suppose that since one kind of unconditioned item
cannot be found, e.g., an absolutely first event, another kind must be posited,
e.g., a complete infinite series of past events. For most of the other
antinomies, Kant indicates that contradiction can be avoided by allowing
endless series in experience (e.g., of chains of causality, of series of
dependent beings), series that are compatible with – but apparently do not
require – unconditioned items (uncaused causes, necessary beings) outside
experience. For the antinomy of quantity, however, he argues that the only
solution is to drop the common dogmatic assumption that the set of
spatiotemporal objects constitutes a determinate whole, either absolutely
finite or infinite. He takes this to show that spatiotemporality must be
transcendentally ideal, only an indeterminate feature of our experience and not
a characteristic of things-in-themselves. Even when structured by the pure
forms of space and time, sensible representations do not yield knowledge until
they are grasped in concepts and these concepts are combined in a judgment.
Otherwise, we are left with mere impressions, scattered in an unintelligible
“multiplicity” or manifold; in Kant’s words, “thoughts without content are
empty, intuitions without concepts are blind.” Judgment requires both concepts
and intuitions; it is not just any relation of concepts, but a bringing
together of them in a particular way, an “objective” unity, so that one concept
is predicated of another – e.g., “all bodies are divisible” – and the latter
“applies to certain appearances that present themselves to us,” i.e., are
intuited. Because any judgment involves a unity of thought that can be prefixed
by the phrase ‘I think’, Kant speaks of all representations, to the extent that
they can be judged by us, as subject to a necessary unity of apperception. This
term originally signified self-consciousness in contrast to direct
consciousness or perception, but Kant uses it primarily to contrast with ‘inner
sense’, the precognitive manifold of temporal representations as they are
merely given in the mind. Kant also contrasts the empirical ego, i.e., the self
as it is known contingently in experience, with the transcendental ego, i.e.,
the self thought of as the subject of structures of intuiting and thinking that
are necessary throughout experience. The fundamental need for concepts and
judgments suggests that our “constitution” may require not just intuitive but
also conceptual forms, i.e., “pure concepts of the understanding,” or
“categories.” The proof that our experience does require such forms comes in
the “deduction of the objective validity of the pure concepts of the
understanding,” also called the transcendental deduction of the categories, or
just the deduction. This most notorious of all Kantian arguments appears to be
in one way harder and in one way easier than the transcendental argument for
pure intuitions. Those intuitions were held to be necessary for our experience
because as structures of our sensibility nothing could even be imagined to be
given to us without them. Yet, as Kant notes, it might seem that once
representations are given in this way we can still imagine that they need not
then be combined in terms of such pure concepts as causality. On the other
hand, Kant proposed that a list of putative categories could be derived from a
list of the necessary forms of the logical table of judgments, and since these
forms would be required for any finite understanding, whatever its mode of sensibility
is like, it can seem that the validity of pure concepts is even more
inescapable than that of pure intuitions. That there is nonetheless a special
difficulty in the transcendental argument for the categories becomes evident as
soon as one considers the specifics of Kant’s list. The logical table of
judgments is an a priori collection of all possible judgment forms organized
under four headings, with three subforms each: quantity (universal, particular,
singular), quality (affirmative, negative, infinite), relation (categorical,
hypothetical, disjunctive), and modality (problematic, assertoric, apodictic).
This list does not map exactly onto any one of the logic textbooks of Kant’s
day, but it has many similarities with them; thus problematic judgments are
simply those that express logical possibility, and apodictic ones are those
that express logical necessity. The table serves Kant as a clue to the
“metaphysical deduction” of the categories, which claims to show that there is
an origin for these concepts that is genuinely a priori, and, on the premise
that the table is proper, that the derived concepts can be claimed to be
fundamental and complete. But by itself the list does not show exactly what
categories follow from, i.e., are necessarily used with, the various forms of
judgment, let alone what their specific meaning is for our mode of experience.
Above all, even when it is argued that each experience and every judgment
requires at least one of the four general forms, and that the use of any form
of judgment does involve a matching pure concept (listed in the table of
categories: reality, negation, limitation; unity, plurality, totality;
inherence and subsistence, causality and dependence, community; possibility –
impossibility, existence –non-existence, and necessity–contingency) applying to
the objects judged about, this does not show that the complex relational forms
and their corresponding categories of causality and community are necessary
unless it is shown that these specific forms of judgment are each necessary for
our experience. Precisely because this is initially not evident, it can appear,
as Kant himself noted, that the validity of controversial categories such as
causality cannot be established as easily as that of the forms of intuition.
Moreover, Kant does not even try to prove the objectivity of the traditional
modal categories but treats the principles that use them as mere definitions
relative to experience. Thus a problematic judgment, i.e., one in which
“affirmation or negation is taken as merely possible,” is used when something
is said to be possible in the sense that it “agrees with the formal conditions
of experience, i.e., with the conditions of intuition and of concepts.” A clue
for rescuing the relational categories is given near the end of the
Transcendental Deduction (B version), where Kant notes that the a priori
all-inclusiveness and unity of space and time that is claimed in the treatment
of sensibility must, like all cognitive unity, ultimately have a foundation in
judgment. Kant expands on this point by devoting a key section called the
analogies of experience to arguing that the possibility of our judging objects
to be determined in an objective position in the unity of time (and,
indirectly, space) requires three a priori principles (each called an
“Analogy”) that employ precisely the relational categories that seemed
especially questionable. Since these categories are established as needed just
for the determination of time and space, which themselves have already been
argued to be transcendentally ideal, Kant can conclude that for us even a
priori claims using pure concepts of the understanding provide what are only
transcendentally ideal claims. Thus we cannot make determinate theoretical
claims about categories such as substance, cause, and community in an absolute
sense that goes beyond our experience, but we can establish principles for
their spatiotemporal specifications, called schemata, namely, the three
Analogies: “in all change of appearance substance is permanent,” “all
alterations take place in conformity with the law of the connection of cause
and effect,” and “all substances, insofar as they can be perceived to coexist
in space, are in thoroughgoing reciprocity.” Kant initially calls these
regulative principles of experience, since they are required for organizing all
objects of our empirical knowledge within a unity, and, unlike the constitutive
principles for the categories of quantity and quality (namely: “all intuitions
[for us] are extensive magnitudes,” and “in all appearances the real that is an
object of sensation has intensive magnitude, that is, a degree”), they do not
characterize any individual item by itself but rather only by its real relation
to other objects of experience. Nonetheless, in comparison to mere heuristic or
methodological principles (e.g., seek simple or teleological explanations),
these Analogies are held by Kant to be objectively necessary for experience,
and for this reason can also be called constitutive in a broader sense. The
remainder of the Critique exposes the “original” or “transcendental” ideas of
pure reason that pretend to be constitutive or theoretically warranted but
involve unconditional components that wholly transcend the realm of experience.
These include not just the antinomic cosmological ideas noted above (of these
Kant stresses the idea of transcendental freedom, i.e., of uncaused causing),
but also the rational psychological ideas of the soul as an immortal substance
and the rational theological idea of God as a necessary and perfect being. Just
as the pure concepts of the understanding have an origin in the necessary forms
of judgments, these ideas are said to originate in the various syllogistic
forms of reason: the idea of a soul-substance is the correlate of an
unconditioned first term of a categorical syllogism (i.e., a subject that can
never be the predicate of something else), and the idea of God is the correlate
of the complete sum of possible predicates that underlies the unconditioned
first term of the disjunctive syllogism used to give a complete determination
of a thing’s properties. Despite the a priori origin of these notions, Kant
claims we cannot theoretically establish their validity, even though they do
have regulative value in organizing our notion of a human or divine spiritual
substance. Thus, even if, as Kant argues, traditional proofs of immortality,
and the teleological, cosmological, and ontological arguments for God’s
existence, are invalid, the notions they involve can be affirmed as long as
there is, as he believes, a sufficient non-theoretical, i.e., moral argument
for them. When interpreted on the basis of such an argument, they are
transformed into ideas of practical reason, ideas that, like perfect virtue,
may not be verified or realized in sensible experience, but have a rational
warrant in pure practical considerations. Although Kant’s pure practical
philosophy culminates in religious hope, it is primarily a doctrine of
obligation. Moral value is determined ultimately by the nature of the intention
of the agent, which in turn is determined by the nature of what Kant calls the
general maxim or subjective principle underlying a person’s action. One follows
a hypothetical imperative when one’s maxim does not presume an unconditional end,
a goal (like the fulfillment of duty) that one should have irrespective of all
sensible desires, but rather a “material end” dependent on contingent
inclinations (e.g., the directive “get this food,” in order to feel happy). In
contrast, a categorical imperative is a directive saying what ought to be done
from the perspective of pure reason alone; it is categorical because what this
perspective commands is not contingent on sensible circumstances and it always
carries overriding value. The general formula of the categorical imperative is
to act only according to those maxims that can be consistently willed as a
universal law – something said to be impossible for maxims aimed merely at
material ends. In accepting this imperative, we are doubly self-determined, for
we are not only determining our action freely, as Kant believes humans do in
all exercises of the faculty of choice; we are also accepting a principle whose
content is determined by that which is absolutely essential to us as agents,
namely our pure practical reason. We thus are following our own law and so have
autonomy when we accept the categorical imperative; otherwise we fall into
heteronomy, or the (free) acceptance of principles whose content is determined
independently of the essential nature of our own ultimate being, which is
rational. Given the metaphysics of his transcendental idealism, Kant can say
that the categorical imperative reveals a supersensible power of freedom in us
such that we must regard ourselves as part of an intelligible world, i.e., a
domain determined ultimately not by natural laws but rather by laws of reason.
As such a rational being, an agent is an end in itself, i.e., something whose
value is not dependent on external material ends, which are contingent and
valued only as means to the end of happiness – which is itself only a
conditional value (since the satisfaction of an evil will would be improper).
Kant regards accepting the categorical imperative as tantamount to respecting
rational nature as an end in itself, and to willing as if we were legislating a
kingdom of ends. This is to will that the world become a “systematic Kant,
Immanuel Kant, Immanuel 465 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 465 union of
different rational beings through common laws,” i.e., laws that respect and
fulfill the freedom of all rational beings. Although there is only one
fundamental principle of morality, there are still different types of specific
duties. One basic distinction is between strict duty and imperfect duty. Duties
of justice, of respecting in action the rights of others, or the duty not to
violate the dignity of persons as rational agents, are strict because they
allow no exception for one’s inclination. A perfect duty is one that requires a
specific action (e.g. keeping a promise), whereas an imperfect duty, such as
the duty to perfect oneself or to help others, cannot be completely discharged
or demanded by right by someone else, and so one has considerable latitude in
deciding when and how it is to be respected. A meritorious duty involves going
beyond what is strictly demanded and thereby generating an obligation in
others, as when one is extraordinarily helpful to others and “merits” their
gratitude.
kennyism: “His surname means ‘white,’ as in penguin, kennedy.” –
Grice. Cited by Grice in his British Academy lecture – Grice was pleased that
Kenny translated Vitters’s “Philosophical Grammar” – “He turned it into more of
a philosophical thing than I would have thought one could!”
kepler: philosopher, born in Weil der
Stadt, near Stuttgart. He studied astronomy with Michael Maestlin at the
University of Tübingen, and then began the regular course of theological
studies that prepared him to become a Lutheran pastor. Shortly before
completing these studies he accepted the post of mathematician at Graz.
“Mathematics” was still construed as including astronomy and astrology. There
he published the Mysterium cosmographicum (1596), the first mjaor astronomical
work to utilize the Copernican system since Copernicus’s own De revolutionibus
half a century before. The Copernican shift of the sun to the center allowed
Kepler to propose an explanation for the spacing of the planets (the Creator
inscribed the successive planetary orbits in the five regular polyhedra) and
for their motions (a sun-centered driving force diminishing with disKao Tzu
Kepler, Johannes 466 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 466 tance from the
sun). In this way, he could claim to have overcome the traditional prohibition
against the mathematical astronomer’s claiming reality for the motion he
postulates. Ability to explain had always been the mark of the philosopher.
Kepler, a staunch Lutheran, was forced to leave Catholic Graz as bitter
religious and political disputes engulfed much of northern Europe. He took refuge
in the imperial capital, Prague, where Tycho Brahe, the greatest observational
astronomer of the day, had established an observatory. Tycho asked Kepler to
compose a defense of Tycho’s astronomy against a critic, Nicolaus Ursus, who
had charged that it was “mere hypothesis.” The resulting Apologia (1600)
remained unpublished; it contains a perceptive analysis of the nature of
astronomical hypothesis. Merely saving the phenomena, Kepler argues, is in
general not sufficient to separate two mathematical systems like those of
Ptolemy and Copernicus. Other more properly explanatory “physical” criteria
will be needed. Kepler was allowed to begin work on the orbit of Mars, using
the mass of data Tycho had accumulated. But shortly afterward, Tycho died
suddenly (1601). Kepler succeeded to Tycho’s post as Imperial Mathematician;
more important, he was entrusted with Tycho’s precious data. Years of labor led
to the publication of the Astronomia nova (1609), which announced the discovery
of the elliptical orbit of Mars. One distinctive feature of Kepler’s long quest
for the true shape of the orbit was his emphasis on finding a possible physical
evaluation for any planetary motion he postulated before concluding that it was
the true motion. Making the sun’s force magnetic allowed him to suppose that
its effect on the earth would vary as the earth’s magnetic axis altered its
orientation to the sun, thus perhaps explaining the varying distances and
speeds of the earth in its elliptical orbit. The full title of his book makes
his ambition clear: A New Astronomy Based on Causes, or A Physics of the Sky.
Trouble in Prague once more forced Kepler to move. He eventually found a place
in Linz (1612), where he continued his exploration of cosmic harmonies, drawing
on theology and philosophy as well as on music and mathematics. The “Harmonia
mundi” was his favorite among his books: “It can wait a century for a reader,
as God himself has waited six thousand years for a witness.” The discovery of
what later became known as his third law, relating the periodic times of any
two planets as the ratio of the 3 /2 power of their mean distances, served to
confirm his long-standing conviction that the universe is fashioned according
to ideal harmonic relationships. In the Epitome astronomiae Copernicanae
(1612), he continued his search for causes “either natural or archetypal,” not
only for the planetary motions, but for such details as the size of the sun and
the densities of the planets. He was more convinced than ever that a physics of
the heavens had to rest upon its ability to explain (and not just to predict)
the peculiarities of the planetary and lunar motions. What prevented him from
moving even further than he did toward a new physics was that he had not
grasped what later came to be called the principle of inertia. Thus he was
compelled to postulate not only an attractive force between planet and sun but
also a second force to urge the planet onward. It was Newton who showed that
the second force is unnecessary, and who finally constructed the “physics of
the sky” that had been Kepler’s ambition. But he could not have done it without
Kepler’s notion of a quantifiable force operating between planet and sun, an
unorthodox notion shaped in the first place by an imagination steeped in Neoplatonic
metaphysics and the theology of the Holy Spirit.
Keynes, j. Neville – “the father of the
better known Keynes, but the more interesting of the pair.” – Grice. Keynes, j.
k., philosopher, author of “The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money”
and “A Treatise on Probability,” cited by Grice for the importance of the
ontological status of properties. Keynes was also active in English Oxbridge
philosophical life, being well acquainted with such philosophers as G. E. Moore
and F. P. Ramsey. In the philosophy of probability, Keynes pioneers the
treatment of the proposition as the bearers of a probability assignment. Unlike
classical subjectivists, Keynes treats probability as objective evidential
relations among at least two proposition in ‘if’ connection. These relations
are to be directly epistemically accessible to an intuitive ‘faculty.’ An
idiosyncratic feature of Keynes’s system is that different probability
assignments cannot always be compared (ordered as equal, less than, or greater
than one another). Keynesianism permanently affected philosophy. Keynes’s philosophy
has a number of important dimensions. While Keynes’s theorizing is in the capitalistic
tradition, he rejects Sctos Smith’s notion of an invisible hand that would
optimize the performance of an economy without any intentional direction by an
individual or by the government. This involved rejection of the economic policy
of “laissez-faire,” according to which government intervention in the economy’s
operation is useless, or worse. Keynes argues that the natural force could
deflect an economy from a course of optimal growth and keep it permanently out
of equilibrium. Keynes proposes a number of mechanisms for adjusting its
performance. Keynes advocates programs of government taxation and spending, not
primarily as a means of providing public goods, but as a means of increasing
prosperity. The philosopher is thereby provided with another means for
justifying the existence of a strong government. One of the important ways that
Keynes’s philosophy still directs much theorizing is its deep division between
microeconomics and macroeconomics. Keynes argues, in effect, that micro-oeconomic
analysis with its emphasis on ideal individual rationality and perfect intersubjective
game-theoretical two-player competition is inadequate as a tool for
understanding a macrophenomenon such as interest, and money. Keynes tries to
show how human psychological foibles and market frictions require a
qualitatively different kind of analysis at the macro level. Much theorizing is
concerned with understanding the connections between micro- and macrophenomena
and micro- and macroeconomics in an attempt to dissolve or blur the division.
This issue is a philosophically important instance of a potential theoretical reduction.
Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Keynes’s ontology in the “Treatise on Probability,” H. P.
Grice, “Credibility and Probability.”
kierkegaard: “Literally, churchyard, fancy
that!” – Grice. Philosopher born to a well-to-do family, he consumed his
inheritance while writing a large corpus of essays in a remarkably short time.
His life was marked by an intense relationship with a devout but melancholy
father, from whom he inherited his own bent to melancholy, with which he
constantly struggled. A decisive event was his broken engagement from Regina
Olsen, which precipitated the beginning of his authorship; his first essays are
partly an attempt to explain, in a covert and symbolic way, the reasons why he
felt he could not marry. Later Kierkegaard was involved in a controversy in
which he was mercilessly attacked by a popular satirical periodical; this
experience deepened his understanding of the significance of suffering and the
necessity for an authentic individual to stand alone if necessary against “the
crowd.” This caused him to abandon his plans to take a pastorate, a post for
which his education had prepared him. At the end of his life, he waged a
lonely, public campaign in the popular press and in a magazine he founded
himself, against the Danish state church. He collapsed on the street with the
final issue of this magazine, The Instant, ready for the printer, and was
carried to a hospital. He died a few weeks later, affirming a strong Christian
faith, but refusing to take communion from the hands of a priest of the
official church. Though some writers have questioned whether Kierkegaard’s
writings admit of a unified interpretation, Kierkegaard himself sees his oeuvre
as serving Christianity; he saw himself as a “missionary” whose task was to
“reintroduce Christianity into Christendom.” However, much of this literature
does not address Christianity directly, but rather concerns itself with an
analysis of human existence. Kierkegaard see this as necessary, because
Christianity is first and foremost a way of existing. He saw much of the
confusion about Christian faith as rooted in confusion about the nature of
existence. Hence to clear up the former, the latter must be carefully analyzed.
The great misfortune of “Christendom” and “the present age” is that people “have
forgotten what it means ‘to exist,’” and Kierkegaard sees himself as a modern
Socrates sent to “remind” others of what they know but have forgotten. It is
not surprising that the analyses of human existence he provides have been of
great interest to many philosophers. Kierkegaard frequently uses the verb ‘to
exist’ (at existere) idiosyncratically, to refer to human existence. In this
sense God is said NOT to exist, even though God has eternal reality.
Kierkegaard describes human existence as an unfinished process, in which “the
individual” (a key concept in his thought) must take responsibility for
achieving an identity as a self through a free choice. Such a choice is
described as a leap, to highlight Kierkegaard’s view that intellectual
reflection alone can never motivate action. A decision to end the process of
reflection is necessary and such a decision must be generated by a passion. The
passions that shape a person’s self are referred to by Kierkegaard as the
individual’s “inwardness” or “subjectivity.” The most significant passion, love
or faith, does not merely happen; they must be cultivated and formed. The
process by which the individual becomes a self is described by Kierkegaard as
ideally moving through three stages, termed the “stages on life’s way.” Since
human development occurs by freedom and not automatically, however, the
individual can become fixated in any of these stages. Thus the stages also
confront each other as rival views of life, or “spheres of existence.” The
three stages or spheres are the “aesthetic,” (or sensual), the ethical, and the
religious. A distinctive feature of Kierkegaard’s philosophy is that these
three lifeviews are represented by pseudonymous “characters” who actually
“author” some of the oeuvre; this leads to interpretive difficulties, since it
is not always clear what to attribute to Kierkegaard himself and what to the
pseudonymous character. Fortunately, he also wrote many devotional and
religious works under his own name, where this problem does not arise. The “aesthetic”
life is described by Kierkegaard as lived for and in “the moment.” It is a life
governed by “immediacy,” or the satisfaction of one’s immediate desire, though
it is capable of a kind of development in which one learns to enjoy life
reflectively. What the aesthetic person lacks is a commitment (except to
sensation itself) which is the key to the ethical life, a life that attempts to
achieve a unified self through commitment to ideals with enduring validity,
rather than simply sensual appeal. The religious life emerges from the ethical
life when the individual realizes both the transcendent character of the true
ideals and also how far short of realizing those ideals the person is. In
Concluding Unscientific Postscript two forms of the religious life are
distinguished: a “natural” religiosity (religiousness “A”) in which the person
attempts to relate to the divine and resolve the problem of guilt, relying
solely on one’s natural “immanent” idea of the divine; and Christianity
(religiousness “B”), in which God becomes incarnate as a human being in order
to establish a relation with humans. Christianity can be accepted only through
the “leap of faith.” It is a religion not of “immanence” but of
“transcendence,” since it is based on a revelation. This revelation cannot be
rationally demonstrated, since the incarnation is a paradox that transcends
human reason. Reason can, however, when the passion of faith is present, come
to understand the appropriateness of recognizing its own limits and accepting
the paradoxical incarnation of God in the form of Jesus Christ. The true
Christian is not merely an admirer of Jesus, but one who believes by becoming a
follower. The irreducibility of the religious life to the ethical life is
illustrated for Kierkegaard in the biblical story of Abraham’s willingness to
sacrifice his son Isaac to obey the command of God. In Fear and Trembling
Kierkegaard (through his pseudonym “de Silentio”) analyzes this act of
Abraham’s as involving a “teleological suspension of the ethical.” Abraham’s
act cannot be understood merely in ethical terms as a conflict of duties in
which one rationally comprehensible duty is superseded by a higher one. Rather,
Abraham seems to be willing to “suspend” the ethical as a whole in favor of a
higher religious duty. Thus, if one admires Abraham as “the father of faith,”
one admires a quality that cannot be reduced to simply moral virtue. Some (like
J. L. Mackie) have read this as a claim that religious faith may require
immoral behavior; others (like P. F. Strawson) argue that what is relativized
by the teleological suspension of the ethical is not an eternally valid set of
moral requirements, but rather ethical obligations as these are embedded in
human social institutions. Thus, in arguing that “the ethical” is not the
highest element in existence, Kierkegaard leaves open the possibility that our
social institutions, and the ethical ideals that they embody, do not deserve
our absolute and unqualified allegiance, an idea with important political
implications. In accord with his claim that existence cannot be reduced to
intellectual thought, Kierkegaard devotes much attention to emotions and
passions. Anxiety is particularly important, since it reflects human freedom.
Anxiety involves a “sympathetic antipathy and an antipathetic sympathy”; it is
the psychological state that precedes the basic human fall into sin, but it
does not explain this “leap,” since no final explanation of a free choice can
be given. Such negative emotions as despair and guilt are also important for
Kierkegaard; they reveal the emptiness of the aesthetic and the ultimately
unsatisfactory character of the ethical, driving individuals on toward the
religious life. Irony and humor are also seen as important “boundary zones” for
the stages of existence. The person who has discovered his or her own “eternal
validity” can look ironically at the relative values that capture most people,
who live their lives aesthetically. Similarly, the “existential humorist” who
has seen the incongruities that necessarily pervade our ethical human projects
is on the border of the religious life. Kierkegaard also analyzes the passions
of faith Kierkegaard, Søren Aabye Kierkegaard, Søren Aabye 469 4065h-l.qxd
08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 469 and love. Faith is ultimately understood as a
“willing to be oneself” that is made possible by a transparent, trusting
relationship to the “power that created the self.” Kierkegaard distinguishes
various forms of love, stressing that Christian love must be understood as
neighbor love, a love that is combined and is not rooted in any natural
relationship to the self, such as friendship or kinship, but ultimately is
grounded in the fact that all humans share a relationship to their creator.
Kierkegaard is well known for his critique of Hegel’s absolute idealism.
Hegel’s claim to have written “the system” is ridiculed for its pretensions of
finality. From the Dane’s perspective, though reality may be a system for God,
it cannot be so for any existing thinker, since both reality and the thinker
are incomplete and system implies completeness. Hegelians are also criticized
for pretending to have found a presuppositionless or absolute starting point;
for Kierkegaard, philosophy begins not with doubt but with wonder. Reflection
is potentially infinite; the doubt that leads to skepticism cannot be ended by
thought alone but only by a resolution of the will. Kierkegaard also defends
traditional Aristotelian logic and the principle of non-contradiction against
the Hegelian introduction of “movement” into logic. Kierkegaard is particularly
disturbed by the Hegelian tendency to see God as immanent in society; he
thought it important to understand God as “wholly other,” the “absolutely
different” who can never be exhaustively embodied in human achievement or
institutions. To stand before God one must stand as an individual, in “fear and
trembling,” conscious that this may require a break with the given social
order. Kierkegaard is often characterized as the father of existentialism.
There are reasons for this; he does indeed philosophize existentially, and he
undoubtedly exercised a deep influence on many twentieth-century
existentialists such as Sartre and Camus. But the characterization is
anachronistic, since existentialism as a movement is a twentieth-century
phenomenon, and the differences between Kierkegaard and those existentialists
are also profound. If existentialism is defined as the denial that there is
such a thing as a human essence or nature, it is unlikely that Kierkegaard is
an existentialist. More recently, the Dane has also been seen as a precursor of
postmodernism. His rejection of classical foundationalist epistemologies and
employment of elusive literary techniques such as his pseudonyms again make
such associations somewhat plausible. However, despite his rejection of the
system and criticism of human claims to finality and certitude, Kierkegaard
does not appear to espouse any form of relativism or have much sympathy for
“anti-realism.” He has the kind of passion for clarity and delight in making
sharp distinctions that are usually associated with contemporary “analytic”
philosophy. In the end he must be seen as his own person, a unique Christian
presence with sensibilities that are in many ways Greek and premodern rather
than postmodern. He has been joyfully embraced and fervently criticized by
thinkers of all stripes. He remains “the individual” he wrote about, and to
whom he dedicated many of his works.
kilvington: Oriel, Oxford. Yorks.
Grice, “The English Place Name Society told me.” “I tried to teach Sophismata
at Oxford, but my tutees complained that Chillington’s Latin chilled them!” –
Grice. English philosopher. He was a scholar associated with the household of
Richard de Bury and an early member of “The Oxford Calculators,” as Grice calls
them, important in the early development of physics. Kilvington’s “Sophismata” is
the only work of his studied extensively to date. It is an investigation of
puzzles regarding ceasing, doubting, the liar, change, velocity and
acceleration, motive power, beginning and ceasing, the continuum, infinity,
knowing and doubting, and the liar and related paradoxes. Kilvington’s
“Sophismata” is peculiar insofar as all these are treated in a conceptual way,
in contrast to the more artificial “calculations” used by Bradwardine,
Heytesbury, and other Oxford Calculators to handle this or that problem. Kilvington
also wrote a commentary on Peter Lombard’s Sentences and questions on
Aristotle’s On Generation and Corruption, Physics, and Nicomachean Ethics. Refs.:
H. P. Grice: “Chillington chills: “Sophismata” – on beginning and ceasing and
knowing and doubting – implicatura.”
kilwardby of rufina: English philosopher, he taught
at Paris, joins the Dominicans and teaches at Oxford. He becomes archbishop of
Canterbury and condemns thirty propositions, among them Aquinas’s position that
there is a single substantial form in a human being. Kilwardby resigns his
archbishopric and is appointed to the bishopric of Santa Rufina, Italy, where
he dies. Kilwardby writes extensively and had considerable medieval influence,
especially in philosophy of language; but it is now unusually difficult to
determine which works are authentically his. “De Ortu Scientiarum advances a
sophisticated account of how a name is imposed and a detailed account of the
nature and role of conceptual analysis. In metaphysics Kilwardby of Rufina
insisted that things are individual and that universality arises from operations
of the soul. He writes extensively on happiness and was concerned to show that
some happiness is possible in this life. In psychology he argued that freedom
of decision is a disposition arising from the cooperation of the intellect and
the will.
cognitum: KK-thesis: the
thesis that knowing entails knowing that one knows, symbolized in propositional
epistemic logic as Kp > KKp, where ‘K’ stands for knowing. According to the
KK-thesis, proposed by Grice in “Method in philosophical psychology: from the
banal to the bizarre,” the (propositional) logic of knowledge resembles the
modal system S4. The KK-thesis was introduced into epistemological discussion
by Hintikka in Knowledge and Belief. He calls the KKthesis a “virtual
implication,” a conditional whose negation is “indefensible.” A tacit or an
explicit acceptance of the thesis has been part of many philosophers’ views
about knowledge since Plato and Aristotle. If the thesis is formalized as Kap P
KaKap, where ‘Ka’ is read as ‘a knows that’, it holds only if the person a
knows that he is referred to by ‘a’; this qualification is automatically
satisfied for the first-person case. The validity of the thesis seems sensitive
to variations in the sense of ‘know’; it has sometimes been thought to
characterize a strong concept of knowledge, e.g., knowledge based on
(factually) conclusive reasons, or active as opposed to implicit knowledge. If
knowledge is regarded as true belief based on conclusive evidence, the KKthesis
entails that a person knows that p only if his evidence for p is also
sufficient to justify the claim that he knows that p; the epistemic claim
should not require additional evidence. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Method in
philosophical psychology: from the banal to the bizarre,” in “The Conception of
Value.”
Shaftesbury: “One of my favourite rationalist
philosophers” – Grice.
Kleist: philosopher whose oeuvre is based
on the antinomy of reason and sentiment, one as impotent as the other, and
reflects the Aufklärung crisis at the turn of the century. He resigned from the
Prussian army. Following a reading of Kant, he lost faith in a “life’s plan” as
inspired by Leibniz’s, Wolff’s, and Shaftesbury’s rationalism. Kleist looks for
salvation in Rousseau but concluded that sentiment revealed itself just as
untrustworthy as reason as soon as man left the state of original grace (“or
grice, his spelling is doubtful” – Grice) and realized himself to be neither a
puppet nor a god (see Essay on the Puppet Theater, 1810). The Schroffenstein
Family repeats the Shakespearian theme of two young people who love each other
but belong to warring families. One already finds in it the major elements of
Kleist’s universe: the incapacity of the individual to master his fate, the
theme of the tragic error, and the importance of the juridical. In 1803, Kleist
returned to philosophy and literature and realized in Amphitryon (1806) the
impossibility of the individual knowing himself and the world and acting
deliberately in it. The divine order that is the norm of tragic art collapses,
and with it, the principle of identity. Kleistian characters, “modern” individuals,
illustrate this normative chaos. The Broken Jug (a comedy) shows Kleist’s
interest in law. In his two parallel plays, Penthesilea and The Young Catherine
of Heilbronn, Kleist presents an alternative: either “the marvelous order of
the world” and the theodicy that carries Catherine’s fate, or the sublime and
apocryphal mission of the Christlike individual who must redeem the corrupt
order. Before his suicide, Kleist looked toward the renaissance of the German
nation for a historical way out of this metaphysical conflict.
knowledge
by acquaintance:
knowledge of objects by means of direct awareness of them. The notion of
knowledge by acquaintance is primarily associated with Russell (The Problems of
Philosophy). Russell first distinguishes knowledge of truths from knowledge of
things. He then distinguishes two kinds of knowledge of things: knowledge by
acquaintance and knowledge by description. Ordinary speech suggests that we are
acquainted with the people and the physical objects in our immediate environments.
On Russell’s view, however, our contact with these things is indirect, being
mediated by our mental representations of them. He holds that the only things
we know by acquaintance are the content of our minds, abstract universals, and,
perhaps, ourselves. Russell says that knowledge by description is indirect
knowledge of objects, our knowledge being mediated by other objects and truths.
He suggests that we know external objects, such as tables and other people,
only by description (e.g., the cause of my present experience). Russell’s
discussion of this topic is quite puzzling. The considerations that lead him to
say that we lack acquaintance with external objects also lead him to say that,
strictly speaking, we lack knowledge of such things. This seems to amount to
the claim that what he has called “knowledge by description” is not, strictly
speaking, a kind of knowledge at all. Russell also holds that every proposition
that a person understands must be composed entirely of elements with which the
person is acquainted. This leads him to propose analyses of familiar
propositions in terms of mental objects with which we are acquainted.
de re/de
sensu:,
knowledge de re, with respect to some object, that it has a particular
property, or knowledge, of a group of objects, that they stand in some
relation. Knowledge de re is typically contrasted with knowledge de dicto,
which is knowledge of facts or propositions. If persons A and B know that a
winner has been declared in an election, but only B knows which candidate has
won, then both have de dicto knowledge that someone has won, but only B has de
re knowledge about some candidate that she is the winner. Person B can
knowingly attribute the property of being the winner to one of the candidates.
It is generally held that to have de re knowledge about an object one must at
least be in some sense familiar with or causally connected to the object. A
related concept is knowledge de se. This is self-knowledge, of the sort
expressed by ‘I am —— ’. Knowledge de se is not simply de re knowledge about
oneself. A person might see a group of people in a mirror and notice that one
of the people has a red spot on his nose. He then has de dicto knowledge that
someone in the group has a red spot on his nose. On most accounts, he also has
de re knowledge with respect to that individual that he has a spot. But if he
has failed to recognize that he himself is the one with the spot, then he lacks
de se knowledge. He doesn’t know (or believe) what he would express by saying
“I have a red spot.” So, according to this view, knowledge de se is not merely
knowledge de re about oneself.
köhler: philosophical
psychologist who, with Wertheimer and Koffka, founded Gestalt psychologie.
Köhler makestwo distinctive contributions to Gestalt doctrine, one empirical,
one theoretical. The empirical contribution was his study of animal thinking,
performed on Tenerife (The Mentality of Apes). The then dominant theory of
problem solving was E. L. Thorndike’s associationist trial-and-error learning theory,
maintaining that animals attack problems by trying out a series of behaviors,
one of which is gradually “stamped in” by success. Köhler argues that
trial-and-error behavior occurred only when, as in Thorndike’s experiments,
part of the problem situation was hidden. He arranged more open puzzles, such
as getting bananas hanging from a ceiling, requiring the ape to get a (visible)
box to stand on. His apes showed insight – suddenly arriving at the correct
solution. Although he demonstrated the existence of insight, its nature remains
elusive, and trial-and-error learning remains the focus of research. Köhler’s
theoretical contribution was the concept of isomorphism, Gestalt psychology’s
theory of psychological representation. He held an identity theory of mind and
body, and isomorphism claims that a topological mapping exists between the
behavioral field in which an organism is acting (cf. Lewin) and fields of
electrical currents in the brain (not the “mind”). Such currents have not been
discovered. Important works by Köhler include Gestalt Psychology, The Place of
Value in a World of Facts, Dynamics in Psychology, and Selected Papers (ed. M.
Henle).
Kotarbigski: philosopher, cofounder, with
Lukasiewicz and Lesniewski, of the Warsaw Centre of Logical Research. His broad
philosophical interests and humanistic concerns, probity, scholarship, and
clarity in argument, consequent persuasiveness, and steadfast championship of
human rights made him heir to their common mentor Kasimir Twardowski, father of
modern Polish philosophy. In philosophical, historical, and methodological
works like his influential Elements of Theory of Knowledge, Formal Logic, and
Scientific Methodology (1929; mistitled Gnosiology in English translation), he
popularized the more technical contributions of his colleagues, and carried on
Twardowski’s objectivist and “anti-irrationalist” critical tradition, insisting
on accuracy and clarity, holding that philosophy has no distinctive method
beyond the logical and analytical methods of the empirical and deductive
sciences. As a free-thinking liberal humanist socialist, resolved to be “a true
compass, not a weathervane,” he defended autonomous ethics against
authoritarianism, left or right. His lifelong concern with community and social
practice led him to develop praxiology as a theory of efficacious action.
Following Lesniewsi’s “refutation” of Twardowski’s Platonism, Kotarbigski
insisted on translating abstractions into more concrete terms. The principal
tenets of his “reist, radical realist, and imitationist” rejection of
Platonism, phenomenalism, and introspectionism are (1) pansomatism or
ontological reism as modernized monistic materialism: whatever is anything at
all (even a soul) is a body – i.e., a concrete individual object, resistant and
spatiotemporally extended, enduring at least a while; (2) consequent radical
realism: no object is a “property,” “relation,” “event,” “fact,” or “abstract
entity” of any other kind, nor “sense-datum,” “phenomenon,” or essentially
“private mental act” or “fact” accessible only to “introspection”; (3)
concretism or semantic reism and imitationism as a concomitant “nominalist”
program – thus, abstract terms that, hypostatized, might appear to name
“abstract entities” are pseudo-names or onomatoids to be eliminated by
philosophical analysis and elucidatory paraphrase. Hypostatizations that might
appear to imply existence of such Platonic universals are translatable into
equivalent generalizations characterizing only bodies. Psychological
propositions are likewise reducible, ultimately to the basic form: Individual
So-and-so experiences thus; Such-and-such is so. Only as thus reduced can such
potentially misleading expressions be rightly understood and judged true or
false.
krause: philosopher representative of a
tendency to develop Kant’s views in the direction of pantheism and mysticism.
Educated at Jena, he came under the influence of Fichte and Schelling. Taking
his philosophical starting point as Fichte’s analysis of self-consciousness,
and adopting as his project a “spiritualized” systematic elaboration of the
philosophy of Spinoza (somewhat like the young Schelling), he arrived at a
position that he called panentheism. According to this, although nature and
human consciousness are part of God or Absolute Being, the Absolute is neither
exhausted in nor identical with them. To some extent, he anticipated Hegel in
invoking an “end of history” in which the finite realm of human affairs would
reunite with the infinite essence in a universal moral and “spiritual” order.
Kripke: philosopher cited by H. P. Grice, he
formulated a semantics for modal logic (the logic of necessity and possibility)
based on Leibniz’s notion of a possible world, and, using the apparatus, proved
completeness for a variety of systems. Possible world semantics (due in part
also to Carnap and others) has proved to be pretty fruitful.. Kripke’s Princeton
lectures, Naming and Necessity are a watershed. The work primarily concerns
proper names of individuals (e.g., ‘H. P. Grice is called ‘H. P. Grice’’) and,
by extension, terms for natural kinds (‘Oxonian’) and similar expressions.
Kripke uses his thesis that any such term is a “rigid designator,”– i.e.,
designates the same thing with respect to every possible world in which that
thing exists (and does not designate anything else with respect to worlds in
which it does not exist) – to argue, contrary to the received Fregeian view,
that the designation of a proper name is not semantically secured by means of a
description that gives the sense of the name. On the contrary, the description
associated with a particular use of a name will frequently designate something
else entirely. Kripke derives putative examples of necessary a posteriori
truths, as well as contingent a priori truths. In addition, he defends
essentialism – the doctrine that some properties of things are properties that
those things could not fail to have (except by not existing) – and uses it,
together with his account of natural-kind terms, to argue against the
identification of mental entities with their physical manifestations (e.g.,
sensations with specific neural events). In a sequel, “A Puzzle about Belief,” Kripke
addresses the problem of substitution failure in sentential contexts
attributing belief or other propositional attitudes. Kripke’s interpretation of
the later Wittgenstein as a semantic skeptic has also had a profound impact
(Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language). His semantic theory of truth
(“Outline of a Theory of Truth”) has sparked renewed interest in the liar
paradox (‘This statement is false’) and related paradoxes, and in the
development of non-classical languages containing their own truth predicates as
possible models for ordinary language. He is also known for his work in
intuitionism and on his theory of transfinite recursion on admissible ordinals.
Kripke, McCosh Professor of Philosophy at Princeton, frequently lectures on
numerous further significant results in philosophy. A Kripke semantics, a type
of formal semantics for languages with operators A and B for necessity and
possibility (‘possible worlds semantics’ and ‘relational semantics’ are
sometimes used for the same notion); also, a similar semantics for
intuitionistic logic. In a basic version a framefor a sentential language with
A and B is a pair (W, R) where W is a non-empty set (the “possible worlds”) and
R is a binary relation on W – the relation of “relative possibility” or
“accessibility.” A model on the frame (W, R) is a triple (W, R, V), where V is
a function (the “valuation function”) that assigns truth-values to sentence
letters at worlds. If w 1 W then a sentence AA is true at world w in the model
(W, R, V) if A is true at all worlds v 1 W for which wRv. Informally, AA is
true at world w if A is true at all the worlds that would be possible if w were
actual. This is a generalization of the doctrine commonly attributed to Leibniz
that necessity is truth in all possible worlds. A is valid in the model (W, R, V)
if it is true at all worlds w 1 W in that model. It is valid in the frame (W, R)
if it is valid in all models on that frame. It is valid if it is valid in all
frames. In predicate logic versions, a frame may include another component D,
that assigns a non-empty set Dw of objects (the existents at w) to each
possible world w. Terms and quantifiers may be treated either as objectual
(denoting and ranging over individuals) or conceptual (denoting and ranging
over functions from possible worlds to individuals) and either as actualist or
possibilist(denoting and ranging over either existents or possible existents).
On some of these treatments there may arise further choices about whether and
how truth-values should be assigned to sentences that assert relations among
non-existents. The development of Kripke semantics marks a watershed in the
modern study of modal systems. A number of axiomatizations for necessity and
possibility were proposed and investigated. Carnap showed that for the simplest
of these systems, C. I. Lewis’s S5, AA can be interpreted as saying that A is
true in all “state descriptions.” Answering even the most basic questions about
the other systems, however, required effort and ingenuity. Stig Kanger, Richard
Montague, Kripke, and Hintikka each formulated interpretations for such systems
that generalized Carnap’s semantics by using something like the accessibility
relation described above. Kripke’s semantics was more natural than the others
in that accessibility was taken to be a relation among mathematically primitive
“possible worlds,” and, in a series of papers, Kripke demonstrated that
versions of it provide characteristic interpretations for a number of modal
systems. For these reasons Kripke’s formulation has become standard. Relational
semantics provided simple solutions to some older problems about the distinctness
and relative strength of the various systems. It also opened new areas of
investigation, facilitating general results (establishing decidability and
other properties for infinite classes of modal systems), incompleteness results
(exhibiting systems not determined by any class of frames), and correspondence
results (showing that the frames verifying certain modal formulas were exactly
the frames meeting certain conditions on R). It suggested parallel
interpretations for notions whose patterns of inference were known to be
similar to that of necessity and possibility, including obligation and
permission, epistemic necessity and possibility, provability and consistency,
and, more recently, the notion of a computation’s inevitably or possibly
terminating in a particular state. It inspired similar semantics for
nonclassical conditionals and the more general neighborhood or functional
variety of possible worlds semantics. The philosophical utility of Kripke
semantics is more difficult to assess. Since the accessibility relation is
often explained in terms of the modal operators, it is difficult to maintain
that the semantics provides an explicit analysis of the modalities it
interprets. Furthermore, questions about which version of the semantics is
correct (particularly for quantified modal systems) are themselves tied to
substantive questions about the nature of things and worlds. The semantics does
impose important constraints on the meaning of modalities, and it provides a
means for many philosophical questions to be posed more clearly and starkly.
Kristeva: The centerpiece of Kristeva’s
semiotic theory has two correlative moments: a focus on the speaking subject as
embodying unconscious motivations (and not simply the conscious intentionality
of a Husserlian transcendental ego) and an articulation of the signifying
phenomenon as a dynamic, productive process (not a static sign-system).
Kristeva’s most systematic philosophical work, La Révolution du langage
poétique brings her semiotics to mature expression through an effective
integration of psychoanalysis (Freud and Lacan), elements of linguistic models
(from Roman Jakobson to Chomskyan generative grammar) and semiology (from
Saussure to Peirce and Louis Hjelmslev), and a literary approach to text
(influenced by Bakhtin). Together the symbolic and the semiotic, two
dialectical and irreconcilable modalities of meaning, constitute the signifying
process. The symbolic designates the systematic rules governing denotative and
propositional speech, while the semiotic isolates an archaic layer of meaning
that is neither representational nor based on relations among signs. The
concept of the chora combines the semiotic, translinguistic layer of meaning
(genotext) with a psychoanalytic, drive-based model of unconscious sound
production, dream logic, and fantasy life that defy full symbolic articulation.
Drawing on Plato’s non-unified notion of the maternal receptacle (Timaeus), the
chora constitutes the space where subjectivity is generated. Drives become
“ordered” in rhythmic patterns during the pre-Oedipal phase before the infant
achieves reflexive capacity, develops spatial intuition and time consciousness,
and posits itself as an enunciating subject. Ordered, but not according to
symbolic laws, semiotic functions arise when the infant forms associations
between its vocal gesticulations and sensorimotor development, and patterns
these associations after the mother’s corporeal modulations. The semiotic
chora, while partly repressed in identity formation, links the subject’s
preverbal yet functional affective life to signification. All literary forms –
epic narrative, metalanguage, contemplation or theoria and text-practice –
combine two different registers of meaning, phenotext and genotext. Yet they do
so in different ways and none encompasses both registers in totality. The
phenotext refers to language in its function “to communicate” and can be
analyzed in terms of syntax and semantics. Though not itself linguistic, the
genotext reveals itself in the way that “phonematic” and “melodic devices” and
“syntactic and logical” features establish “semantic” fields. The genotext
isolates the specific mode in which a text sublimates drives; it denotes the
“process” by which a literary form generates a particular type of subjectivity.
Poetic language is unique in that it largely reveals the genotext. This linkage
between semiotic processes, genotext, and poetic language fulfills the early
linguistic project (1967–73) and engenders a novel post-Hegelian social theory.
Synthesizing semiotics and the destructive death drive’s attack against stasis
artfully restores permanence to Hegelian negativity. Poetic mimesis, because it
transgresses grammatical rules while sustaining signification, reactivates the
irreducible negativity and heterogeneity of drive processes. So effectuating
anamnesis, poetry reveals the subject’s constitution within language and, by
holding open rather than normalizing its repressed desire, promotes critical
analysis of symbolic and institutionalized values. Later works like Pouvoirs de
l’horreur (1980), Etrangers à nous-mêmes (1989), Histoires d’amour, and Les
Nouvelles maladies de l’âme shift away from collective political agency to a
localized, culturally therapeutic focus. Examining xenophobic social
formations, abjection and societal violence, romantic love, grief, women’s
melancholic poison in patriarchy, and a crisis of moral values in the
postmetaphysical age, they harbor forceful implications for ethics and social
theory.
Kropotkin: philosopher, best remembered
for his anarchism and his defense of mutual aid as a factor of evolution.
Traveling extensively in Siberia on scientific expeditions (1862–67), he was
stimulated by Darwin’s newly published theory of evolution and sought, in the
Siberian landscape, confirmation of Darwin’s Malthusian principle of the
struggle for survival. Instead Kropotkin found that underpopulation was the
rule, that climate was the main obstacle to survival, and that mutual aid was a
far more common phenomenon than Darwin recognized. He soon generalized these
findings to social theory, opposing social Darwinism, and also began to espouse
anarchist theory.
No comments:
Post a Comment