Animatum -- philosophical psychology, --
vide H. P. Grice: “Method in philosophical psychology: from the banal to the
bizarre” – in “Conception of Value,” Oxford, Clarendon Press. -- philosophy of
mind, the branch of philosophy that includes the philosophy of psychology,
philosophical psychology, and the area of metaphysics concerned with the nature
of mental phenomena and how they fit into the causal structure of reality.
Philosophy of psychology, a branch of the philosophy of science, examines what
psychology says about the nature of psychological phenomena; examines aspects
of psychological theorizing such as the models used, explanations offered, and
laws invoked; and examines how psychology fits with the social sciences and
natural sciences. Philosophical psychology investigates folk psychology, a body
of commonsensical, protoscientific views about mental phenomena. Such
investigations attempt to articulate and refine views found in folk psychology
about conceptualization, memory, perception, sensation, consciousness, belief,
desire, intention, reasoning, action, and so on. The mindbody problem, a
central metaphysical one in the philosophy of mind, is the problem of whether
mental phenomena are physical and, if not, how they are related to physical
phenomena. Other metaphysical problems in the philosophy of mind include the
free will problem, the problem of personal identity, and the problem of how, if
at all, irrational phenomena such as akrasia and self-deception are possible.
Mindbody dualism Cartesian dualism. The doctrine that the soul is distinct from
the body is found in Plato and discussed throughout the history of philosophy,
but Descartes is considered the father of the modern mindbody problem. He
maintained that the essence of the physical is extension in space. Minds are
unextended substances and thus are distinct from any physical substances. The
essence of a mental substance is to think. This twofold view is called
Cartesian dualism. Descartes was well aware of an intimate relationship between
mind and the brain. There is no a priori reason to think that the mind is
intimately related to the brain; Aristotle, e.g., did not associate them.
Descartes mistakenly thought the seat of the relationship was in the pineal
gland. He maintained, however, that our minds are not our brains, lack spatial
location, and can continue to exist after the death and destruction of our
bodies. Cartesian dualism invites the question: What connects the mind and brain?
Causation is Descartes’s answer: states of our minds causally interact with
states of our brains. When bodily sensations such as aches, pains, itches, and
tickles cause us to moan, wince, scratch, or laugh, they do so by causing brain
states events, processes, which in turn cause bodily movements. In deliberate
action, we act on our desires, motives, and intentions to carry out our
purposes; and acting on these mental states involves their causing brain
states, which in turn cause our bodies to move, thereby causally influencing
the physical world. The physical world, in turn, influences our minds through
its influence on our brains. Perception of the physical world with five
senses sight, hearing, smell, taste, and
touch involves causal transactions from
the physical to the mental: what we perceive i.e., see, hear, etc. causes a
sense experience i.e., a visual experience, aural experience, etc.. Thus,
Descartes held that there is two-way psychophysical causal interaction: from
the mental to the physical as in action and from the physical to the mental as
in perception. The conjunction of Cartesian dualism and the doctrine of two-way
psychophysical causal interaction is called Cartesian interactionism. Perhaps
the most widely discussed difficulty for this view is how states of a
non-spatial substance a mind can causally interact with states of a substance
that is in space a brain. Such interactions have seemed utterly mysterious to
many philosophers. Mystery would remain even if an unextended mind is locatable
at a point in space say, the center of the pineal gland. For Cartesian
interactionism would still have to maintain that causal transactions between
mental states and brain states are fundamental, i.e., unmediated by any
underlying mechanism. Brain states causally interact with mental states, but
there is no answer to the question of how they do so. The interactions are
brute facts. Many philosophers, including many of Descartes’s contemporaries,
have found that difficult to accept. Parallelism. Malebranche and Leibniz,
among others, rejected the possibility of psychophysical causal interaction.
They espoused versions of parallelism: the view that the mental and physical
realms run in parallel, in that types of mental phenomena co-occur with certain
types of physical phenomena, but these co-occurrences never involve causal
interactions. On all extant versions, the parallels hold because of God’s
creation. Leibniz’s parallelism is preestablished harmony: the explanation of
why mental types and certain physical types co-occur is that in the possible
world God actualized i.e., this world they co-occur. In discussing the relation
between the mental and physical realms, Leibniz used the analogy of two
synchronized but unconnected clocks. The analogy is, however, somewhat
misleading; suggesting causal mechanisms internal to each clock and intramental
and intraphysical causal transactions. But Leibniz’s monadology doctrine
excludes the possibility of such transactions: mental and physical phenomena
have no effects even within their own realms. Malebranche is associated with
occasionalism, according to which only God, through his continuous activities,
causes things to happen: non-divine phenomena never cause anything.
Occasionalism differs from preestablished harmony in holding that God is
continually engaged in acts of creation; each moment creating the world anew,
in such a way that the correlations hold. Both brands of parallelism face
formidable difficulties. First, both rest on highly contentious, obscure theological
hypotheses. The contention that God exists and the creation stories in question
require extensive defense and explanation. God’s relationship to the world can
seem at least as mysterious as the relationship Descartes posits between minds
and brains. Second, since parallelism denies the possibility of psychophysical
interaction, its proponents must offer alternatives to the causal theory of
perception and the causal theory of action or else deny that we can perceive
and that we can act intentionally. Third, since parallelism rejects intramental
causation, it must either deny that reasoning is possible or explain how it is
possible without causal connections between thoughts. Fourth, since parallelism
rejects physical transactions, it is hard to see how it can allow, e.g., that
one physical thing ever moves another; for that would require causing a change
in location. Perhaps none of these weighty difficulties is ultimately
insuperable; in any case, parallelism has been abandoned. Epiphenomenalism. Empirical
research gives every indication that the occurrence of any brain state can, in
principle, be causally explained by appeal solely to other physical states. To
accommodate this, some philosophers espoused epiphenomenalism, the doctrine
that physical states cause mental states, but mental states do not cause
anything. This thesis was discussed under the name ‘conscious automatism’ by
Huxley and Hogeson in the late nineteenth century. William James was the first
to use the term ‘epiphenomena’ to mean phenomena that lack causal efficacy. And
James Ward coined the term ‘epiphenomenalism’ in 3. Epiphenomenalism implies
that there is only one-way psychophysical action from the physical to the mental. Since
epiphenomenalism allows such causal action, it can embrace the causal theory of
perception. However, when combined with Cartesian dualism, epiphenomenalism,
like Cartesian interactionism, implies the problematic thesis that states of an
extended substance can affect states of an unextended substance. An epiphenomenalist
can avoid this problem by rejecting the view that the mind is an unextended
substance while maintaining that mental states and events are nonetheless
distinct from physical states and events. Still, formidable problems would
remain. It is hard to see how epiphenomenalism can allow that we are ever
intentional agents. For intentional agency requires acting on reasons, which,
according to the causal theory of action, requires a causal connection between
reasons and actions. Since epiphenomenalism denies that such causal connections
are possible, it must either maintain that our sense of agency is illusory or
offer an alternative to the causal theory of action. Similarly, it must explain
how thinking is possible given that there are no causal connections between
thoughts. Monism The dual-aspect theory. Many philosophers reject Descartes’s
bifurcation of reality into mental and physical substances. Spinoza held a
dualattribute theory also called the
dual-aspect theory according to which
the mental and the physical are distinct modes of a single substance, God. The
mental and the physical are only two of infinitely many modes of this one
substance. Many philosophers opted for a thoroughgoing monism, according to
which all of reality is really of one kind. Materialism, idealism, and neutral
monism are three brands of monism. Hobbes, a contemporary of Descartes,
espoused materialism, the brand of monism according to which everything is
material or physical. Berkeley is associated with idealism, the brand of monism
according to which everything is mental. He held that both mental and physical
phenomena are perceptions in the mind of God. For Hegel’s idealism, everything
is part of the World Spirit. The early twentieth-century British philosophers
Bradley and McTaggart also held a version of idealism. Neutral monism is the
doctrine that all of reality is ultimately of one kind, which is neither mental
nor physical. Hume was a neutral monist, maintaining that mental and physical
substances are really just bundles of the neutral entities. Versions of neutral
monism were later held by Mach and, for a short time, Russell. Russell called
his neutral entities sensibilia and claimed that minds and physical objects are
logical constructions out of them. Phenomenalism. This view, espoused in the
twentieth century by, among others, Ayer, argues that all empirical statements
are synonymous with statements solely about phenomenal appearances. While the
doctrine is about statements, phenomenalism is either a neutral monism or an
idealism, depending on whether phenomenal appearances are claimed to be neither
mental nor physical or, instead, mental. The required translations of physical
statements into phenomenal ones proved not to be forthcoming, however. Chisholm
offered a reason why they would not be: what appearances a physical state of
affairs e.g., objects arrayed in a room has depends both on physical conditions
of observation e.g., lighting and physical conditions of the perceiver e.g., of
the nervous system. At best, a statement solely about phenomenal appearances is
equivalent to one about a physical state of affairs, only when certain physical
conditions of observation and certain physical conditions of the perceiver
obtain. Materialism. Two problems face any monism: it must characterize the
phenomena it takes as basic, and it must explain how the fundamental phenomena
make up non-basic phenomena. The idealist and neutral monist theories proposed
thus far have faltered on one or both counts. Largely because of scientific
successes of the twentieth century, such as the rebirth of the atomic theory of
matter, and the successes of quantum mechanics in explaining chemistry and of
chemistry in turn in explaining much of biology, many philosophers today hold
that materialism will ultimately succeed where idealism and neutral monism
apparently failed. Materialism, however, comes in many different varieties and
each faces formidable difficulties. Logical behaviorism. Ryle ridiculed
Cartesianism as the view that there is a ghost in the machine the body. He
claimed that the view that the mind is a substance rests on a category mistake:
‘mind’ is a noun, but does not name an object. Cartesianism confuses the logic
of discourse about minds with the logic of discourse about bodies. To have a
mind is not to possess a special sort of entity; it is simply to have certain
capacities and dispositions. Compare the thesis that to be alive is to possess
not a certain entity, an entelechy or élan vital, but rather certain capacities
and dispositions. Ryle maintained, moreover, that it was a mistake to regard
mental states such as belief, desire, and intention as internal causes of
behavior. These states, he claimed, are dispositions to behave in overt ways.
In part in response to the dualist point that one can understand our ordinary
psychological vocabulary ‘belief’, ‘desire’, ‘pain’, etc. and know nothing
about the physical states and events in the brain, logical behaviorism has been
proposed as a materialist doctrine that explains this fact. On this view, talk
of mental phenomena is shorthand for talk of actual and potential overt bodily
behavior i.e., dispositions to overt bodily behavior. Logical behaviorism was
much discussed from roughly the 0s until the early 0s. While Ryle is sometimes
counted as a logical behaviorist, he was not committed to the thesis that all
mental talk can be tr. into behavioral talk. The translations promised by
logical behaviorism appear unachievable. As Putnam and others pointed out, one
can fake being in pain and one can be in pain and yet not behave or be disposed
to behave as if one were in pain e.g., one might be paralyzed or might be a
“super-spartan”. Logical behaviorism faces similar difficulties in translating
sentences about what Russell called propositional attitudes i.e., beliefs that
p, desires that p, hopes that p, intentions that p, and the like. Consider the
following sample proposal similar to one offered by Carnap: one believes that
the cat is on the mat if and only if one is disposed to assent to ‘The cat is
on the mat’. First, the proposed translation meets the condition of being
purely behavioral only if assenting is understandable in purely behavioral
terms. That is doubtful. The proposal also fails to provide a sufficient or a
necessary condition: someone may assent to ‘The cat is on the mat’ and yet not
believe the cat is on the mat for the person may be trying to deceive; and a
belief that the cat is on the mat will dispose one to assent to ‘The cat is on
the mat’ only if one understands what is being asked, wants to indicate that
one believes the cat is on the mat, and so on. But none of these conditions is
required for believing that the cat is on the mat. Moreover, to invoke any of
these mentalistic conditions defeats the attempt to provide a purely behavioral
translation of the belief sentence. Although the project of translation has
been abandoned, in recent years Dennett has defended a view in the spirit of
logical behaviorism, intentional systems theory: belief-desire talk functions
to characterize overall patterns of dispositions to overt behavior in an
environmental context for the purposes of predicting overt behavior. The theory
is sometimes characterized as supervenient behaviorism since it implies that
whether an individual has beliefs, desires, intentions and the like supervenes
on his dispositions to overt behavior: if two individuals are exactly alike in
respect of their dispositions to overt behavior, the one has intentional states
if and only if the other does. This view allows, however, that the contents of
an individual’s intentional states what
the individual believes, desires, etc.
may depend on environmental factors. So it is not committed to the supervenience
of the contents of intentional states on dispositions to overt behavior.the
discussion of content externalism below. One objection to this view, due to Ned
Block, is that it would mistakenly count as an intentional agent a giant
look-up table “a Blockhead” that has the same dispositions to peripheral
behavior as a genuine intentional agent. A look-up table is a simple mechanical
device that looks up preprogrammed responses. Identity theories. In the early
0s, Herbert Feigl claimed that mental states are brain states. He pointed out
that if mental properties or state types are merely nomologically correlated
with physical properties or state types, the connecting laws would be
“nomological danglers”: irreducible to physical laws, and thus additional
fundamental laws. According to the identity theory, the connecting laws are not
fundamental laws and so not nomological danglers since they can be explained by
identifying the mental and physical properties in question. In the late 0s and
the early 0s, the philosopher Smart and the psychologist U. T. Place defended
the materialist view that sensations are identical with brain processes. Smart
claimed that while mental terms differ in meaning from physical terms,
scientific investigation reveals that they have the same referents as certain
physical terms. Compare the fact that while ‘the Morning Star’ and ‘the Evening
Star’ differ in meaning empirical investigation reveals the same referent:
Venus. Smart and Place claimed that feeling pain, e.g., is some brain process,
exactly which one to be determined by scientific investigation. Smart claimed
that sensation talk is paraphraseable in topic-neutral terms; i.e., in terms
that leave open whether sensational properties are mental or physical. ‘I have
an orange afterimage’ is paraphraseable roughly as: ‘There is something going
on like what is going on when I have my eyes open, am awake, and there is an
orange illuminated in good light in front of me, i.e., when I really see an
orange’. The description is topic-neutral since it leaves open whether what is
going on is mental or physical. Smart maintained that scientific investigation
reveals that what in fact meets the topic-neutral description is a brain
process. He held that psychophysical identity statements such as ‘Pain is
C-fiber firing’ are contingent, likening these to, e.g., ‘Lightning is
electrical discharge’, which is contingent and knowable only through empirical
investigation. Central state materialism. This brand of materialism was
defended in the late 0s and the early 0s by Armstrong and others. On this view,
mental states are states that are apt to produce a certain range of behavior.
Central state materialists maintain that scientific investigation reveals that
such states are states of the central nervous system, and thus that mental
states are contingently identical with states of the central nervous system.
Unlike logical behaviorism, central state materialism does not imply that
mental sentences can be tr. into physical sentences. Unlike both logical
behaviorism and philosophy of mind philosophy of mind 687 687 intentional systems theory, central
state materialism implies that mental states are actual internal states with
causal effects. And unlike Cartesian interactionism, it holds that
psychophysical interaction is just physical causal interaction. Some central state
materialists held in addition that the mind is the brain. However, if the mind
were the brain, every change in the brain would be a change in the mind; and
that seems false: not every little brain change amounts to a change of mind.
Indeed, the mind ceases to exist when brain death occurs, while the brain
continues to exist. The moral that most materialists nowadays draw from such
considerations is that the mind is not any physical substance, since it is not
a substance of any sort. To have a mind is not to possess a special substance,
but rather to have certain capacities to
think, feel, etc. To that extent, Ryle was right. However, central state
materialists insist that the properly functioning brain is the material seat of
mental capacities, that the exercise of mental capacities consists of brain
processes, and that mental states are brain states that can produce behavior.
Epistemological objections have been raised to identity theories. As
self-conscious beings, we have a kind of privileged access to our own mental
states. The exact avenue of privileged access, whether it is introspection or
not, is controversial. But it has seemed to many philosophers that our access
to our own mental states is privileged in being open only to us, whereas we
lack any privileged access to the states of our central nervous systems. We
come to know about central nervous system states in the same way we come to
know about the central nervous system states of others. So, against central
state materialism and the identity theory, it is claimed that mental states
cannot be states of our central nervous systems. Taking privileged access to
imply that we have incorrigible knowledge of our conscious mental states, and
despairing of squaring privileged access so understood with materialism, Rorty
advocated eliminative materialism, the thesis that there actually are no mental
phenomena. A more common materialist response, however, is to deny that
privileged access entails incorrigibility and to maintain that privileged
access is compatible with materialism. Some materialists maintain that while
certain types of mental states e.g., sensations are types of neurological
states, it will be knowable only by empirical investigation that they are.
Suppose pain is a neural state N. It will be only a posteriori knowable that
pain is N. Via the avenue of privileged access, one comes to believe that one
is in a pain state, but not that one is in an N-state. One can believe one is
in a pain state without believing that one is in an N-state because the concept
of pain is different from the concept of N. Nevertheless, pain is N. Compare
the fact that while water is H2O, the concept of water is different from that
of H2O. Thus, while water is H2O, one can believe there is water in the glass
without believing that there is H2O in it. The avenue of privileged access
presents N conceptualized as pain, but never as neurological state N. The
avenue of privileged access involves the exercise of mental, but not
neurophysiological, concepts. However, our mental concepts answer to apply in virtue of the same properties state types as do certain
of our neurophysiological concepts. The identity theory and central state
materialism both hold that there are contingent psychophysical property and
type identities. Some theorists in this tradition tried to distinguish a notion
of theoretical identity from the notion of strict identity. They held that
mental states are theoretically, but not strictly, identical with brain states.
Against any such distinction, Kripke argued that identities are metaphysically
necessary, i.e., hold in every possible world. If A % B, then necessarily A %
B. Kripke acknowledged that there can be contingent statements of identity. But
such statements, he argued, will employ at least one term that is not a rigid
designator, i.e., a term that designates the same thing in every world in which
it designates anything. Thus, since ‘the inventor of bifocals’ is a non-rigid
designator, ‘Benjamin Franklin is the inventor of bifocals’ is contingent. While
Franklin is the inventor of bifocals, he might not have been. However,
statements of identity in which the identity sign is flanked by rigid
designators are, if true, metaphysically necessary. Kripke held that proper
names are rigid designators, and hence, the true identity statement ‘Cicero is
Tully’ is metaphysically necessary. Nonetheless, a metaphysically necessary
identity statement can be knowable only a posteriori. Indeed, ‘Cicero is Tully’
is knowable only a posteriori. Both ‘water’ and ‘H2O’, he maintained, are rigid
designators: each designates the same kind of stuff in every possible world.
And he thus maintained that it is metaphysically necessary that water is H2O,
despite its not being a priori knowable that water is H2O. On Kripke’s view,
any psychophysical identity statement that employs mental terms and physical
terms that are rigid designators will also be metaphysically necessary, if
true. Central state materialists maintain that mental concepts are equivalent
to concepts whose descriptive content is the state that is apt to produce
such-and-such behavior in such-and-such circumstances. These defining
descriptions for mental concepts are intended to be meaning-giving, not
contingent reference-fixing descriptions; they are, moreover, not rigid
designators. Thus, the central state materialists can concede that all
identities are necessary, but maintain that psychophysical claims of identity
are contingent claims of identity since the mental terms that figure in those
statements are not rigid designators. However, Kripke maintained that our
concepts of sensations and other qualitative states are not equivalent to the
sorts of descriptions in question. The term ‘pain’, he maintained, is a rigid
designator. This position might be refuted by a successful functional analysis
of the concept of pain in physical and/or topic-neutral terms. However, no
successful analysis of this sort has yet been produced. See the section on
consciousness below. A materialist can grant Kripke that ‘pain’ is a rigid designator
and claim that a statement such as ‘Pain is C-fiber firing’ will be
metaphysically necessary if true, but only a posteriori knowable. However,
Kripke raised a formidable problem for this materialism. He pointed out that if
a statement is metaphysically necessary but only a posteriori knowable, its
appearance of contingency calls for explanation. Despite being metaphysically
necessary, ‘Water is H2O’ appears contingent. According to Kripke, we explain
this appearance by noting that one can coherently imagine a world in which
something has all the phenomenal properties of water, and so is an “epistemic
counterpart” of it, yet is not H2O. The fact that we can coherently imagine
such epistemic counterparts explains why ‘Water is H2O’ appears contingent. But
no such explanation is available for e.g. ‘Pain is C-fiber firing’. For an
epistemic counterpart of pain, something with the phenomenal properties of
pain the feel of pain is pain. Something can look, smell, taste,
and feel like water yet not be water. But whatever feels like pain is pain:
pain is a feeling. In contrast, we can explain the apparent contingency of
claims like ‘Water is H2O’ because water is not constituted by its phenomenal
properties; our concept of water allows that it may have a “hidden essence,”
i.e., an essential microstructure. If Kripke is right, then anyone who
maintains that a statement of identity concerning a type of bodily sensation
and a type of physical state is metaphysically necessary yet a posteriori, must
explain the appearance of contingency in a way that differs from the way Kripke
explains the appearance of contingency of ‘Water is H2O’. This is a formidable
challenge. The final section, on consciousness, sketches some materialist
responses to it. The general issue of property and state type identity is
controversial. The claim that water is H2O despite the fact that the concept of
water is distinct from the concept of H2O seems plausible. However, property or
state type identity is more controversial than the identity of types of
substances. For properties or state types, there are no generally accepted
“non-duplication principles” to use a
phrase of David Lewis’s. A nonduplication principle for A’s will say that no
two A’s can be exactly alike in a certain respect; e.g., no two sets can have
exactly the same members. It is widely denied, for instance, that no two
properties can be possessed by exactly the same things. Two properties, it is
claimed, can be possessed by the same things; likewise, two state types can
occur in the same space-time regions. Even assuming that mental concepts are
distinct from physical concepts, the issue of whether mental state types are
physical state types raises the controversial issue of the non-duplication
principle for state types. Token and type physicalisms. Token physicalism is
the thesis that every particular is physical. Type physicalism is the thesis
that every type or kind of entity is physical; thus, the identity thesis and
central state materialism are type physicalist theses since they imply that
types of mental states are types of physical states. Type physicalism implies
token physicalism: given the former, every token falls under some physical
type, and therefore is token-token identical with some token of a physical type.
But token physicalism does not imply type physicalism; the former leaves open
whether physical tokens fall under non-physical types. Some doctrines billed as
materialist or physicalist embrace token epiphenomenalism, but reject type
physicalism. Non-reductive materialism. This form of materialism implies token
physicalism, but denies type physicalism and, as well, that mental types
properties, etc. are reducible to physical types. This doctrine has been
discussed since at least the late nineteenth century and was widely discussed
in the first third of the twentieth century. The British philosophers George
Henry Lewes, Samuel Alexander, Lloyd Morgan, and C. D. Broad all held or
thought plausible a certain version of non-reductive materialism. They held or sympathized
with the view that every substance philosophy of mind philosophy of mind
689 689 either is or is wholly made up
of physical particles, that the well-functioning brain is the material seat of
mental capacities, and that token mental states events, processes, etc. are
token neurophysiological states events, processes, etc.. However, they either
held or thought plausible the view that mental capacities, properties, etc.,
emerge from, and thus do not reduce to, physical capacities, properties, etc.
Lewes coined the term ‘emergence’; and Broad later labeled the doctrine
emergent materialism. Emergent materialists maintain that laws correlating
mental and physical properties are irreducible. These laws would be what Feigl
called nomological danglers. Emergentists maintain that, despite their
untidiness, such laws must be accepted with natural piety. Davidson’s doctrine
of anomalous monism is a current brand of non-reductive materialism. He
explicitly formulates this materialist thesis for events; and his
irreducibility thesis is restricted to intentional mental types e.g., believings, desirings, and intendings.
Anomalous monism says that every event token is physical, but that intentional
mental predicates and concepts ones expressing propositional attitudes do not
reduce, by law or definition, to physical predicates or concepts. Davidson
offers an original argument for this irreducibility thesis. Mental predicates
and concepts are, he claims, governed by constitutive principles of
rationality, but physical predicates and concepts are not. This difference, he
contends, excludes the possibility of reduction of mental predicates and
concepts to physical ones. Davidson denies, moreover, that there are strict
psychological or psychophysical laws. He calls the conjunction of this thesis
and his irreducibility thesis the principle of the anomalism of the mental. His
argument for token physicalism for events appeals to the principle of the
anomalism of the mental and to the principle of the nomological character of
causality: when two events are causally related, they are subsumed by a strict
law. He maintains that all strict laws are physical. Given that claim, and
given the principle of the nomological character of causality, it follows that
every event that is a cause or effect is a physical event. On this view,
psychophysical causation is just causation between physical events. Stephen
Schiffer has also maintained a non-reductive materialism, one he calls
ontological physicalism and sentential dualism: every particular is physical,
but mental truths are irreducible to physical truths. Non-reductive materialism
presupposes that mental state event tokens can fall under physical state types
and, thereby, count as physical state tokens. This presupposition is controversial;
no uncontroversial non-duplication principle for state tokens settles the
issue. Suppose, however, that mental state tokens are physical state tokens,
despite mental state types not being physical state types. The issue of how
mental state types and physical state types are related remains. Suppose that
some physical token x is of a mental type M say, a belief that the cat is on
the mat and some other physical token y is not of type M. There must, it seems,
be some difference between x and y in virtue of which x is, and y is not, of
type M. Otherwise, it is simply a brute fact that x is and y is not of type M.
That, however, seems implausible. The claim that certain physical state tokens
fall under mental state types simply as a matter of brute fact would leave the
difference in question utterly mysterious. But if it is not a brute fact, then
there is some explanation of why a certain physical state is a mental state of
a certain sort. The non-reductive materialist owes us an explanation that does
not imply psychophysical reduction. Moreover, even though the non-reductive
materialist can claim that mental states are causes because they are physical
states with physical effects, there is some question whether mental state types
are relevant to causal relations. Suppose every state is a physical state.
Given that physical states causally interact in virtue of falling under
physical types, it follows that whenever states causally interact they do so in
virtue of falling under physical types. That raises the issue of whether states
are ever causes in virtue of falling under mental types. Type epiphenomenalism
is the thesis that no state can cause anything in virtue of falling under a
mental type. Token epiphenomenalism, the thesis that no mental state can cause
anything, implies type epiphenomenalism, but not conversely. Nonreductive
materialists are not committed to token physicalism. However, token
epiphenomenalism may be false but type epiphenomenalism true since mental
states may be causes only in virtue of falling under physical types, never in
virtue of falling under mental types. Broad raised the issue of type
epiphenomenalism and discussed whether emergent materialism is committed to it.
Ted Honderich, Jaegwon Kim, Ernest Sosa, and others have in recent years raised
the issue of whether non-reductive materialism is committed to type
epiphenomenalism. Brian McLaughlin has argued that the claim that an event acts
as a cause in virtue of falling under a certain physical type is consistent
with the claim that it also acts as a cause in virtue of falling under a
certain mental type, even when the mental type is not identical with the
physical type. But even if this is so, the relationship between mental types
and physical types must be addressed. Ernest LePore and Barry Loewer, Frank
Jackson and Philip Pettit, Stephen Yablo, and others have attempted to
characterize a relation between mental types and physical types that allows for
the causal relevance of mental types. But whether there is a relation between
mental and physical properties that is both adequate to secure the causal
relevance of mental properties and available to non-reductive materialists
remains an open question. Davidson’s anomalous monism may appear to be a kind
of dual-aspect theory: there are events and they can have two sorts of
autonomous aspects, mental and physical. However, while Davidson holds that
mental properties or types do not reduce to physical ones, he also holds that
the mental properties of an event depend on its physical properties in that the
former supervene on the latter in this sense: no two events can be exactly
alike in every physical respect and yet differ in some mental respect. This
proposal introduced the notion of supervenience into contem- porary philosophy
of mind. Often nonreductive materialists argue that mental properties types
supervene on physical properties types. Kim, however, has distinguished various
supervenience relations, and argues that some are too weak to count as versions
of materialism as opposed to, say, dual-aspect theory, while other
supervenience relations are too strong to use to formulate non-reductive
materialism since they imply reducibility. According to Kim, non-reductive
materialism is an unstable position. Materialism as a supervenience thesis.
Several philosophers have in recent years attempted to define the thesis of
materialism using a global supervenience thesis. Their aim is not to formulate
a brand of non-reductive materialism; they maintain that their supervenience
thesis may well imply reducibility. Their aim is, rather, to formulate a thesis
to which anyone who counts as a genuine materialist must subscribe. David Lewis
has maintained that materialism is true if and only if any non-alien possible
worlds that are physically indiscernible are mentally indiscernible as well.
Non-alien possible worlds are worlds that have exactly the same perfectly
natural properties as the actual world. Frank Jackson has offered this
proposal: materialism is true if and only if any minimal physical duplicate of
the actual world is a duplicate simpliciter of the actual world. A world is a
physical duplicate of the actual world if and only if it is exactly like the
actual world in every physical respect physical particular for physical
particular, physical property for physical property, physical relation for
physical relation, etc.; and a world is a duplicate simpliciter of the actual
world if and only if it is exactly like the actual world in every respect. A
minimal physical duplicate of the actual world is a physical duplicate that
contains nothing else by way of particulars, kinds, properties, etc. than it
must in order to be a physical duplicate of the actual world. Two questions
arise for any formulation of the thesis of materialism. Is it adequate to
materialism? And, if it is, is it true? Functionalism. The nineteenth-century
British philosopher George Henry Lewes maintained that while not every
neurological event is mental, every mental event is neurological. He claimed
that what makes certain neurological events mental events is their causal role
in the organism. This is a very early version of functionalism, nowadays a
leading approach to the mindbody problem. Functionalism implies an answer to
the question of what makes a state token a mental state of a certain kind M:
namely, that it is an instance of some functional state type identical with M.
There are two versions of this proposal. On one, a mental state type M of a
system will be identical with the state type that plays a certain causal role R
in the system. The description ‘the state type that plays R in the system’ will
be a nonrigid designator; moreover, different state types may play R in
different organisms, in which case the mental state is multiply realizable. On
the second version, a mental state type M is identical with a second-order
state type, the state of being in some first-order state that plays causal role
R. More than one first-order state may play role R, and thus M may be multiply
realizable. On either version, if the relevant causal roles are specifiable in
physical or topic-neutral terms, then the functional definitions of mental
state types will be, in principle, physically reductive. Since the roles would
be specified partly in topic-neutral terms, there may well be possible worlds
in which the mental states are realized by non-physical states; thus,
functionalism does not imply token physicalism. However, functionalists
typically maintain that, on the empirical evidence, mental states are realized
in our world only by physical states. Functionalism comes in many varieties.
philosophy of mind philosophy of mind 691
691 Smart’s topic-neutral analysis of our talk of sensations is in the
spirit of functionalism. And Armstrong’s central state materialism counts as a
kind of functionalism since it maintains that mental states are states apt to
produce a certain range of behavior, and thus identifies states as mental
states by their performing this causal role. However, functionalists today
typically hold that the defining causal roles include causal roles vis-à-vis
input state types, as well as output state types, and also vis-à-vis other
internal state types of the system in question. In the 0s David Lewis proposed
a functionalist theory, analytical functionalism, according to which
definitions of mental predicates such as ‘belief’, ‘desire’, and the like
though not predicates such as ‘believes that p’ or ‘desires that q’ can be
obtained by conjoining the platitudes of commonsense psychology and formulating
the Ramsey sentence for the conjunction. The relevant Ramsey sentence is a
second-order quantificational sentence that quantifies over the mental
predicates in the conjunction of commonsense psychological platitudes, and from
it one can derive definitions of the mental predicates. On this view, it will
be analytic that a certain mental state e.g., belief is the state that plays a
certain causal role vis-à-vis other states; and it is a matter of empirical
investigation what state plays the role. Lewis claimed that such investigation
reveals that the state types that play the roles in question are physical
states. In the early 0s, Putnam proposed a version of scientific functionalism,
machine state functionalism: according to this view, mental states are types of
Turing machine table states. Turing machines are mechanical devices consisting
of a tape with squares on it that either are blank or contain symbols, and an
executive that can move one square to the left, or one square to the right, or
stay where it is. And it can either write a symbol on a square, erase a symbol
on a square, or leave the square as it is. According to the Church-Turing
thesis, every computable function can be computed by a Turing machine. Now
there are two functions specifying such a machine: one from input states to
output states, the other from input states to input states. And these functions
are expressible by counterfactuals e.g., ‘If the machine is in state s 1 and
receives input I, it will emit output O and enter state s2’. Machine tables are
specified by the counterfactuals that express the functions in question. So the
main idea of machine state functionalism is that any given mental type is
definable as the state type that participates in certain counterfactual
relationships specified in terms of purely formal, and so not semantically
interpreted, state types. Any system whose inputs, outputs, and internal states
are counterfactually related in the way characterized by a machine table is a
realization of that table. This version of machine state functionalism has been
abandoned: no one maintains that the mind has the architecture of a Turing
machine. However, computational psychology, a branch of cognitive psychology,
presupposes a scientific functionalist view of cognitive states: it takes the mind
to have a computational architecture. See the section on cognitive psychology
below. Functionalism the view that what
makes a state a realization of a mental state is its playing a certain causal
role remains a leading theory of mind.
But functionalism faces formidable difficulties. Block has pinpointed one. On
the one hand, if the input and output states that figure in the causal role
alleged to define a certain mental state are specified in insufficient detail,
the functional definition will be too liberal: it will mistakenly classify
certain states as of that mental type. On the other hand, if the input and
output states are specified in too much detail, the functional definition will
be chauvinistic: it will fail to count certain states as instances of the
mental state that are in fact such instances. Moreover, it has also been argued
that functionalism cannot capture conscious states since types of conscious
states do not admit of functional definitions. Cognitive psychology, content,
and consciousness Cognitive psychology. Many claim that one aim of cognitive
psychology is to provide explanations of intentional capacities, capacities to
be in intentional states e.g., believing and to engage in intentional
activities e.g., reasoning. Fodor has argued that classical cognitive
psychology postulates a cognitive architecture that includes a language of
thought: a system of mental representation with a combinatorial syntax and
semantics, and computational processes defined over these mental representations
in virtue of their syntactic structures. On this view, cognition is
rule-governed symbol manipulation. Mental symbols have meanings, but they
participate in computational processes solely in virtue of their syntactic or
formal properties. The mind is, so to speak, a syntactic engine. The view
implies a kind of content parallelism: syntaxsensitive causal transitions
between symbols will preserve semantic coherence. Fodor has mainphilosophy of
mind philosophy of mind 692 692 tained
that, on this language-of-thought view of cognition the classical view, being
in a beliefthat-p state can be understood as consisting in bearing a
computational relation one that is constitutive of belief to a sentence in the
language of thought that means that p; and similarly for desire, intention, and
the like. The explanation of intentional capacities will be provided by a
computational theory for mental sentences in conjunction with a psychosemantic
theory, a theory of meaning for mental sentences. A research program in cognitive
science called connectionism postulates networks of neuron-like units. The
units can be either on or off, or can have continuous levels of activation.
Units are connected, the connections have various degrees of strength, and the
connections can be either inhibitory or excitatory. Connectionism has provided
fruitful models for studying how neural networks compute information. Moreover,
connectionists have had much success in modeling pattern recognition tasks
e.g., facial recognition and tasks consisting of learning categories from
examples. Some connectionists maintain that connectionism will yield an
alternative to the classical language-of-thought account of intentional states
and capacities. However, some favor a mixed-models approach to cognition: some
cognitive capacities are symbolic, some connectionist. And some hold that
connectionism will yield an implementational architecture for a symbolic
cognitive architecture, one that will help explain how a symbolic cognitive
architecture is realized in the nervous system. Content externalism. Many today
hold that Twin-Earth thought experiments by Putnam and Tyler Burge show that
the contents of a subject’s mental states do not supervene on intrinsic
properties of the subject: two individuals can be exactly alike in every
intrinsic respect, yet be in mental states with different contents. In response
to Twin-Earth thought experiments, some philosophers have, however, attempted
to characterize a notion of narrow content, a kind of content that supervenes
on intrinsic properties of thinkers. Content, externalists claim, depends on
extrinsic-contextual factors. If externalism is correct, then a psychosemantic
theory must examine the relation between mental symbols and the extrinsic,
contextual factors that determine contents. Stephen Stich has argued that
psychology should eschew psychosemantics and concern itself only with the
syntactic properties of mental sentences. Such a psychology could not explain
intentional capacities. But Stich urges that computational psychology also
eschew that explanatory goal. If, however, psychology is to explain intentional
capacities, a psychosemantic theory is needed. Dretske, Fodor, Ruth Millikan,
and David Papineau have each independently attempted to provide, in physicalistically
respectable terms, foundations for a naturalized externalist theory of the
content of mental sentences or internal physical states. Perhaps the leading
problem for these theories of content is to explain how the physical and
functional facts about a state determine a unique content for it. Appealing to
work by Quine and by Kripke, some philosophers argue that such facts will not
determine unique contents. Both causal and epistemic concerns have been raised
about externalist theories of content. Such theories invite the question
whether the property of having a certain content is ever causally relevant. If
content is a contextual property of a state that has it, can states have
effects in virtue of their having a certain content? This is an important issue
because intentional states figure in explanations not only in virtue of their
intentional mode whether they are beliefs, or desires, etc. but also in virtue
of their contents. Consider an everyday belief-desire explanation. The fact
that the subject’s belief was that there was milk in the refrigerator and the
fact that the subject’s desire was for milk are both essential to the belief
and desire explaining why the subject went to the refrigerator. Dretske, who
maintains that content depends on a causal-historical context, has attempted to
explain how the property of having a certain content can be causally relevant
even though the possession of the property depends on causal-historical
factors. And various other philosophers have attempted to explain how the
causal relevance of content can be squared with the fact that it fails to
supervene on intrinsic properties of the subject. A further controversial
question is whether externalism is consistent with our having privileged access
to what we are thinking. Consciousness. Conscious states such as pain states,
visual experiences, and so on, are such that it is “like” something for the
subject of the state to be in them. Such states have a qualitative aspect, a
phenomenological character. The what-it-is-like aspects of experiences are
called qualia. Qualia pose a serious difficulty for physicalism. Broad argued
that one can know all the physical properties of a chemical and how it causally
interacts with other physical phenomena and yet not know what it is like to
smell it. He concluded that the smell of the chemical is philosophy of mind
philosophy of mind 693 693 not itself
a physical property, but rather an irreducible emergent property. Frank Jackson
has recently defended a version of the argument, which has been dubbed the
knowledge argument. Jackson argues that a super-scientist, Mary, who knows all
the physical and functional facts about color vision, light, and matter, but
has never experienced redness since she has spent her entire life in a black
and white room, would not know what it is like to visually experience red. He
concludes that the physical and functional topic-neutral facts do not entail
all the facts, and thus materialism is false. In response, Lawrence Nemirow,
David Lewis, and others have argued that knowing what it is like to be in a
certain conscious state is, in part, a matter of know-how e.g., to be able to
imagine oneself in the state rather than factual knowledge, and that the
failure of knowledge of the physical and functional facts to yield such
know-how does not imply the falsity of materialism. Functionalism seems unable
to solve the problem of qualia since qualia seem not to be functionally
definable. In the 0s, Fodor and Ned Block argued that two states can have the
same causal role, thereby realizing the same functional state, yet the qualia
associated with each can be inverted. This is called the problem of inverted
qualia. The color spectrum, e.g., might be inverted for two individuals a
possibility raised by Locke, despite their being in the same functional states.
They further argued that two states might realize the same functional state,
yet the one might have qualia associated with it and the other not. This is
called the problem of absent qualia. Sydney Shoemaker has argued that the
possibility of absent qualia can be ruled out on functionalist grounds.
However, he has also refined the inverted qualia scenario and further
articulated the problem it poses for functionalism. Whether functionalism or
physicalism can avoid the problems of absent and inverted qualia remains an
open question. Thomas Nagel claims that conscious states are subjective: to
fully understand them, one must understand what it is like to be in them, but
one can do that only by taking up the experiential point of view of a subject
in them. Physical states, in contrast, are objective. Physical science attempts
to characterize the world in abstraction from the experiential point of view of
any subject. According to Nagel, whether phenomenal mental states reduce to
physical states turns on whether subjective states reduce to objective states;
and, at present, he claims, we have no understanding of how they could. Nagel
has suggested that consciousness may be explainable only by appeal to as yet
undiscovered basic nonmental, non-physical properties “proto-mental properties” the idea being that experiential points of
view might be constituted by protomental properties together with physical
properties. He thus claims that panphysicism is worthy of serious consideration.
Frank Jackson, James Van Cleve, and David Chalmers have argued that conscious
properties are emergent, i.e., fundamental, irreducible macro-properties; and
Chalmers sympathizes with a brand of panphysicism. Colin McGinn claims that
while conscious properties are likely reductively explainable by brain
properties, our minds seem conceptually closed to the explaining properties: we
are unable to conceptualize them, just as a cat is unable to conceptualize a
square root. Dennett attempts to explain consciousness in supervenient
behaviorist terms. David Rosenthal argues that consciousness is a special case
of intentionality more specifically,
that conscious states are just states we can come in a certain direct way to
believe we are in. Dretske, William Lycan, and Michael Tye argue that conscious
properties are intentional properties and physicalistically reducible. Patricia
Churchland argues that conscious phenomena are reducible to neurological
phenomena. Brian Loar contends that qualia are identical with either functional
or neurological states of the brain; and Christopher Hill argues specifically
that qualia are identical with neurological states. Loar and Hill attempt to
explain away the appearance of contingency of psychophysical identity claims,
but in a way different from the way Kripke attempts to explain the appearance
of contingency of ‘Water is H2O’, since they concede that that mode of
explanation is unavailable. They appeal to differences in the conceptual roles
of neurological and functional concepts by contrast with phenomenal concepts.
They argue that while such concepts are different, they answer to the same
properties. The nature of consciousness thus remains a matter of dispute.
Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Method in philosophical psychology: from the banal to the
bizarre,” in The Conception of Value, Oxford, Clarendon.
Animatum – vide: H. P. Grice, “Psychology,
folk psychology, etc.” -- philosophy of psychology, the philosophical study of
psychology. Psychology began to separate from philosophy with the work of the
nineteenth-century G. experimentalists, especially Fechner 180187, Helmholtz
1821 94, and Wundt 18320. In the first half of the twentieth century, the
separation was completed in this country insofar as separate psychology departments
were set up in most universities, psychologists established their own journals
and professional associations, and experimental methods were widely employed,
although not in every area of psychology the first experimental study of the
effectiveness of a psychological therapy did not occur until 3. Despite this
achievement of autonomy, however, issues have remained about the nature of the
connections, if any, that should continue between psychology and philosophy.
One radical view, that virtually all such connections should be severed, was
defended by the behaviorist John Watson in his seminal 3 paper “Psychology as
the Behaviorist Views It.” Watson criticizes psychologists, even the
experimentalists, for relying on introspective methods and for making
consciousness the subject matter of their discipline. He recommends that
psychology be a purely objective experimental branch of natural science, that
its theoretical goal be to predict and control behavior, and that it discard
all reference to consciousness. In making behavior the sole subject of
psychological inquiry, we avoid taking sides on “those time-honored relics of
philosophical speculation,” namely competing theories about the mindbody
problem, such as interactionism and parallelism. In a later work, published in
5, Watson claimed that the success of behaviorism threatened the very existence
of philosophy: “With the behavioristic point of view now becoming dominant, it
is hard to find a place for what has been called philosophy. Philosophy is passing has all but passed, and unless new issues
arise which will give a foundation for a new philosophy, the world has seen its
last great philosopher.” One new issue was the credibility of behaviorism.
Watson gave no argument for his view that prediction and control of behavior
should be the only theoretical goals of psychology. If the attempt to explain
behavior is also legitimate, as some anti-behaviorists argue, then it would
seem to be an empirical question whether that goal can be met without appealing
to mentalistic causes. Watson and his successors, such as B. F. Skinner, cited
no credible empirical evidence that it could, but instead relied primarily on
philosophical arguments for banning postulation of mentalistic causes. As a
consequence, behaviorists virtually guaranteed that philosophers of psychology
would have at least one additional task beyond wrestling with traditional mind
body issues: the analysis and criticism of behaviorism itself. Although
behaviorism and the mindbody problem were never the sole subjects of philosophy
of psychology, a much richer set of topics developed after 0 when the so-called
cognitive revolution occurred in
psychology. These topics include innate knowledge and the acquisition of
transformational grammars, intentionality, the nature of mental representation,
functionalism, mental imagery, the language of thought, and, more recently,
connectionism. Such topics are of interest to many cognitive psychologists and
those in other disciplines, such as linguistics and artificial intelligence,
who contributed to the emerging discipline known as cognitive science. Thus,
after the decline of various forms of behaviorism and the consequent rise of
cognitivism, many philosophers of psychology collaborated more closely with psychologists.
This increased cooperation was probably due not only to a broadening of the
issues, but also to a methodological change in philosophy. In the period
roughly between 5 and 5, conceptual analysis dominated both and English philosophy of psychology and the
closely related discipline, the philosophy of mind. Many philosophers took the
position that philosophy was essentially an a priori discipline. These
philosophers rarely cited the empirical studies of psychologists. In recent
decades, however, philosophy of psychology has become more empirical, at least
in the sense that more attention is being paid to the details of the empirical
studies of psychologists. The result is more interchanges between philosophers
and psychologists. Although interest in cognitive psychology appears to
predominate in recent philosophy of
psychology, the new emphasis on empirical studies is also reflected in
philosophic work on topics not directly related to cognitive psychology. For
example, philosophers of psychology have written books in recent years on the
clinical foundations of psychoanalysis, the foundations of behavior therapy and
behavior modification, and self-deception. The emphasis on empirical data has
been taken one step further by naturalists, who argue that in epistemology, at
least, and perhaps in all areas of philosophy, philosophical questions should
either be replaced by questions from empirical psychology or be answered by
appeal to empirical studies in psychology and related disciplines. It is
philosophy of psychology philosophy of psychology 695 695 still too early to predict the
fruitfulness of the naturalist approach, but this new trend might well have
pleased Watson. Taken to an extreme, naturalism would make philosophy dependent
on psychology instead of the reverse and thus would further enhance the
autonomy of psychology that Watson desired.
philosophical
theology:
Grice: “At Oxford, pretentious as they are, they like ‘divinity’ – there are
doctors in divinity!” -- philosophy of religion, the subfield of philosophy
devoted to the study of religious phenomena. Although religions are typically
complex systems of theory and practice, including both myths and rituals,
philosophers tend to concentrate on evaluating religious truth claims. In the
major theistic traditions, Judaism, Christianity, and Islam, the most important
of these claims concern the existence, nature, and activities of God. Such
traditions commonly understand God to be something like a person who is
disembodied, eternal, free, all-powerful, all-knowing, the creator and
sustainer of the universe, and the proper object of human obedience and
worship. One important question is whether this conception of the object of
human religious activity is coherent; another is whether such a being actually
exists. Philosophers of religion have sought rational answers to both
questions. The major theistic traditions draw a distinction between religious
truths that can be discovered and even known by unaided human reason and those
to which humans have access only through a special divine disclosure or
revelation. According to Aquinas, e.g., the existence of God and some things
about the divine nature can be proved by unaided human reason, but such
distinctively Christian doctrines as the Trinity and Incarnation cannot be thus
proved and are known to humans only because God has revealed them. Theists
disagree about how such divine disclosures occur; the main candidates for
vehicles of revelation include religious experience, the teachings of an
inspired religious leader, the sacred scriptures of a religious community, and
the traditions of a particular church. The religious doctrines Christian
traditions take to be the content of revelation are often described as matters
of faith. To be sure, such traditions typically affirm that faith goes beyond
mere doctrinal belief to include an attitude of profound trust in God. On most
accounts, however, faith involves doctrinal belief, and so there is a contrast
within the religious domain itself between faith and reason. One way to spell
out the contrast though not the only
way is to imagine that the content of
revelation is divided into two parts. On the one hand, there are those doctrines,
if any, that can be known by human reason but are also part of revelation; the
existence of God is such a doctrine if it can be proved by human reason alone.
Such doctrines might be accepted by some people on the basis of rational
argument, while others, who lack rational proof, accept them on the authority
of revelation. On the other hand, there are those doctrines that cannot be
known by human reason and for which the authority of revelation is the sole
basis. They are objects of faith rather than reason and are often described as
mysteries of faith. Theists disagree about how such exclusive objects of faith
are related to reason. One prominent view is that, although they go beyond
reason, they are in harmony with it; another is that they are contrary to
reason. Those who urge that such doctrines should be accepted despite the fact
that, or even precisely because, they are contrary to reason are known as
fideists; the famous slogan credo quia absurdum ‘I believe because it is
absurd’ captures the flavor of extreme fideism. Many scholars regard
Kierkegaard as a fideist on account of his emphasis on the paradoxical nature
of the Christian doctrine that Jesus of Nazareth is God incarnate. Modern
philosophers of religion have, for the most part, confined their attention to
topics treatable without presupposing the truth of any particular tradition’s
claims about revelation and have left the exploration of mysteries of faith to
the theologians of various traditions. A great deal of philosophical work
clarifying the concept of God has been prompted by puzzles that suggest some
incoherence in the traditional concept. One kind of puzzle concerns the
coherence of individual claims about the nature of God. Consider the
traditional affirmation that God is allpowerful omnipotent. Reflection on this
doctrine raises a famous question: Can God make a stone so heavy that even God
cannot lift it? No matter how this is answered, it seems that there is at least
one thing that even God cannot do, i.e., make such a stone or lift such a
stone, and so it appears that even God cannot be all-powerful. Such puzzles
stimulate attempts by philosophers to analyze the concept of omnipotence in a
way that specifies more precisely the scope of the powers coherently
attributable to an omnipotent being. To the extent that such attempts succeed,
they foster a deeper understanding of the concept of God and, if God exists, of
the divine nature. Another sort of puzzle concerns the consistency of
attributing two or more properties to philosophy of religion philosophy of
religion 696 696 God. Consider the
claim that God is both immutable and omniscient. An immutable being is one that
cannot undergo internal change, and an omniscient being knows all truths, and
believes no falsehoods. If God is omniscient, it seems that God must first know
and hence believe that it is now Tuesday and not believe that it is now
Wednesday and later know and hence believe that it is now Wednesday and not
believe that it is now Tuesday. If so, God’s beliefs change, and since change
of belief is an internal change, God is not immutable. So it appears that God
is not immutable if God is omniscient. A resolution of this puzzle would
further contribute to enriching the philosophical understanding of the concept
of God. It is, of course, one thing to elaborate a coherent concept of God; it
is quite another to know, apart from revelation, that such a being actually
exists. A proof of the existence of God would yield such knowledge, and it is
the task of natural theology to evaluate arguments that purport to be such
proofs. As opposed to revealed theology, natural theology restricts the
assumptions fit to serve as premises in its arguments to things naturally
knowable by humans, i.e., knowable without special revelation from supernatural
sources. Many people have hoped that such natural religious knowledge could be
universally communicated and would justify a form of religious practice that
would appeal to all humankind because of its rationality. Such a religion would
be a natural religion. The history of natural theology has produced a
bewildering variety of arguments for the existence of God. The four main types
are these: ontological arguments, cosmological arguments, teleological
arguments, and moral arguments. The earliest and most famous version of the
ontological argument was set forth by Anselm of Canterbury in chapter 2 of his
Proslogion. It is a bold attempt to deduce the existence of God from the
concept of God: we understand God to be a perfect being, something than which
nothing greater can be conceived. Because we have this concept, God at least
exists in our minds as an object of the understanding. Either God exists in the
mind alone, or God exists both in the mind and as an extramental reality. But
if God existed in the mind alone, then we could conceive of a being greater
than that than which nothing greater can be conceived, namely, one that also
existed in extramental reality. Since the concept of a being greater than that
than which nothing greater can be conceived is incoherent, God cannot exist in
the mind alone. Hence God exists not only in the mind but also in extramental
reality. The most celebrated criticism of this form of the argument was Kant’s,
who claimed that existence is not a real predicate. For Kant, a real predicate
contributes to determining the content of a concept and so serves as a part of
its definition. But to say that something falling under a concept exists does
not add to the content of a concept; there is, Kant said, no difference in
conceptual content between a hundred real dollars and a hundred imaginary
dollars. Hence whether or not there exists something that corresponds to a
concept cannot be settled by definition. The existence of God cannot be deduced
from the concept of a perfect being because existence is not contained in the
concept or the definition of a perfect being. Contemporary philosophical
discussion has focused on a slightly different version of the ontological
argument. In chapter 3 of Proslogion Anselm suggested that something than which
nothing greater can be conceived cannot be conceived not to exist and so exists
necessarily. Following this lead, such philosophers as Charles Hartshorne,
Norman Malcolm, and Alvin Plantinga have contended that God cannot be a
contingent being who exists in some possible worlds but not in others. The
existence of a perfect being is either necessary, in which case God exists in
every possible world, or impossible, in which case God exists in no possible
worlds. On this view, if it is so much as possible that a perfect being exists,
God exists in every possible world and hence in the actual world. The crucial
premise in this form of the argument is the assumption that the existence of a
perfect being is possible; it is not obviously true and could be rejected
without irrationality. For this reason, Plantinga concedes that the argument
does not prove or establish its conclusion, but maintains that it does make it
rational to accept the existence of God. The key premises of various
cosmological arguments are statements of obvious facts of a general sort about
the world. Thus, the argument to a first cause begins with the observation that
there are now things undergoing change and things causing change. If something
is a cause of such change only if it is itself caused to change by something
else, then there is an infinitely long chain of causes of change. But, it is
alleged, there cannot be a causal chain of infinite length. Therefore there is
something that causes change, but is not caused to change by anything else,
i.e., a first cause. Many critics of this form of the argument deny its
assumption that there cannot be an infinite causal regress or chain of causes.
This argument also fails to show that there is only one first cause and does
not prove that a first cause must have such divine attributes as omniscience,
omnipotence, and perfect goodness. A version of the cosmological argument that
has attracted more attention from contemporary philosophers is the argument
from contingency to necessity. It starts with the observation that there are
contingent beings beings that could have
failed to exist. Since contingent beings do not exist of logical necessity, a
contingent being must be caused to exist by some other being, for otherwise
there would be no explanation of why it exists rather than not doing so. Either
the causal chain of contingent beings has a first member, a contingent being
not caused by another contingent being, or it is infinitely long. If, on the
one hand, the chain has a first member, then a necessary being exists and
causes it. After all, being contingent, the first member must have a cause, but
its cause cannot be another contingent being. Hence its cause has to be
non-contingent, i.e., a being that could not fail to exist and so is necessary.
If, on the other hand, the chain is infinitely long, then a necessary being
exists and causes the chain as a whole. This is because the chain as a whole,
being itself contingent, requires a cause that must be noncontingent since it
is not part of the chain. In either case, if there are contingent beings, a
necessary being exists. So, since contingent beings do exist, there is a
necessary being that causes their existence. Critics of this argument attack
its assumption that there must be an explanation for the existence of every
contingent being. Rejecting the principle that there is a sufficient reason for
the existence of each contingent thing, they argue that the existence of at
least some contingent beings is an inexplicable brute fact. And even if the
principle of sufficient reason is true, its truth is not obvious and so it
would not be irrational to deny it. Accordingly, William Rowe b.1 concludes
that this version of the cosmological argument does not prove the existence of
God, but he leaves open the question of whether it shows that theistic belief
is reasonable. The starting point of teleological arguments is the phenomenon
of goal-directedness in nature. Aquinas, e.g., begins with the claim that we
see that things which lack intelligence act for an end so as to achieve the
best result. Modern science has discredited this universal metaphysical
teleology, but many biological systems do seem to display remarkable
adaptations of means to ends. Thus, as William Paley 17431805 insisted, the eye
is adapted to seeing and its parts cooperate in complex ways to produce sight.
This suggests an analogy between such biological systems and human artifacts,
which are known to be products of intelligent design. Spelled out in mechanical
terms, the analogy grounds the claim that the world as a whole is like a vast
machine composed of many smaller machines. Machines are contrived by
intelligent human designers. Since like effects have like causes, the world as
a whole and many of its parts are therefore probably products of design by an
intelligence resembling the human but greater in proportion to the magnitude of
its effects. Because this form of the argument rests on an analogy, it is known
as the analogical argument for the existence of God; it is also known as the
design argument since it concludes the existence of an intelligent designer of
the world. Hume subjected the design argument to sustained criticism in his
Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion. If, as most scholars suppose, the
character Philo speaks for Hume, Hume does not actually reject the argument. He
does, however, think that it warrants only the very weak conclusion that the
cause or causes of order in the universe probably bear some remote analogy to
human intelligence. As this way of putting it indicates, the argument does not
rule out polytheism; perhaps different minor deities designed lions and tigers.
Moreover, the analogy with human artificers suggests that the designer or
designers of the universe did not create it from nothing but merely imposed
order on already existing matter. And on account of the mixture of good and
evil in the universe, the argument does not show that the designer or designers
are morally admirable enough to deserve obedience or worship. Since the time of
Hume, the design argument has been further undermined by the emergence of Darwinian
explanations of biological adaptations in terms of natural selection that give
explanations of such adaptations in terms of intelligent design stiff
competition. Some moral arguments for the existence of God conform to the
pattern of inference to the best explanation. It has been argued that the
hypothesis that morality depends upon the will of God provides the best
explanation of the objectivity of moral obligations. Kant’s moral argument,
which is probably the best-known specimen of this type, takes a different tack.
According to Kant, the complete good consists of perfect virtue rewarded with
perfect happiness, and virtue deserves to be rewarded with proportional
happiness because it makes one worthy to be happy. If morality is to command
the allegiance of reason, the complete good must be a real possibility, and so
practical reason is entitled to postulate that the conditions necessary to
guarantee its possibility obtain. As far as anyone can tell, nature and its
laws do not furnish such a guarantee; in this world, apparently, the virtuous
often suffer while the vicious flourish. And even if the operation of natural
laws were to produce happiness in proportion to virtue, this would be merely
coincidental, and hence finite moral agents would not have been made happy just
because they had by their virtue made themselves worthy of happiness. So
practical reason is justified in postulating a supernatural agent with
sufficient goodness, knowledge, and power to ensure that finite agents receive
the happiness they deserve as a reward for their virtue, though theoretical
reason can know nothing of such a being. Critics of this argument have denied
that we must postulate a systematic connection between virtue and happiness in
order to have good reasons to be moral. Indeed, making such an assumption might
actually tempt one to cultivate virtue for the sake of securing happiness
rather than for its own sake. It seems therefore that none of these arguments
by itself conclusively proves the existence of God. However, some of them might
contribute to a cumulative case for the existence of God. According to Richard
Swinburne, cosmological, teleological, and moral arguments individually
increase the probability of God’s existence even though none of them makes it
more probable than not. But when other evidence such as that deriving from
providential occurrences and religious experiences is added to the balance,
Swinburne concludes that theism becomes more probable than its negation.
Whether or not he is right, it does appear to be entirely correct to judge the
rationality of theistic belief in the light of our total evidence. But there is
a case to be made against theism too. Philosophers of religion are interested
in arguments against the existence of God, and fairness does seem to require
admitting that our total evidence contains much that bears negatively on the
rationality of belief in God. The problem of evil is generally regarded as the
strongest objection to theism. Two kinds of evil can be distinguished. Moral evil
inheres in the wicked actions of moral agents and the bad consequences they
produce. An example is torturing the innocent. When evil actions are considered
theologically as offenses against God, they are regarded as sins. Natural evils
are bad consequences that apparently derive entirely from the operations of
impersonal natural forces, e.g. the human and animal suffering produced by
natural catastrophes such as earthquakes and epidemics. Both kinds of evil
raise the question of what reasons an omniscient, omnipotent, and perfectly
good being could have for permitting or allowing their existence. Theodicy is
the enterprise of trying to answer this question and thereby to justify the
ways of God to humans. It is, of course, possible to deny the presuppositions
of the question. Some thinkers have held that evil is unreal; others have
maintained that the deity is limited and so lacks the power or knowledge to
prevent the evils that occur. If one accepts the presuppositions of the
question, the most promising strategy for theodicy seems to be to claim that
each evil God permits is necessary for some greater good or to avoid some
alternative to it that is at least as bad if not worse. The strongest form of
this doctrine is the claim made by Leibniz that this is the best of all
possible worlds. It is unlikely that humans, with their cognitive limitations,
could ever understand all the details of the greater goods for which evils are
necessary, assuming that such goods exist; however, we can understand how some
evils contribute to achieving goods. According to the soul-making theodicy of
John Hick b.2, which is rooted in a tradition going back to Irenaeus, admirable
human qualities such as compassion could not exist except as responses to
suffering, and so evil plays a necessary part in the formation of moral
character. But this line of thought does not seem to provide a complete
theodicy because much animal suffering occurs unnoticed by humans and child
abuse often destroys rather than strengthens the moral character of its
victims. Recent philosophical discussion has often focused on the claim that
the existence of an omniscient, omnipotent, and perfectly good being is
logically inconsistent with the existence of evil or of a certain quantity of
evil. This is the logical problem of evil, and the most successful response to
it has been the free will defense. Unlike a theodicy, this defense does not
speculate about God’s reasons for permitting evil but merely argues that God’s
existence is consistent with the existence of evil. Its key idea is that moral
good cannot exist apart from libertarian free actions that are not causally
determined. If God aims to produce moral good, God must create free creatures
upon whose cooperation he must depend, and so divine omnipotence is limited by
the freedom God confers on creatures. Since such creatures are also free to do
evil, it is possible that God could not have created a world containing moral
good but no moral evil. Plantinga extends the defense from moral to natural
evil by suggesting that it is also possible that all natural evil is due to the
free actions of non-human persons such as Satan and his cohorts. Plantinga and
Swinburne have also addressed the probabilistic problem of evil, which is the
claim that the existence of evil disconfirms or renders improbable the
hypothesis that God exists. Both of them argue for the conclusion that this is
not the case. Finally, it is worth mentioning three other topics on which
contemporary philosophers of religion have worked to good effect. Important
studies of the meaning and use of religious language were stimulated by the
challenge of logical positivism’s claim that theological language is
cognitively meaningless. Defenses of such Christian doctrines as the Trinity,
Incarnation, and Atonement against various philosophical objections have
recently been offered by people committed to elaborating an explicitly
Christian philosophy. And a growing appreciation of religious pluralism has
both sharpened interest in questions about the cultural relativity of religious
rationality and begun to encourage progress toward a comparative philosophy of
religions. Such work helps to make philosophy of religion a lively and diverse
field of inquiry. Grice: “It is extremely important that in a dictionary entry
we keep the ‘philosophical’ – surely we are not lower ourselves to the level of
a theologian – if I am a theologican, I am a philosophical theologian. -- theodicy from Grecian theos, ‘God’, and dike,
‘justice’, a defense of the justice or goodness of God in the face of doubts or
objections arising from the phenomena of evil in the world ‘evil’ refers here
to bad states of affairs of any sort. Many types of theodicy have been proposed
and vigorously debated; only a few can be sketched here. 1 It has been argued
that evils are logically necessary for greater goods e.g., hardships for the
full exemplification of certain virtues, so that even an omnipotent being
roughly, one whose power has no logically contingent limits would have a
morally sufficient reason to cause or permit the evils in order to obtain the
goods. Leibniz, in his Theodicy 1710, proposed a particularly comprehensive
theodicy of this type. On his view, God had adequate reason to bring into
existence the actual world, despite all its evils, because it is the best of
all possible worlds, and all actual evils are essential ingredients in it, so
that omitting any of them would spoil the design of the whole. Aside from
issues about whether actual evils are in fact necessary for greater goods, this
approach faces the question whether it assumes wrongly that the end justifies
the means. 2 An important type of theodicy traces some or all evils to sinful
free actions of humans or other beings such as angels created by God.
Proponents of this approach assume that free action in creatures is of great
value and is logically incompatible with divine causal control of the
creatures’ actions. It follows that God’s not intervening to prevent sins is
necessary, though the sins themselves are not, to the good of created freedom.
This is proposed as a morally sufficient reason for God’s not preventing them.
It is a major task for this type of theodicy to explain why God would permit
those evils that are not themselves free choices of creatures but are at most consequences
of such choices. 3 Another type of theodicy, both ancient and currently
influential among theologians, though less congenial to orthodox traditions in
the major theistic religions, proposes to defend God’s goodness by abandoning
the doctrine that God is omnipotent. On this view, God is causally, rather than
logically, unable to prevent many evils while pursuing sufficiently great
goods. A principal sponsor of this approach at present is the movement known as
process theology, inspired by Whitehead; it depends on a complex metaphysical
theory about the nature of causal relationships. 4 Other theodicies focus more
on outcomes than on origins. Some religious beliefs suggest that God will turn
out to have been very good to created persons by virtue of gifts especially
religious gifts, such as communion with God as supreme Good that may be
bestowed in a life Tetractys theodicy 910
910 after death or in religious experience in the present life. This
approach may be combined with one of the other types of theodicy, or adopted by
people who think that God’s reasons for permitting evils are beyond our finding
out. Then there’s heologia naturalis
Latin, ‘natural theology’, theology that uses the methods of investigation and
standards of rationality of any other area of philosophy. Traditionally, the
central problems of natural theology are proofs for the existence of God and
the problem of evil. In contrast with natural theology, supernatural theology
uses methods that are supposedly revealed by God and accepts as fact beliefs
that are similarly outside the realm of rational acceptability. Relying on a
prophet or a pope to settle factual questions would be acceptable to
supernatural, but not to natural, theology. Nothing prevents a natural
theologian from analyzing concepts that can be used sanguinely by supernatural
theologians, e.g., revelation, miracles, infallibility, and the doctrine of the
Trinity. Theologians often work in both areas, as did, e.g., Anselm and
Aquinas. For his brilliant critiques of traditional theology, Hume deserves the
title of “natural anti-theologian.”
Grice was totally against “the philosophy of X” – never the philosophy
of god – but philosophical theology -- theological naturalism, the attempt to
develop a naturalistic conception of God. As a philosophical position,
naturalism holds 1 that the only reliable methods of knowing what there is are
methods continuous with those of the developed sciences, and 2 that the
application of those methods supports the view that the constituents of reality
are either physical or are causally dependent on physical things and their
modifications. Since supernaturalism affirms that God is purely spiritual and
causally independent of physical things, naturalists hold that either belief in
God must be abandoned as rationally unsupported or the concept of God must be
reconstituted consistently with naturalism. Earlier attempts to do the latter
include the work of Feuerbach and Comte. In twentieth-century naturalism the most significant attempts to develop
a naturalistic conception of God are due to Dewey and Henry Nelson Wieman 45.
In A Common Faith Dewey proposed a view of God as the unity of ideal ends
resulting from human imagination, ends arousing us to desire and action.
Supernaturalism, he argued, was the product of a primitive need to convert the
objects of desire, the greatest ideals, into an already existing reality. In
contrast to Dewey, Wieman insisted on viewing God as a process in the natural
world that leads to the best that humans can achieve if they but submit to its
working in their lives. In his earlier work he viewed God as a cosmic process
that not only works for human good but is what actually produced human life.
Later he identified God with creative interchange, a process that occurs only
within already existing human communities. While Wieman’s God is not a human
creation, as are Dewey’s ideal ends, it is difficult to see how love and
devotion are appropriate to a natural process that works as it does without
thought or purpose. Thus, while Dewey’s God ideal ends lacks creative power but
may well qualify as an object of love and devotion, Wieman’s God a process in
nature is capable of creative power but, while worthy of our care and
attention, does not seem to qualify as an object of love and devotion. Neither
view, then, satisfies the two fundamental features associated with the
traditional idea of God: possessing creative power and being an appropriate
object of supreme love and devotion. H.
P. Grice, “Why I never pursued a doctorate in divinity!” --.
Scientism: One of the twelve labours of H.
P. Grice --. Grice: “When Cicero coined ‘scientia’ out of scire he didn’t know
what he was doing!” -- philosophy of science, the branch of philosophy that is
centered on a critical examination of the sciences: their methods and their
results. One branch of the philosophy of science, methodology, is closely
related to the theory of knowledge. It explores the methods by which science
arrives at its posited truths concerning the world and critically explores
alleged rationales for these methods. Issues concerning the sense in which
theories are accepted in science, the nature of the confirmation relation
between evidence and hypothesis, the degree to which scientific claims can be
falsified by observational data, and the like, are the concern of methodology.
Other branches of the philosophy of science are concerned with the meaning and
content of the posited scientific results and are closely related to
metaphysics and the philosophy of language. Typical problems examined are the
nature of scientific laws, the cognitive content of scientific theories
referring to unobservables, and the structure of scientific explanations.
Finally, philosophy of science explores specific foundational questions arising
out of the specific results of the sciences. Typical questions explored might
be metaphysical presuppositions of space-time theories, the role of probability
in statistical physics, the interpretation of measurement in quantum theory,
the structure of explanations in evolutionary biology, and the like. Concepts
of the credibility of hypotheses. Some crucial concepts that arise when issues
of the credibility of scientific hypotheses are in question are the following:
Inductivism is the view that hypotheses can receive evidential support from
their predictive success with respect to particular cases falling under them.
If one takes the principle of inductive inference to be that the future will be
like the past, one is subject to the skeptical objection that this rule is
empty of content, and even self-contradictory, if any kind of “similarity” of
cases is permitted. To restore content and consistency to the rule, and for
other methodological purposes as well, it is frequently alleged that only
natural kinds, a delimited set of “genuine” properties, should be allowed in
the formulation of scientific hypotheses. The view that theories are first
arrived at as creative hypotheses of the scientist’s imagination and only then
confronted, for justificatory purposes, with the observational predictions
deduced from them, is called the hypotheticodeductive model of science. This
model is contrasted with the view that the very discovery of hypotheses is
somehow “generated” out of accumulated observational data. The view that
hypotheses are confirmed to the degree that they provide the “best explanatory
account” of the data is often called abduction and sometimes called inference
to the best explanation. The alleged relation that evidence bears to
hypothesis, warranting its truth but not, generally, guaranteeing that truth,
is called confirmation. Methodological accounts such as inductivism countenance
such evidential warrant, frequently speaking of evidence as making a hypothesis
probable but not establishing it with certainty. Probability in the
confirmational context is supposed to be a relationship holding between
propositions that is quantitative and is described by the formal theory of
probability. It is supposed to measure the “degree of support” that one proposition
gives to another, e.g. the degree of support evidential statements give to a
hypothesis allegedly supported by them. Scientific methodologists often claim
that science is characterized by convergence. This is the claim that scientific
theories in their historical order are converging to an ultimate, final, and
ideal theory. Sometimes this final theory is said to be true because it
corresponds to the “real world,” as in realist accounts of convergence. In
pragmatist versions this ultimate theory is the defining standard of truth. It
is sometimes alleged that one ground for choosing the most plausible theory,
over and above conformity of the theory with the observational data, is the
simplicity of the theory. Many versions of this thesis exist, some emphasizing
formal elements of the theory and others, e.g., emphasizing paucity of
ontological commitment by the theory as the measure of simplicity. It is
sometimes alleged that in choosing which theory to believe, the scientific
community opts for theories compatible with the data that make minimal changes
in scientific belief necessary from those demanded by previously held theory.
The believer in methodological conservatism may also try to defend such
epistemic conservatism as normatively rational. An experiment that can
decisively show a scientific hypothesis to be false is called a crucial
experiment for the hypothesis. It is a thesis of many philosophers that for
hypotheses that function in theories and can only confront observational data
when conjoined with other theoretical hypotheses, no absolutely decisive
crucial experiment can exist. Concepts of the structure of hypotheses. Here are
some of the essential concepts encountered when it is the structure of
scientific hypotheses that is being explored: In its explanatory account of the
world, science posits novel entities and properties. Frequently these are
alleged to be not accessible to direct observation. A theory is a set of
hypotheses positing such entities and properties. Some philosophers of science
divide the logical consequences of a theory into those referring only to
observable things and features and those referring to the unobservables as
well. Various reductionist, eliminationist, and instrumentalist approaches to
theory agree that the full cognitive content of a theory is exhausted by its
observational consequences reported by its observation sentences, a claim
denied by those who espouse realist accounts of theories. The view that the
parts of a theory that do not directly relate observational consequences ought
not to be taken as genuinely referential at all, but, rather, as a “mere
linguistic instrument” allowing one to derive observational results from
observationally specifiable posits, is called instrumentalism. From this point
of view terms putatively referring to unobservables fail to have genuine
reference and individual non-observational sentences containing such terms are
not individually genuinely true or false. Verificationism is the general name
for the doctrine that, in one way or another, the semantic content of an
assertion is exhausted by the conditions that count as warranting the
acceptance or rejection of the assertion. There are many versions of
verificationist doctrines that try to do justice both to the empiricist claim that
the content of an assertion is its totality of empirical consequences and also
to a wide variety of anti-reductionist intuitions about meaning. The doctrine
that theoretical sentences must be strictly translatable into sentences
expressed solely in observational terms in order that the theoretical
assertions have genuine cognitive content is sometimes called operationalism.
The “operation” by which a magnitude is determined to have a specified value,
characterized observationally, is taken to give the very meaning of attributing
that magnitude to an object. The doctrine that the meanings of terms in
theories are fixed by the role the terms play in the theory as a whole is often
called semantic holism. According to the semantic holist, definitions of theoretical
terms by appeal to observational terms cannot be given, but all of the
theoretical terms have their meaning given “as a group” by the structure of the
theory as a whole. A related doctrine in confirmation theory is that
confirmation accrues to whole theories, and not to their individual assertions
one at a time. This is confirmational holism. To see another conception of
cognitive content, conjoin all the sentences of a theory together. Then replace
each theoretical term in the sentence so obtained with a predicate variable and
existentially quantify over all the predicate variables so introduced. This is
the Ramsey sentence for a finitely axiomatized theory. This sentence has the
same logical consequences framable in the observational vocabulary alone as did
the original theory. It is often claimed that the Ramsey sentence for a theory
exhausts the cognitive content of the theory. The Ramsey sentence is supposed
to “define” the meaning of the theoretical terms of the original theory as well
as have empirical consequences; yet by asserting the existence of the
theoretical properties, it is sometimes alleged to remain a realist construal
of the theory. The latter claim is made doubtful, however, by the existence of
“merely representational” interpretations of the Ramsey sentence. Theories are
often said to be so related that one theory is reducible to another. The study
of the relation theories bear to one another in this context is said to be the
study of intertheoretic reduction. Such reductive claims can have philosophical
origins, as in the alleged reduction of material objects to sense-data or of
spatiotemporal relations to causal relations, or they can be scientific
discoveries, as in the reduction of the theory of light waves to the theory of
electromagnetic radiation. Numerous “models” of the reductive relation exist,
appropriate for distinct kinds and cases of reduction. The term scientific
realism has many and varied uses. Among other things that have been asserted by
those who describe themselves as scientific realists are the claims that
“mature” scientific theories typically refer to real features of the world,
that the history of past falsifications of accepted scientific theories does
not provide good reason for persistent skepticism as to the truth claims of
contemporary theories, and that the terms of theories that putatively refer to
unobservables ought to be taken at their referential face value and not
reinterpreted in some instrumentalistic manner. Internal realism denies
irrealist claims founded on the past falsification of accepted theories.
Internal realists are, however, skeptical of “metaphysical” claims of
“correspondence of true theories to the real world” or of any notion of truth
that can be construed in radically non-epistemic terms. While theories may
converge to some ultimate “true” theory, the notion of truth here must be
understood in some version of a Peircian idea of truth as “ultimate warranted
assertability.” The claim that any theory that makes reference to posited unobservable
features of the world in its explanatory apparatus will always encounter rival
theories incompatible with the original theory but equally compatible with all
possible observational data that might be taken as confirmatory of the original
theory is the claim of the underdetermination thesis. A generalization taken to
have “lawlike force” is called a law of nature. Some suggested criteria for
generalizations having lawlike force are the ability of the generalization to
back up the truth of claims expressed as counterfactual conditions; the ability
of the generalization to be confirmed inductively on the basis of evidence that
is only a proper subset of all the particular instances falling under the
generality; and the generalization having an appropriate place in the simple,
systematic hierarchy of generalizations important for fundamental scientific
theories of the world. The application of a scientific law to a given actual
situation is usually hedged with the proviso that for the law’s predictions to hold,
“all other, unspecified, features of the situation are normal.” Such a
qualifying clause is called a ceteris paribus clause. Such “everything else
being normal” claims cannot usually be “filled out,” revealing important
problems concerning the “open texture” of scientific claims. The claim that the
full specification of the state of the world at one time is sufficient, along
with the laws of nature, to fix the full state of the world at any other time,
is the claim of determinism. This is not to be confused with claims of total
predictability, since even if determinism were true the full state of the world
at a time might be, in principle, unavailable for knowledge. Concepts of the
foundations of physical theories. Here, finally, are a few concepts that are
crucial in discussing the foundations of physical theories, in particular
theories of space and time and quantum theory: The doctrine that space and time
must be thought of as a family of spatial and temporal relations holding among
the material constituents of the universe is called relationism. Relationists
deny that “space itself” should be considered an additional constituent of the
world over and above the world’s material contents. The doctrine that “space
itself” must be posited as an additional constituent of the world over and
above ordinary material things of the world is substantivalism. Mach’s
principle is the demand that all physical phenomena, including the existence of
inertial forces used by Newton to argue for a substantivalist position, be
explainable in purely relationist terms. Mach speculated that Newton’s
explanation for the forces in terms of acceleration with respect to “space
itself” could be replaced with an explanation resorting to the acceleration of
the test object with respect to the remaining matter of the universe the “fixed
stars”. In quantum theory the claim that certain “conjugate” quantities, such
as position and momentum, cannot be simultaneously “determined” to arbitrary
degrees of accuracy is the uncertainty principle. The issue of whether such a
lack of simultaneous exact “determination” is merely a limitation on our
knowledge of the system or is, instead, a limitation on the system’s having
simultaneous exact values of the conjugate quantities, is a fundamental one in
the interpretation of quantum mechanics. Bell’s theorem is a mathematical
result aimed at showing that the explanation of the statistical correlations
that hold between causally noninteractive systems cannot always rely on the
positing that when the systems did causally interact in the past independent
values were fixed for some feature of each of the two systems that determined
their future observational behavior. The existence of such “local hidden
variables” would contradict the correlational predictions of quantum mechanics.
The result shows that quantum mechanics has a profoundly “non-local” nature.
Can quantum probabilities and correlations be obtained as averages over
variables at some deeper level than those specifying the quantum state of a system?
If such quantities exist they are called hidden variables. Many different types
of hidden variables have been proposed: deterministic, stochastic, local,
non-local, etc. A number of proofs exist to the effect that positing certain
types of hidden variables would force probabilistic results at the quantum
level that contradict the predictions of quantum theory. Complementarity was
the term used by Niels Bohr to describe what he took to be a fundamental
structure of the world revealed by quantum theory. Sometimes it is used to
indicate the fact that magnitudes occur in conjugate pairs subject to the
uncertainty relations. Sometimes it is used more broadly to describe such
aspects as the ability to encompass some phenomena in a wave picture of the
world and other phenomena in a particle picture, but implying that no one
picture will do justice to all the experimental results. The orthodox
formalization of quantum theory posits two distinct ways in which the quantum
state can evolve. When the system is “unobserved,” the state evolves according
to the deterministic Schrödinger equation. When “measured,” however, the system
suffers a discontinuous “collapse of the wave packet” into a new quantum state
determined by the outcome of the measurement process. Understanding how to
reconcile the measurement process with the laws of dynamic evolution of the
system is the measurement problem. Conservation and symmetry. A number of
important physical principles stipulate that some physical quantity is
conserved, i.e. that the quantity of it remains invariant over time. Early
conservation principles were those of matter mass, of energy, and of momentum.
These became assimilated together in the relativistic principle of the
conservation of momentum-energy. Other conservation laws such as the
conservation of baryon number arose in the theory of elementary particles. A
symmetry in physical theory expressed the invariance of some structural feature
of the world under some transformation. Examples are translation and rotation
invariance in space and the invariance under transformation from one uniformly
moving reference frame to another. Such symmetries express the fact that
systems related by symmetry transformations behave alike in their physical
evolution. Some symmetries are connected with space-time, such as those noted
above, whereas others such as the symmetry of electromagnetism under socalled
gauge transformations are not. A very important result of the mathematician
Emma Noether shows that each conservation law is derivable from the existence
of an associated underlying symmetry. Chaos theory and chaotic systems. In the
history of the scientific study of deterministic systems, the paradigm of
explanation has been the prediction of the future states of a system from a
specification of its initial state. In order for such a prediction to be
useful, however, nearby initial states must lead to future states that are
close to one another. This is now known to hold only in exceptional cases. In
general deterministic systems are chaotic systems, i.e., even initial states
very close to one another will lead in short intervals of time to future states
that diverge quickly from one another. Chaos theory has been developed to
provide a wide range of concepts useful for describing the structure of the
dynamics of such chaotic systems. The theory studies the features of a system
that will determine if its evolution is chaotic or non-chaotic and provides the
necessary descriptive categories for characterizing types of chaotic motion.
Randomness. The intuitive distinction between a sequence that is random and one
that is orderly plays a role in the foundations of probability theory and in
the scientific study of dynamical systems. But what is a random sequence?
Subjectivist definitions of randomness focus on the inability of an agent to
determine, on the basis of his knowledge, the future occurrences in the
sequence. Objectivist definitions of randomness seek to characterize it without
reference to the knowledge of any agent. Some approaches to defining objective
randomness are those that require probability to be the same in the original
sequence and in subsequences “mechanically” selectable from it, and those that
define a sequence as random if it passes every “effectively constructible” statistical
test for randomness. Another important attempt to characterize objective
randomness compares the length of a sequence to the length of a computer
program used to generate the sequence. The basic idea is that a sequence is
random if the computer programs needed to generate the sequence are as long as
the sequence itself. H. P. Grice, “My
labour with Scientism.”
Scientism – Grice: “Winch is not only
happy with natural science that he wants a social science – linguistics
included!” -- philosophy of the social sciences, the study of the logic and
methods of the social sciences. Central questions include: What are the
criteria of a good social explanation? How if at all are the social sciences
distinct from the natural sciences? Is there a distinctive method for social
research? Through what empirical procedures are social science assertions to be
evaluated? Are there irreducible social laws? Are there causal relations among
social phenomena? Do social facts and regularities require some form of reduction
to facts about individuals? What is the role of theory in social explanation?
The philosophy of social science aims to provide an interpretation of the
social sciences that answers these questions. The philosophy of social science,
like that of natural science, has both a descriptive and a prescriptive side.
On the one hand, the field is about the social sciences the explanations, methods, empirical
arguments, theories, hypotheses, etc., that actually occur in the social
science literature. This means that the philosopher needs extensive knowledge
of several areas of social science research in order to be able to formulate an
analysis of the social sciences that corresponds appropriately to scientists’
practice. On the other hand, the field is epistemic: it is concerned with the
idea that scientific theories and hypotheses are put forward as true or
probable, and are justified on rational grounds empirical and theoretical. The
philosopher aims to provide a critical evaluation of existing social science methods
and practices insofar as these methods are found to be less truth-enhancing
than they might be. These two aspects of the philosophical enterprise suggest
that philosophy of social science should be construed as a rational
reconstruction of existing social science practice a reconstruction guided by existing practice
but extending beyond that practice by identifying faulty assumptions, forms of
reasoning, and explanatory frameworks. Philosophers have disagreed over the
relation between the social and natural sciences. One position is naturalism,
according to which the methods of the social sciences should correspond closely
to those of the natural sciences. This position is closely related to
physicalism, the doctrine that all higher-level phenomena and regularities including social phenomena are ultimately reducible to physical entities
and the laws that govern them. On the other side is the view that the social
sciences are inherently distinct from the natural sciences. This perspective
holds that social phenomena are metaphysically distinguishable from natural
phenomena because they are intentional
they depend on the meaningful actions of individuals. On this view,
natural phenomena admit of causal explanation, whereas social phenomena require
intentional explanation. The anti-naturalist position also maintains that there
is a corresponding difference between the methods appropriate to natural and
social science. Advocates of the Verstehen method hold that there is a method
of intuitive interpretation of human action that is radically distinct from
methods of inquiry in the natural sciences. One important school within the
philosophy of social science takes its origin in this fact of the
meaningfulness of human action. Interpretive sociology maintains that the goal
of social inquiry is to provide interpretations of human conduct within the
context of culturally specific meaningful arrangements. This approach draws an
analogy between literary texts and social phenomena: both are complex systems
of meaningful elements, and the goal of the interpreter is to provide an
interpretation of the elements that makes sense of them. In this respect social
science involves a hermeneutic inquiry: it requires that the interpreter should
tease out the meanings underlying a particular complex of social behavior, much
as a literary critic pieces together an interpretation of the meaning of a
complex philosophy of the social sciences philosophy of the social sciences
704 704 literary text. An example of
this approach is Weber’s treatment of the relation between capitalism and the
Protestant ethic. Weber attempts to identify the elements of western European
culture that shaped human action in this environment in such a way as to
produce capitalism. On this account, both Calvinism and capitalism are
historically specific complexes of values and meanings, and we can better
understand the emergence of capitalism by seeing how it corresponds to the
meaningful structures of Calvinism. Interpretive sociologists often take the meaningfulness
of social phenomena to imply that social phenomena do not admit of causal
explanation. However, it is possible to accept the idea that social phenomena
derive from the purposive actions of individuals without relinquishing the goal
of providing causal explanations of social phenomena. For it is necessary to
distinguish between the general idea of a causal relation between two events or
conditions and the more specific idea of “causal determination through strict
laws of nature.” It is true that social phenomena rarely derive from strict
laws of nature; wars do not result from antecedent political tensions in the
way that earthquakes result from antecedent conditions in plate tectonics.
However, since non-deterministic causal relations can derive from the choices
of individual persons, it is evident that social phenomena admit of causal
explanation, and in fact much social explanation depends on asserting causal
relations between social events and processes
e.g., the claim that the administrative competence of the state is a
crucial causal factor in determining the success or failure of a revolutionary
movement. A central goal of causal explanation is to discover the conditions
existing prior to the event that, given the law-governed regularities among
phenomena of this sort, were sufficient to produce this event. To say that C is
a cause of E is to assert that the occurrence of C, in the context of a field
of social processes and mechanisms F, brought about E or increased the
likelihood of the occurrence of E. Central to causal arguments in the social
sciences is the idea of a causal mechanism
a series of events or actions leading from cause to effect. Suppose it
is held that the extension of a trolley line from the central city to the
periphery caused the deterioration of public schools in the central city. In
order to make out such a claim it is necessary to provide some account of the
social and political mechanisms that join the antecedent condition to the
consequent. An important variety of causal explanation in social science is
materialist explanation. This type of explanation attempts to explain a social
feature in terms of features of the material environment in the context of
which the social phenomenon occurs. Features of the environment that often
appear in materialist explanations include topography and climate; thus it is
sometimes maintained that banditry thrives in remote regions because the rugged
terrain makes it more difficult for the state to repress bandits. But
materialist explanations may also refer to the material needs of society e.g., the need to produce food and other
consumption goods to support the population. Thus Marx holds that it is the
development of the “productive forces” technology that drives the development
of property relations and political systems. In each case the materialist
explanation must refer to the fact of human agency the fact that human beings are capable of
making deliberative choices on the basis of their wants and beliefs in order to carry out the explanation; in the
banditry example, the explanation depends on the fact that bandits are prudent
enough to realize that their prospects for survival are better in the periphery
than in the core. So materialist explanations too accept the point that social
phenomena depend on the purposive actions of individuals. A central issue in
the philosophy of social science involves the relation between social
regularities and facts about individuals. Methodological individualism is the
position that asserts the primacy of facts about individuals over facts about
social entities. This doctrine takes three forms: a claim about social
entities, a claim about social concepts, and a claim about social regularities.
The first version maintains that social entities are reducible to ensembles of
individuals as an insurance company
might be reduced to the ensemble of employees, supervisors, managers, and
owners whose actions constitute the company. Likewise, it is sometimes held that
social concepts must be reducible to concepts involving only individuals e.g., the concept of a social class might be
defined in terms of concepts pertaining only to individuals and their behavior.
Finally, it is sometimes held that social regularities must be derivable from
regularities of individual behavior. There are several positions opposed to
methodological individualism. At the extreme there is methodological
holism the doctrine that social
entities, facts, and laws are autonomous and irreducible; for example, that
social structures such as the state have dynamic properties independent of the
beliefs and purposes of the particular persons who occupy positions within the
structure. A third position intermediate between these two holds that every
social explanation requires microfoundations
an account of the circumstances at the individual level that led
individuals to behave in such ways as to bring about the observed social
regularities. If we observe that an industrial strike is successful over an
extended period of time, it is not sufficient to explain this circumstance by
referring to the common interest that members of the union have in winning
their demands. Rather, we need information about the circumstances of the
individual union member that induce him or her to contribute to this public
good. The microfoundations dictum does not require, however, that social
explanations be couched in non-social concepts; instead, the circumstances of
individual agents may be characterized in social terms. Central to most
theories of explanation is the idea that explanation depends on general laws
governing the phenomena in question. Thus the discovery of the laws of
electrodynamics permitted the explanation of a variety of electromagnetic
phenomena. But social phenomena derive from the actions of purposive men and
women; so what kinds of regularities are available on the basis of which to
provide social explanations? A fruitful research framework in the social
sciences is the idea that men and women are rational, so it is possible to
explain their behavior as the outcome of a deliberation about means of
achieving their individual ends. This fact in turn gives rise to a set of
regularities about individual behavior that may be used as a ground for social
explanation. We may explain some complex social phenomenon as the aggregate
result of the actions of a large number of individual agents with a
hypothesized set of goals within a structured environment of choice. Social
scientists have often been inclined to offer functional explanations of social
phenomena. A functional explanation of a social feature is one that explains
the presence and persistence of the feature in terms of the beneficial
consequences the feature has for the ongoing working of the social system as a
whole. It might be held, e.g., that sports clubs in working-class Britain exist
because they give working-class people a way of expending energy that would
otherwise go into struggles against an exploitative system, thus undermining
social stability. Sports clubs are explained, then, in terms of their
contribution to social stability. This type of explanation is based on an
analogy between biology and sociology. Biologists explain species traits in
terms of their contribution to reproductive fitness, and sociologists sometimes
explain social traits in terms of their contribution to “social” fitness.
However, the analogy is misleading, because there is a general mechanism
establishing functionality in the biological realm that is not present in the
social realm. This is the mechanism of natural selection, through which a
species arrives at a set of traits that are locally optimal. There is no
analogous process at work in the social realm, however; so it is groundless to
suppose that social traits exist because of their beneficial consequences for
the good of society as a whole or important subsystems within society. So
functional explanations of social phenomena must be buttressed by specific
accounts of the causal processes that underlie the postulated functional
relationships. Grice: “It’s a good thing I studied at Oxford: at other places
you HAVE to learn a non-Indo-Euroopean lingo!” --.
phrastic:
It is convenient to take Grice mocking Hare in Prolegomena. “To say ‘x is good’
is to recommend x.’ An implicaturum: annullable: “x is good but I don’t recommend it.” Hare
was well aware of the implicaturum. Loving Grice’s account of ‘or,’ Hare gives
the example: “Post the letter: therefore; post the letter or burn it.” Grice
mainly quotes Hare’s duet, the phrastic and the neustic, and spends some time
exploring what the phrastic actually is. He seems to prefer ‘radix.’ But then
Hare also has then the ‘neustic,’ that Grice is not so concerned with since he
has his own terminology for it. And for Urmson’s festschrift, Hare comes up
with the tropic and the clistic. So each has a Griceian correlate.
physicalism: One of the twelve labours of
H. P. Grice. (“As different from Naturalism, you know.”) - Churchland, p. s.,
philosopher and advocate of neurophilosophy. She received her B.Phil. from
Oxford in 9 and held positions at the Unichün-tzu Churchland, Patricia Smith
140 140 versity of Manitoba and the
Institute for Advanced Studies at Princeton, settling at the
ofCalifornia,SanDiego, with appointments in philosophy and the Institute for
Neural Computation. Skeptical of philosophy’s a priori specification of mental
categories and dissatisfied with computational psychology’s purely top-down
approach to their function, Churchland began studying the brain at the of Manitoba medical school. The result was a
unique merger of science and philosophy, a “neurophilosophy” that challenged
the prevailing methodology of mind. Thus, in a series of articles that includes
“Fodor on Language Learning” 8 and “A Perspective on Mind-Brain Research” 0,
she outlines a new neurobiologically based paradigm. It subsumes simple
non-linguistic structures and organisms, since the brain is an evolved organ;
but it preserves functionalism, since a cognitive system’s mental states are
explained via high-level neurofunctional theories. It is a strategy of
cooperation between psychology and neuroscience, a “co-evolutionary” process
eloquently described in Neurophilosophy 6 with the prediction that genuine
cognitive phenomena will be reduced, some as conceptualized within the commonsense
framework, others as transformed through the sciences. The same intellectual
confluence is displayed through Churchland’s various collaborations: with
psychologist and computational neurobiologist Terrence Sejnowski in The
Computational Brain 2; with neuroscientist Rodolfo Llinas in The Mind-Brain
Continuum 6; and with philosopher and husband Paul Churchland in On the
Contrary 8 she and Paul Churchland are jointly appraised in R. McCauley, The
Churchlands and Their Critics, 6. From the viewpoint of neurophilosophy,
interdisciplinary cooperation is essential for advancing knowledge, for the
truth lies in the intertheoretic details. Churchland: Paul M. b.2, -born philosopher, leading proponent of eliminative
materialism. He received his Ph.D. from the of Pittsburgh in 9 and held positions at the
Universities of Toronto, Manitoba, and the Institute for Advanced Studies at
Princeton. He is professor of philosophy and member of the Institute for Neural
Computation at the of California, San
Diego. Churchland’s literary corpus constitutes a lucidly written,
scientifically informed narrative where his neurocomputational philosophy
unfolds. Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind 9 maintains that, though
science is best construed realistically, perception is conceptually driven,
with no observational given, while language is holistic, with meaning fixed by
networks of associated usage. Moreover, regarding the structure of science,
higher-level theories should be reduced by, incorporated into, or eliminated in
favor of more basic theories from natural science, and, in the specific case,
commonsense psychology is a largely false empirical theory, to be replaced by a
non-sentential, neuroscientific framework. This skepticism regarding
“sentential” approaches is a common thread, present in earlier papers, and
taken up again in “Eliminative Materialism and the Propositional Attitudes” 1.
When fully developed, the non-sentential, neuroscientific framework takes the
form of connectionist network or parallel distributed processing models. Thus,
with essays in A Neurocomputational Perspective 9, Churchland adds that genuine
psychological processes are sequences of activation patterns over neuronal
networks. Scientific theories, likewise, are learned vectors in the space of
possible activation patterns, with scientific explanation being prototypical
activation of a preferred vector. Classical epistemology, too, should be
neurocomputationally naturalized. Indeed, Churchland suggests a semantic view
whereby synonymy, or the sharing of concepts, is a similarity between patterns
in neuronal state-space. Even moral knowledge is analyzed as stored prototypes
of social reality that are elicited when an individual navigates through other
neurocomputational systems. The entire picture is expressed in The Engine of
Reason, the Seat of the Soul 6 and, with his wife Patricia Churchland, by the
essays in On the Contrary 8. What has emerged is a neurocomputational
embodiment of the naturalist program, a panphilosophy that promises to capture
science, epistemology, language, and morals in one broad sweep of its
connectionist net. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Physicalism and naturalism.”
physicalism: one of the twelve labours of
Grice. in the widest sense of the term, materialism applied to the question of
the nature of mind. So construed, physicalism is the thesis call it ontological physicalism that whatever exists or occurs is ultimately
constituted out of physical entities. But sometimes ‘physicalism’ is used to
refer to the thesis that whatever exists or occurs can be completely described
in the vocabulary of physics. Such a view goes with either reductionism or
eliminativism about the mental. Here reductionism is the view that
psychological explanations, including explanations in terms of
“folk-psychological” concepts such as those of belief and desire, are reducible
to explanations formulable in a physical vocabulary, which in turn would imply
that entities referred to in psychological explanations can be fully described
in physical terms; and elminativism is the view that nothing corresponds to the
terms in psychological explanations, and that the only correct explanations are
in physical terms. The term ‘physicalism’ appears to have originated in the
Vienna Circle, and the reductionist version initially favored there was a
version of behaviorism: psychological statements were held to be translatable
into behavioral statements, mainly hypothetical conditionals, expressible in a
physical vocabulary. The psychophysical identity theory held by Herbert Feigl,
Smart, and others, sometimes called type physicalism, is reductionist in a
somewhat different sense. This holds that mental states and events are
identical with neurophysiological states and events. While it denies that there
can be analytic, meaning-preserving translations of mental statements into
physicalistic ones, it holds that by means of synthetic “bridge laws,”
identifying mental types with physical ones, mental statements can in principle
be tr. into physicalistic ones with which they are at least nomologically
equivalent if the terms in the bridge laws are rigid designators, the
equivalence will be necessary. The possibility of such a translation is
typically denied by functionalist accounts of mind, on the grounds that the
same mental state may have indefinitely many different physical realizations,
and sometimes on the grounds that it is logically possible, even if it never
happens, that mental states should be realized non-physically. In his classic
paper “The ‘mental’ and the ‘physical’ “ 8, Feigl distinguishes two senses of
‘physical’: ‘physical1’ and ‘physical2’. ‘Physical1’ is practically synonymous
with ‘scientific’, applying to whatever is “an essential part of the coherent
and adequate descriptive and explanatory account of the spatiotemporal world.”
‘Physical2’ refers to “the type of concepts and laws which suffice in principle
for the explanation and prediction of inorganic processes.” It would seem that
if Cartesian dualism were true, supposing that possible, then once an
integrated science of the interaction of immaterial souls and material bodies
had been developed, concepts for describing the former would count as
physical1. Construed as an ontological doctrine, physicalism says that whatever
exists or occurs is entirely constituted out of those entities that constitute
inorganic things and processes. Construed as a reductionist or elminativist
thesis about description and explanation, it is the claim that a vocabulary
adequate for describing and explaining inorganic things and processes is
adequate for describing and explaining whatever exists. While the second of
these theses seems to imply the first, the first does not imply the second. It
can be questioned whether the notion of a “full” description of what exists makes
sense. And many ontological physicalists materialists hold that a reduction to
explanations couched in the terminology of physics is impossible, not only in
the case of psychological explanations but also in the case of explanations
couched in the terminology of such special sciences as biology. Their objection
to such reduction is not merely that a purely physical description of e.g.
biological or psychological phenomena would be unwieldy; it is that such
descriptions necessarily miss important laws and generalizations, ones that can
only be formulated in terms of biological, psychological, etc., concepts. If
ontological physicalists materialists are not committed to the reducibility of
psychology to physics, neither are they committed to any sort of identity
theory claiming that entities picked out by mental or psychological
descriptions are identical to entities fully characterizable by physical
descriptions. As already noted, materialists who are functionalists deny that
there are typetype identities between mental entities and physical ones. And
some deny that materialists are even committed to token-token identities,
claiming that any psychological event could have had a different physical
composition and so is not identical to any event individuated in terms of a
purely physical taxonomy. Refs.: H. P.
Grice, “From Physicalism to Naturalism – and Back: fighting two at once!”
physis, Grecian term for nature, primarily
used to refer to the nature or essence of a living thing Aristotle, Metaphysics
V.4. Physis is defined by Aristotle in Physics II.1 as a source of movement and
rest that belongs to something in virtue of itself, and identified by him
primarily with the form, rather than the matter, of the thing. The term is also
used to refer to the natural world as a whole. Physis is often contrasted with
techne, art; in ethics it is also contrasted with nomos, convention, e.g. by
Callicles in Plato’s Gorgias 482e ff., who distinguishes natural from
conventional justice.
physiologicum: Oddly, among the twelve isms that attack Grice on his
ascent to the city of eternal truth, there is Naturalism and Physicalism – but
Roman natura is Grecian physis. In “Some remarks about the senses,” Grice
distinguishes a physicalist identification of the senses (in terms of the
different stimuli and the mechanisms that connects the organs to the brain)
versus other criteria, notably one involving introspection and the nature of
‘experience’ – “providing,” he adds, that ‘seeing’ is an experience! Grice
would use ‘natural,’ relying on the idea that it’s Grecian ‘physis.’ Liddell and Scott
have “φύσις,” from “φύω,” and which they render as “origin.” the natural form
or constitution of a person or thing as the result of growth, and hence nature,
constitution, and nature as an originating power, “φ. λέγεται . . ὅθεν ἡ
κίνησις ἡ πρώτη ἐν ἑκάστῳ τῶν φύσει ὄντων” Arist.Metaph.1014b16; concrete, the
creation, 'Nature.’ Grice is casual in his use of ‘natural’ versus
‘non-natural’ in 1948 for the Oxford Philosophical Society. In later works,
there’s a reference to naturalism, which is more serious. Refs.: The keyword
should be ‘naturalism,’ but also Grice’s diatribes against ‘physicalism,’ and
of course the ‘natural’ and ‘non-natural,’ BANC.
lapis
philosophorum: alchemy:
a quasi-scientific practice and mystical art, mainly ancient and medieval, that
had two broad aims: to change baser metals into gold and to develop the elixir
of life, the means to immortality. Classical Western alchemy probably
originated in Egypt in the first three centuries A.D. with earlier Chin. and
later Islamic and variants and was
practiced in earnest in Europe by such figures as Paracelsus and Newton until
the eighteenth century. Western alchemy addressed concerns of practical
metallurgy, but its philosophical significance derived from an early Grecian
theory of the relations among the basic elements and from a
religious-allegorical understanding of the alchemical transmutation of ores
into gold, an understanding that treats this process as a spiritual ascent from
human toward divine perfection. The purification of crude ores worldly matter
into gold material perfection was thought to require a transmuting agent, the
philosopher’s stone, a mystical substance that, when mixed with alcohol and
swallowed, was believed to produce immortality spiritual perfection. The
alchemical search for the philosopher’s stone, though abortive, resulted in the
development of ultimately useful experimental tools e.g., the steam pump and
methods e.g., distillation.
piaget: philosopher who profoundly
influenced questions, theories, and methods in the study of cognitive
development. The philosophical interpretation and implications of his work,
however, remain controversial. Piaget regarded himself as engaged in genetic
epistemology, the study of what knowledge is through an empirical investigation
of how our epistemic relations to objects are improved. Piaget hypothesized
that our epistemic relations are constructed through the progressive
organization of increasingly complex behavioral interactions with physical
objects. The cognitive system of the adult is neither learned, in the
Skinnerian sense, nor genetically preprogrammed. Rather, it results from the
organization of specific interactions whose character is shaped both by the features
of the objects interacted with a process called accommodation and by the
current cognitive system of the child a process called assimilation. The
tendency toward equilibrium results in a change in the nature of the
interaction as well as in the cognitive system. Of particular importance for
the field of cognitive development were Piaget’s detailed descriptions and
categorizations of changes in the organization of the cognitive system from
birth through adolescence. That work focused on changes in the child’s
understanding of such things as space, time, cause, number, length, weight, and
morality. Among his major works are The Child’s Conception of Number 1, Biology
and Knowledge 7, Genetic Epistemology 0, and Psychology and Epistemology 0.
pico
della mirandola
-- philosopher who wrote a series of 900 theses which he hoped to dispute
publicly in Rome. Thirteen of these theses are criticized by a papal
commission. When Pico defends himself in his “Apologia,” the pope condemns all
900 theses. Pico flees to France, but is imprisoned. On his escape, he returns to
Florence and devotes himself to private study at the swimming-pool at his
villa. He hoped to write a Concord of Plato and Aristotle, but the only part he
was able to complete was “On Being and the One,” – “Blame it on the Toscana!”
-- in which he uses Aquinas and Christianity to reconcile Plato’s and
Aristotle’s views about God’s being and unity. Mirandola is often described as
a syncretist, but in fact he made it clear that the truth of Christianity has
priority over the prisca theologia or ancient wisdom found in the hermetic
corpus and the cabala. Though he was interested in magic and astrology,
Mirandola adopts a guarded attitude toward them in his “Heptaplus,” which
contains a mystical interpretation of Genesis; and in his Disputations Against
Astrology, he rejects them both. The treatise is largely technical, and the
question of human freedom is set aside as not directly relevant. This fact
casts some doubt on the popular thesis that Pico’s philosophy is a celebration
of man’s freedom and dignity. Great weight has been placed on Pico’s “On the
Dignity of Man.” This is a short oration intended as an introduction to the
disputation of his 900 theses – all condemned by the evil pope --, and the title
was suggested by his wife (“She actually suggested, “On the dignity of woman,”
but I found that otiose.””). Mirandola has been interpreted as saying that man
(or woman) is set apart from the rest of creation, and is completely free to
form his (or her) own nature. In fact, as The Heptaplus shows, Pico sees man as
a microcosm containing elements of the angelic, celestial, and elemental
worlds. Man (if not woman) is thus firmly within the hierarchy of nature, and
is a bond and link between the worlds. In the oration, the emphasis on freedom
is a moral one: man is free to choose between good and evil. Grice: “This
irritated Nietzsche so much that he wrote ‘beyond good and evil.’ Refs.: H. P.
Grice, “Goodwill and illwill – must we have both?”
pilgrimage: Grice’s
pilgrimage. In his pilgrimage towards what he calls the city of Eternal Truth
he finds twelve perils – which he lists. The first is Extensionalism (as
opposed to Intensionalism – vide intentum -- consequentes
rem intellectam: intendere est essentialiter ipsum esse intentio ...
quam a concepto sibi adequato: Odint 226; esse intentum est esse non reale: The
second is Nominalism (opposite Realism and Conceptualism – Universalism,
Abstractionism). It is funny that Grice was criticised for representing each of
the perils!The third is Positivism. Opposite to Negativism. Just kidding. Opposite to anything Sir Freddie Ayer was
opposite to!The fourth is Naturalism. Opposite Non-Naturalism. Just joking! But
that’s the hateful word brought by G. E. Moore, whom Grice liked (“Some like
Witters, but Moore’s MY man.”) The fifth is Mechanism. Opposite Libertarianism,
or Finalism, But I guess one likes Libertarianism.The sixth is Phenomenalism.
You cannot oppose it to Physicalism, beause that comes next. So this is G. A.
Paul (“Is there a problem about sense data?). And the opposite is anything this
Scots philosopher was against!The seventh is Reductionism. Opposite
Reductivism. Grice was proud to teach J. M. Rountree the distinction between a
benevolent reductionist and a malignant eliminationist reductionist. The eighth
is physicalism.Opposite metaphysicalism.
The ninth is materialism. Hyleism. Opposite Formalism. Or Immaterialism.
The tenth is Empiricism. Opposite Rationalism. The eleventh is
Scepticism.Opposite Dogmatism.and the twelfth is functionalism. Opposite Grice!
So now let’s order the twelve perils alphabetically. Empiricism.
Extensionalism. Functionalism. MaterialismMechanism. Naturalism. Nominalism.
Phenomenalism. Positivism. Physicalism. Reductionism. Scepticism. Now let us
see how they apply to the theory of the conversational implicaturum and
conversation as rational cooperation. Empiricism – Grice is an avowed
rationalist.Extensionalism – His main concern is that the predicate in the
proposition which is communicated is void, we yield the counterintuitive result
that an emissor who communicates that the S is V, where V is vacuous
communicates the same thing he would be communicating for any other vacuous
predicate V’Functionalism – There is a purely experiential qualia in some
emissor communicating that p that is not covered by the common-or-garden
variety of functionalism. E.g. “I love myself.” Materialism – rationalism means
dealing with a realm of noumena which goes beyond materialismMechanism – rationalism
entails end-setting unweighed finality and freedom. Naturalism – communication
involves optimality which is beyond naturalism Nominalism – a predicate is an
abstractum. Phenomenalism – there is realism which gives priority to the
material thing, not the sense datum. A sense datum of an apple does not nourish
us. Positivism – an emissor may communicate a value, which is not
positivistically reduced to something verifiable. Physicalism – there must be
multiple realization, and many things physicalists say sound ‘harsh’ to Grice’s
ears (“Smith’s brain being in state C doesn’t have adequate evidence”).
Reductionism – We are not eliminating anything. Scepticism – there are dogmas
which are derived from paradigm cases, even sophisticated ones.How to introduce
the twelve entriesEmpiricism – from Greek empereia – cf. etymology for English
‘experience.’Extensionalism -- extensumFunctionalism – functum.
Materialism -- Mechanism Naturalism
Nominalism Phenomenalism Positivism Physicalism Reductionism Scepticism. this section events are reviewed according to
principal scenes of action. Place names appear in the order in which major
incidents occur. City of Destruction. The
city stands as a symbol of the entire world as it is, with all of its sins,
corruptions, and sorrows. No one living there can have any hope of salvation.
Convinced that the city is about to be blasted by the wrath of God, Christian
flees and sets out alone on a pilgrimage which he hopes will lead him to Mount
Zion, to the Celestial City, where he can enjoy eternal life in the happy
company of God and the Heavenly Host. Slough
of Despond. A swamp, a bog, a quagmire, the first obstacle in
Christian's course. Pilgrims are apt to get mired down here by their doubts and
fears. After much difficulty and with some providential help, Christian finally
manages to flounder across the treacherous bog and is on his way again. Village of Morality. Near the village
Christian meets Mr. Worldly Wiseman, who, though not religiously inclined, is a
friendly and well-disposed person. He tells Christian that it would be foolish
of him to continue his pilgrimage, the end of which could only be hunger, pain,
and death. Christian should be a sensible fellow and settle down in the Village
of Morality. It would be a good place to raise a family, for living was cheap
there and they would have honest, well-behaved people as neighbors — people who
lived by the Ten Commandments. More than a little tempted by this, Christian
decides that he should at least have a look at Morality. But along the way he
is stopped by his friend Evangelist, who berates him sharply for having
listened to anything Mr. Worldly Wiseman might have to say. If Christian is
seriously interested in saving his soul, he would be well advised to get back
as quickly as possible on the path to the Wicket Gate which Evangelist had
pointed out to him before. Wicket Gate.
Arriving almost out of breath, Christian reads the sign on the gate:
"Knock and it shall be opened unto you." He knocks a number of times
before arousing the gatekeeper, a "grave person" named Good-will, who
comes out to ask what Christian wants. After the latter has explained his
mission, he is let through the gate, which opens on the Holy Way, a straight
and narrow path leading toward the Celestial City. Christian asks if he can now
be relieved of the heavy burden — a sack filled with his sins and woes — that
he has been carrying on his back for so long. Good-will replies that he cannot
help him, but that if all goes well, Christian will be freed of his burden in
due course. Interpreter's House. On
Good-will's advice, Christian makes his first stop at the large house of
Interpreter, a character symbolizing the Holy Spirit. Interpreter shows his
guest a number of "excellent things." These include a portrait of the
ideal pastor with the Bible in his hand and a crown of gold on his head; a
dusty parlor which is like the human heart before it is cleansed with the
Gospel; a sinner in an iron cage, an apostate doomed to suffer the torments of
Hell through all eternity; a wall with a fire burning against it. A figure (the
Devil himself) is busily throwing water on the fire to put it out. But he would
never succeed, Interpreter explains, because the fire represents the divine
spirit in the human heart and a figure on the far side of the wall keeps the
fire burning brightly by secretly pouring oil on it — "the oil of Christ's
Grace." The Cross. Beyond
Interpreter's House, Christian comes to the Cross, which stands on higher
ground beside the Holy Way. Below it, at the foot of the gentle slope, is an
open sepulcher. When Christian stops by the Cross, the burden on his back
suddenly slips from his shoulders, rolls down the slope, and falls into the
open sepulcher, to be seen no more. As Christian stands weeping with joy, three
Shining Ones (angels) appear. They tell him all his sins are now forgiven, give
him bright new raiment to replace his old ragged clothes, and hand him a
parchment, "a Roll with a seal upon it." For his edification and
instruction, Christian is to read the Roll as he goes along, and when he
reaches the Pearly Gates, he is to present it as his credentials a sort of
passport to Heaven, as it were. Difficulty
Hill. The Holy Way beyond the Cross is fenced in with a high wall on
either side. The walls have been erected to force all aspiring Pilgrims to
enter the Holy Way in the proper manner, through the Wicket Gate. As Christian
is passing along, two men — Formalist and Hypocrisy — climb over the wall and
drop down beside him. Christian finds fault with this and gives the
wall-jumpers a lecture on the dangers of trying shortcuts. They have been
successfully taking shortcuts all their lives, the intruders reply, and all
will go well this time. Not too pleased with his company, Christian proceeds
with Hypocrisy and Formalist to the foot of Difficulty Hill, where three paths
join and they must make a choice. One path goes straight ahead up the steep
slope of the hill; another goes around the base of the hill to the right; the
third, around the hill to the left. Christian argues that the right path is the
one leading straight ahead up Difficulty Hill. Not liking the prospect of much
exertion, Formalist and Hypocrisy decide to take the easier way on the level
paths going around the hill. Both get lost and perish. Halfway up Difficulty
Hill, so steep in places that he has to inch forward on hands and knees,
Christian comes to a pleasant arbor provided for the comfort of weary Pilgrims.
Sitting down to rest, Christian reaches into his blouse and takes out his precious
Roll. While reading it, he drops off to sleep, being awakened when he hears a
voice saying sternly: "Go to the ant, thou sluggard; consider her ways,
and be wise." Jumping up, Christian makes with all speed to the top of the
hill, where he meets two Pilgrims coming toward him — Timorous and Mistrust.
They have been up ahead, they say, and there are lions there. They are giving
up their pilgrimage and returning home, and unsuccessfully try to persuade
Christian to come with them. Their report about the lions disturbs Christian,
who reaches into his blouse to get his Roll so that he may read it and be
comforted. To his consternation, the Roll is not there. Carefully searching
along the way, Christian retraces his steps to the arbor, where, as he recalls,
he had been reading the Roll when he allowed himself to doze off in
"sinful sleep." Not finding his treasure immediately, he sits down
and weeps, considering himself utterly undone by his carelessness in losing
"his pass into the Celestial City." When in deepest despair, he
chances to see something lying half-covered in the grass. It is his precious
Roll, which he tucks away securely in his blouse. Having offered a prayer of
thanks "to God for directing his eye to the place where it lay,"
Christian wearily climbs back to the top of Difficulty Hill. From there he sees
a stately building and as it is getting on toward dark, hastens there. Palace Beautiful. A narrow path leads
off the Holy Way to the lodge in front of Palace Beautiful. Starting up the
path, Christian sees two lions, stops, and turns around as if to retreat. The
porter at the lodge, Watchful, who has been observing him, calls out that there
is nothing to be afraid of if one has faith. The lions are chained, one on
either side of the path, and anyone with faith can pass safely between them if
he keeps carefully to the middle of the path, which Christian does. Arriving at
the lodge, he asks if he can get lodging for the night. The porter, Watchful,
replies that he will find out from those in charge of Palace Beautiful. Soon,
four virgins come out to the lodge, all of them "grave and beautiful
damsels": Discretion, Prudence, Piety, and Charity. Satisfied with
Christian's answers to their questions, they invite him in, introduce him to
the rest of the family, serve him supper, and assign him to a beautiful bedroom
— Peace — for the night. Next morning, the virgins show him the
"rarities" of the place: First, the library, filled with ancient
documents dating back to the beginning of time; next, the armory, packed with
swords, shields, helmets, breastplates, and other things sufficient to equip
all servants of the Lord, even if they were as numerous as the stars in the
sky. Leading their guest to the roof of the palace, the virgins point to
mountains in the distance — the Delectable Mountains, which lie on the way to
the Celestial City. Before allowing Christian to depart, the virgins give him
arms and armor to protect himself during the next stretch of his journey, which
they warn will be dangerous. Valley of
Humiliation. Here Christian is attacked and almost overcome by a
"foul fiend" named Apollyon — a hideous monster with scales like a
fish, wings like a dragon, mouth like a lion, and feet like a bear; flames and
smoke belch out of a hole in his belly. Christian, after a painful struggle,
wounds the fiend with his sword and drives him off. Valley of the Shadow of Death. This is a wilderness, a land of
deserts and pits, inhabited only by yowling hobgoblins and other dreadful
creatures. The path here is very narrow, edged on one side by a deep,
water-filled ditch in which many have drowned; on the other side, by a
treacherous bog. Walking carefully, Christian goes on and soon finds himself
close to the open mouth of Hell, the Burning Pit, out of which comes a cloud of
noxious fumes, long fingers of fire, showers of sparks, and hideous noises.
With flames flickering all around and smoke almost choking him, Christian
manages to get through by use of "All-prayer." Nearing the end of the
valley, he hears a shout raised by someone up ahead: "Though I walk
through the Valley of the Shadow of Death, I will fear none ill, for Thou art
with me." As only a Pilgrim could have raised that cry, Christian hastens
forward to see who it might be. To his surprise and delight he finds that it is
an old friend, Faithful, one of his neighbors in the City of Destruction. Vanity Fair. Happily journeying
together, exchanging stories about their adventures and misadventures, the two
Pilgrims come to the town of Vanity Fair, through which they must pass.
Interested only in commerce and money-making, the town holds a year-round fair
at which all kinds of things are bought and sold — "houses, lands, trades,
titles, . . . lusts, pleasures, . . . bodies, souls, silver, gold, pearls, precious
stones, and what not." Christian and Faithful infuriate the merchandisers
by turning up their noses at the wares offered them, saying that they would buy
nothing but the Truth. Their presence and their attitude cause a hubbub in the
town, which leads the authorities to jail them for disturbing the peace. The
prisoners conduct themselves so well that they win the sympathy of many
townspeople, producing more strife and commotion in the streets, and the
prisoners are held responsible for this, too, though they have done nothing. It
is decided to indict them on the charge of disrupting trade, creating
dissension, and treating with contempt the customs and laws laid down for the
town by its prince, old Beelzebub himself. Brought to trial first, Faithful is
convicted and sentenced to be executed in the manner prescribed by the
presiding judge, Lord Hate-good. The hapless Faithful is scourged, brutally
beaten, lanced with knives, stoned, and then burned to ashes at the stake.
Thus, he becomes another of the Christian martyrs assured of enjoying eternal
bliss up on high. Doubting Castle and
Giant Despair. In a manner only vaguely explained, Christian gets free
and goes on his way — but not alone, for he has been joined by Hopeful, a
native of Vanity Fair who is fleeing in search of better things. After a few
minor adventures, the two reach a sparkling stream, the River of the Water of
Life, which meanders through beautiful meadows bright with flowers. For a time
the Holy Way follows the river bank but then veers off into rougher ground
which is hard on the sore tired feet of the travelers. Wishing there were an
easier way, they plod along until they come to another meadow behind a high
fence. Having climbed the fence to have a look, Christian persuades Hopeful
that they should move over into By-path Meadow, where there is a soft grassy
path paralleling theirs. Moving along, they catch up with Vain-confidence, who
says that he is bound for the Celestial City and knows the way perfectly. Night
comes on, but he continues to push ahead briskly, with Christian and Hopeful
following. Suddenly, the latter hear a frightened cry and a loud thud.
Vain-confidence has been dashed to pieces by falling into a deep pit dug by the
owner of the meadow. Christian and Hopeful retreat, but as they can see nothing
in the dark, they decide to lie down in the meadow to pass the night. Next
morning, they are surprised and seized by the prince of By-path Meadow, a giant
named Despair. Charging them with malicious trespassing, he hauls them to his
stronghold, Doubting Castle, and throws them into a deep dark dungeon, where
they lie for days without food or drink. At length, Giant Despair appears,
beats them almost senseless, and advises them to take their own lives so that
he will not have to come back to finish them off himself. When all seems
hopeless, Christian suddenly brightens up, "as one half amazed," and
exclaims: "What a fool am I, thus to lie in a stinking dungeon when I may
as well walk at liberty. I have a key in my bosom called Promise which will (I
am persuaded) open any lock in Doubting Castle." Finding that the magic
key works, the prisoners are soon out in the open and running as fast as they
can to get back onto the Holy Way, where they erect a sign warning other
Pilgrims against being tempted by the apparent ease of traveling by way of
By-path Meadow. Delectable Mountains. Christian
and Hopeful next come to the Delectable Mountains, where they find gardens,
orchards, vineyards, and fountains of water. Four shepherds — Experience, Knowledge,
Watchful, and Sincere — come to greet them, telling them that the mountains are
the Lord's, as are the flocks of sheep grazing there. Having been escorted
around the mountains and shown the sights there, the two Pilgrims on the eve of
their departure receive from the shepherds a paper instructing them on what to
do and what to avoid on the journey ahead. For one thing, they should not lie
down and sleep in the Enchanted Ground, for that would be fatal. Country of Beulah. This is a happy
land where the sun shines day and night, flowers bloom continuously, and the
sweet and pleasant air is filled with bird-song. There is no lack of grain and
wine. Christian and Hopeful stop to rest and enjoy themselves here, pleased
that the Celestial City is now within sight, which leads them to assume that
the way there is now clear. Dark River.
Proceeding, they are amazed when they come to the Dark River, a wide,
swift-flowing stream. They look around for a bridge or boat on which to cross.
A Shining One appears and tells them that they must make their way across as
best they can, that fording the river is a test of faith, that those with faith
have nothing to fear. Wading into the river, Hopeful finds firm footing, but
Christian does not He is soon floundering in water over his head, fearing that
he will be drowned, that he will never see "the land that flows with milk
and honey." Hopeful helps Christian by holding his head above water, and
the two finally achieve the crossing. Celestial
City. On the far side of the river, two Shining Ones are waiting for the
Pilgrims and take them by the arm to assist them in climbing the steep slope to
the Celestial City, which stands on a "mighty hill . . . higher than the
clouds." Coming to the gate of the city, built all of precious stones,
Christian and Hopeful present their credentials, which are taken to the King
(God). He orders the gate to be opened, and the two weary but elated Pilgrims
go in, to find that the streets are paved with gold and that along them walk
many men with crowns on their heads and golden harps in their hands.
Plantinga: Grice, “A philosopher of
religion – which means he is not possibly good at it! I kid!” – Plantinga’s deas
have determined the direction of debate in many aspects of the discipline. He
has also contributed substantially to analytic epistemology and the metaphysics
of modality. Plantinga is director of the Center for Philosophy of Religion and
John O’Brien (an Irishman) Professor of Philosophy at the of Notre Dame. Plantinga’s philosophy of
religion has centered on the epistemology of religious belief. His God and
Other Minds 7 introduced a defining claim of his career that belief in God may be rational even if it
is not supported by successful arguments from natural theology. This claim was
fully developed in a series of articles published in the 0s, in which he argued
for the position he calls “Reformed Epistemology.” Borrowing from the work of
theologians such as Calvin, Bavinck, and Barth, Plantinga reasoned that
theistic belief is “properly basic,” justified not by other beliefs but by
immediate experience. This position was most thoroughly treated in his article
“Reason and Belief in God” Plantinga and Wolterstorff, eds., Faith and
Rationality, 3. In early work Plantinga assumed an internalist view of
epistemic justification. Later he moved to externalism, arguing that basic
theistic belief would count as knowledge if true and appropriately produced. He
developed this approach in “Justification and Theism” Faith and Philosophy, 7.
These ideas led to the development of a full-scale externalist epistemological
theory, first presented in his 9 Gifford Lectures and later published in the
two-volume set Warrant: The Current Debate and Warrant and Proper Function 3.
This theory has become the focal point of much contemporary debate in analytic
epistemology. Plantinga is also a leading theorist in the metaphysics of
modality. The Nature of Necessity 4 developed a possible worlds semantics that
has become standard in the literature. His analysis of possible worlds as
maximally consistent states of affairs offers a realist compromise between
nominalist and extreme reificationist conceptions. In the last two chapters,
Plantinga brings his modal metaphysics to bear on two classical topics in the
philosophy of religion. He presented what many consider the definitive version
of the free will defense against the argument from evil and a modal version of
the ontological argument that may have produced more response than any version
since Anselm’s original offering.
platonic --: Grice: “At Oxford you HAVE to
be platonic! Aristotelian is jaded!” -- H. P. Grice as a Platonian commentator
– vide his “Metaphysics, Philosophical Eschatology, and Plato’s Republic” --
commentaries on Plato, a term designating the works in the tradition of
commentary hypomnema on Plato that may go back to the Old Academy Crantor is
attested by Proclus to have been the first to have “commented” on the Timaeus.
More probably, the tradition arises in the first century B.C. in Alexandria,
where we find Eudorus commenting, again, on the Timaeus, but possibly also if
the scholars who attribute to him the Anonymous Theaetetus Commentary are
correct on the Theaetetus. It seems also as if the Stoic Posidonius composed a
commentary of some sort on the Timaeus. The commentary form such as we can
observe in the biblical commentaries of Philo of Alexandria owes much to the
Stoic tradition of commentary on Homer, as practiced by the second-century B.C.
School of Pergamum. It was normal to select usually consecutive portions of
text lemmata for general, and then detailed, comment, raising and answering
“problems” aporiai, refuting one’s predecessors, and dealing with points of
both doctrine and philology. By the second century A.D. the tradition of
Platonic commentary was firmly established. We have evidence of commentaries by
the Middle Platonists Gaius, Albinus, Atticus, Numenius, and Cronius, mainly on
the Timaeus, but also on at least parts of the Republic, as well as a work by
Atticus’s pupil Herpocration of Argos, in twentyfour books, on Plato’s work as
a whole. These works are all lost, but in the surviving works of Plutarch we
find exegesis of parts of Plato’s works, such as the creation of the soul in
the Timaeus 35a36d. The Latin commentary of Calcidius fourth century A.D. is
also basically Middle Platonic. In the Neoplatonic period after Plotinus, who
did not indulge in formal commentary, though many of his essays are in fact
informal commentaries, we have evidence of much more comprehensive exegetic
activity. Porphyry initiated the tradition with commentaries on the Phaedo,
commentaries on Plato commentaries on Plato 160 160 Cratylus, Sophist, Philebus, Parmenides
of which the surviving anonymous fragment of commentary is probably a part, and
the Timaeus. He also commented on the myth of Er in the Republic. It seems to
have been Porphyry who is responsible for introducing the allegorical
interpretation of the introductory portions of the dialogues, though it was
only his follower Iamblichus who also commented on all the above dialogues, as
well as the Alcibiades and the Phaedrus who introduced the principle that each
dialogue should have only one central theme, or skopos. The tradition was
carried on in the Athenian School by Syrianus and his pupils Hermeias on the
Phaedrus surviving and Proclus
Alcibiades, Cratylus, Timaeus, Parmenides
all surviving, at least in part, and continued in later times by
Damascius Phaedo, Philebus, Parmenides and Olympiodorus Alcibiades, Phaedo,
Gorgias also surviving, though sometimes
only in the form of pupils’ notes. These commentaries are not now to be valued
primarily as expositions of Plato’s thought though they do contain useful
insights, and much valuable information; they are best regarded as original
philosophical treatises presented in the mode of commentary, as is so much of
later Grecian philosophy, where it is not originality but rather faithfulness
to an inspired master and a great tradition that is being striven for. Platonism Platonism -- Damascius c.462c.550,
Grecian Neoplatonist philosopher, last head of the Athenian Academy before its
closure by Justinian in A.D. 529. Born probably in Damascus, he studied first
in Alexandria, and then moved to Athens shortly before Proclus’s death in 485.
He returned to Alexandria, where he attended the lectures of Ammonius, but came
back again to Athens in around 515, to assume the headship of the Academy.
After the closure, he retired briefly with some other philosophers, including
Simplicius, to Persia, but left after about a year, probably for Syria, where
he died. He composed many works, including a life of his master Isidorus, which
survives in truncated form; commentaries on Aristotle’s Categories, On the
Heavens, and Meteorologics I all lost; commentaries on Plato’s Alcibiades,
Phaedo, Philebus, and Parmenides, which survive; and a surviving treatise On
First Principles. His philosophical system is a further elaboration of the
scholastic Neoplatonism of Proclus, exhibiting a great proliferation of metaphysical
entities. Platonism -- Eudoxus, Grecian
astronomer and mathematician, a student of Plato. He created a test of the
equality of two ratios, invented the method of exhaustion for calculating areas
and volumes within curved boundaries, and introduced an astronomical system
consisting of homocentric celestial spheres. This system views the visible
universe as a set of twenty-seven spheres contained one inside the other and
each concentric to the earth. Every celestial body is located on the equator of
an ideal eudaimonia Eudoxus of Cnidus 291
291 sphere that revolves with uniform speed on its axis. The poles are
embedded in the surface of another sphere, which also revolves uniformly around
an axis inclined at a constant angle to that of the first sphere. In this way
enough spheres are introduced to capture the apparent motions of all heavenly
bodies. Aristotle adopted the system of homocentric spheres and provided a
physical interpretation for it in his cosmology. R.E.B. Euler diagram, a logic
diagram invented by the mathematician Euler that represents standard form
statements in syllogistic logic by two circles and a syllogism by three
circles. In modern adaptations of Euler diagrams, distributed terms are
represented by complete circles and undistributed terms by partial circles
circle segments or circles made with dotted lines: Euler diagrams are more
perspicuous ways of showing validity and invalidity of syllogisms than Venn
diagrams, but less useful as a mechanical test of validity since there may be
several choices of ways to represent a syllogism in Euler diagrams, only one of
which will show that the syllogism is invalid.
Plato: preeminent Grecian philosopher whose chief contribution consists
in his conception of the observable world as an imperfect image of a realm of
unobservable and unchanging “Forms,” and his conception of the best life as one
centered on the love of these divine objects. Life and influences. Born in
Athens to a politically powerful and aristocratic family, Plato came under the
influence of Socrates during his youth and set aside his ambitions for a
political career after Socrates was executed for impiety. His travels in
southern Italy and Sicily brought him into closer contact with the followers of
Pythagoras, whose research in mathematics played an important role in his
intellectual development. He was also acquainted with Cratylus, a follower of
Heraclitus, and was influenced by their doctrine that the world is in constant
flux. He wrote in opposition to the relativism of Protagoras and the purely
materialistic mode of explanation adopted by Democritus. At the urging of a
devoted follower, Dion, he became involved in the politics of Syracuse, the
wealthiest city of the Grecian world, but his efforts to mold the ideas of its tyrant,
Dionysius II, were unmitigated failures. These painful events are described in
Plato’s Letters Epistles, the longest and most important of which is the
Seventh Letter, and although the authenticity of the Letters is a matter of
controversy, there is little doubt that the author was well acquainted with
Plato’s life. After returning from his first visit to Sicily in 387, Plato
established the Academy, a fraternal association devoted to research and
teaching, and named after the sacred site on the outskirts of Athens where it
was located. As a center for political training, it rivaled the school of
Isocrates, which concentrated entirely on rhetoric. The bestknown student of
the Academy was Aristotle, who joined at the age of seventeen when Plato was sixty
and remained for twenty years. Chronology of the works. Plato’s works, many of
which take the form of dialogues between Socrates and several other speakers,
were composed over a period of about fifty years, and this has led scholars to
seek some pattern of philosophical development in them. Increasingly
sophisticated stylometric tests have been devised to calculate the linguistic
similarities among the dialogues. Ancient sources indicate that the Laws was
Plato’s last work, and there is now consensus that many affinities exist
between the style of this work and several others, which can therefore also be
safely regarded as late works; these include the Sophist, Statesman, and
Philebus perhaps written in that order. Stylometric tests also support a rough division
of Plato’s other works into early and middle periods. For example, the Apology,
Charmides, Crito, Euthyphro, Hippias Minor, Ion, Laches, and Protagoras listed
alphabetically are widely thought to be early; while the Phaedo, Symposium,
Republic, and Phaedrus perhaps written in that order are agreed to belong to
his middle period. But in some cases it is difficult or impossible to tell
which of two works belonging to the same general period preceded the other;
this is especially true of the early dialogues. The most controversial
chronological question concerns the Timaeus: stylometric tests often place it
with the later dialogues, though some scholars think that its philosophical
doctrines are discarded in the later dialogues, and they therefore assign it to
Plato’s middle period. The underlying issue is whether he abandoned some of the
main doctrines of this middle period. Early and middle dialogues. The early
dialogues typically portray an encounter between Socrates and an interlocutor
who complacently assumes that he understands a common evaluative concept like
courage, piety, or beauty. For example, Euthyphro, in the dialogue that bears
his name, denies that there is any impiety in prosecuting his father, but
repeated questioning by Socrates shows that he cannot say what single thing all
pious acts have in common by virtue of which they are rightly called pious.
Socrates professes to have no answer to these “What is X?” questions, and this
fits well with the claim he makes in the Apology that his peculiarly human form
of wisdom consists in realizing how little he knows. In these early dialogues,
Socrates seeks but fails to find a philosophically defensible theory that would
ground our use of normative terms. The Meno is similar to these early dialogues it asks what virtue is, and fails to find an
answer but it goes beyond them and marks
a transition in Plato’s thinking. It raises for the first time a question about
methodology: if one does not have knowledge, how is it possible to acquire it
simply by raising the questions Socrates poses in the early dialogues? To show
that it is possible, Plato demonstrates that even a slave ignorant of geometry
can begin to learn the subject through questioning. The dialogue then proposes
an explanation of our ability to learn in this way: the soul acquired knowledge
before it entered the body, and when we learn we are really recollecting what
we once knew and forgot. This bold speculation about the soul and our ability
to learn contrasts with the noncommittal position Socrates takes in the
Apology, where he is undecided whether the dead lose all consciousness or
continue their activities in Hades. The confidence in immortality evident in
the Meno is bolstered by arguments given in the Phaedo, Republic, and Phaedrus.
In these dialogues, Plato uses metaphysical considerations about the nature of
the soul and its ability to learn to support a conception of what the good
human life is. Whereas the Socrates of the early dialogues focuses almost
exclusively on ethical questions and is pessimistic about the extent to which
we can answer them, Plato, beginning with the Meno and continuing throughout
the rest of his career, confidently asserts that we can answer Socratic
questions if we pursue ethical and metaphysical inquiries together. The Forms.
The Phaedo is the first dialogue in which Plato decisively posits the existence
of the abstract objects that he often called “Forms” or “Ideas.” The latter
term should be used with caution, since these objects are not creations of a mind,
but exist independently of thought; the singular Grecian terms Plato often uses
to name these abstract objects are eidos and idea. These Forms are eternal,
changeless, and incorporeal; since they are imperceptible, we can come to have
knowledge of them only through thought. Plato insists that it would be an error
to identify two equal sticks with what Equality itself is, or beautiful bodies
with what Beauty itself is; after all, he says, we might mistakenly take two
equal sticks to be unequal, but we would never suffer from the delusion that
Equality itself is unequal. The unchanging and incorporeal Form is the sort of
object that is presupposed by Socratic inquiry; what every pious act has in
common with every other is that it bears a certain relationship called “participation” to one and the same thing, the Form of Piety.
In this sense, what makes a pious act pious and a pair of equal sticks equal
are the Forms Piety and Equality. When we call sticks equal or acts pious, we
are implicitly appealing to a standard of equality or piety, just as someone
appeals to a standard when she says that a painted portrait of someone is a
man. Of course, the pigment on the canvas is not a man; rather, it is properly
called a man because it bears a certain relationship to a very different sort
of object. In precisely this way, Plato claims that the Forms are what many of
our words refer to, even though they are radically different sorts of objects
from the ones revealed to the senses. For Plato the Forms are not merely an
unusual item to be added to our list of existing objects. Rather, they are a
source of moral and religious inspiration, and their discovery is therefore a
decisive turning point in one’s life. This process is described by a fictional
priestess named Diotima in the Symposium, a dialogue containing a series of
speeches in praise of love and concluding with a remarkable description of the
passionate response Socrates inspired in Alcibiades, his most notorious
admirer. According to Diotima’s account, those who are in love are searching
for something they do not yet understand; whether they realize it or not, they
seek the eternal possession of the good, and they can obtain it only through
productive activity of some sort. Physical love perpetuates the species and
achieves a lower form of immortality, but a more beautiful kind of offspring is
produced by those who govern cities and shape the moral characteristics of
future generations. Best of all is the kind of love that eventually attaches
itself to the Form of Beauty, since this is the most beautiful of all objects
and provides the greatest happiness to the lover. One develops a love for this
Form by ascending through various stages of emotional attachment and
understanding. Beginning with an attraction to the beauty of one person’s body,
one gradually develops an appreciation for the beauty present in all other
beautiful bodies; then one’s recognition of the beauty in people’s souls takes
on increasing strength, and leads to a deeper attachment to the beauty of
customs, laws, and systems of knowledge; and this process of emotional growth
and deepening insight eventually culminates in the discovery of the eternal and
changeless beauty of Beauty itself. Plato’s theory of erotic passion does not
endorse “Platonic love,” if that phrase designates a purely spiritual
relationship completely devoid of physical attraction or expression. What he
insists on is that desires for physical contact be restrained so that they do
not subvert the greater good that can be accomplished in human relationships.
His sexual orientation like that of many of his Athenian contemporaries is
clearly homosexual, and he values the moral growth that can occur when one man
is physically attracted to another, but in Book I of the Laws he condemns
genital activity when it is homosexual, on the ground that such activity should
serve a purely procreative purpose. Plato’s thoughts about love are further
developed in the Phaedrus. The lover’s longing for and physical attraction to
another make him disregard the norms of commonplace and dispassionate human
relationships: love of the right sort is therefore one of four kinds of divine
madness. This fourfold classificatory scheme is then used as a model of proper
methodology. Starting with the Phaedrus, classification what Plato calls the “collection and division
of kinds” becomes the principal method
to be used by philosophers, and this approach is most fully employed in such
late works as the Sophist, Statesman, and Philebus. Presumably it contributed
to Aristotle’s interest in categories and biological classification. The
Republic. The moral and metaphysical theory centered on the Forms is most fully
developed in the Republic, a dialogue that tries to determine whether it is in
one’s own best interests to be a just person. It is commonly assumed that
injustice pays if one can get away with it, and that just behavior merely
serves the interests of others. Plato attempts to show that on the contrary
justice, properly understood, is so great a good that it is worth any
sacrifice. To support this astonishing thesis, he portrays an ideal political
community: there we will see justice writ large, and so we will be better able
to find justice in the individual soul. An ideal city, he argues, must make
radical innovations. It should be ruled by specially trained philosophers,
since their understanding of the Form of the Good will give them greater
insight into everyday affairs. Their education is compared to that of a
prisoner who, having once gazed upon nothing but shadows in the artificial
light of a cave, is released from bondage, leaves the cave, eventually learns
to see the sun, and is thereby equipped to return to the cave and see the
images there for what they are. Everything in the rulers’ lives is designed to
promote their allegiance to the community: they are forbidden private
possessions, their sexual lives are regulated by eugenic considerations, and
they are not to know who their children are. Positions of political power are
open to women, since the physical differences between them and men do not in
all cases deprive them of the intellectual or moral capacities needed for
political office. The works of poets are to be carefully regulated, for the
false moral notions of the traditional poets have had a powerful and
deleterious impact on the general public. Philosophical reflection is to
replace popular poetry as the force that guides moral education. What makes
this city ideally just, according to Plato, is the dedication of each of its
components to one task for which it is naturally suited and specially trained.
The rulers are ideally equipped to rule; the soldiers are best able to enforce
their commands; and the economic class, composed of farmers, craftsmen,
builders, and so on, are content to do their work and to leave the tasks of
making and enforcing the laws to others. Accordingly what makes the soul of a
human being just is the same principle: each of its components must properly
perform its own task. The part of us that is capable of understanding and
reasoning is the part that must rule; the assertive part that makes us capable
of anger and competitive spirit must give our understanding the force it needs;
and our appetites for food and sex must be trained so that they seek only those
objects that reason approves. It is not enough to educate someone’s reason, for
unless the emotions and appetites are properly trained they will overpower it.
Just individuals are those who have fully integrated these elements of the
soul. They do not unthinkingly follow a list of rules; rather, their just
treatment of others flows from their own balanced psychological condition. And
the paradigm of a just person is a philosopher, for reason rules when it
becomes passionately attached to the most intelligible objects there are: the
Forms. It emerges that justice pays because attachment to these supremely
valuable objects is part of what true justice of the soul is. The worth of our
lives depends on the worth of the objects to which we devote ourselves. Those
who think that injustice pays assume that wealth, domination, or the pleasures
of physical appetite are supremely valuable; their mistake lies in their
limited conception of what sorts of objects are worth loving. Late dialogues.
The Republic does not contain Plato’s last thoughts on moral or metaphysical
matters. For example, although he continues to hold in his final work, the
Laws, that the family and private wealth should ideally be abolished, he
describes in great detail a second-best community that retains these and many
other institutions of ordinary political life. The sovereignty of law in such a
state is stressed continually; political offices are to be filled by elections
and lots, and magistrates are subject to careful scrutiny and prosecution.
Power is divided among several councils and offices, and philosophical training
is not a prerequisite for political participation. This second-best state is
still worlds apart from a modern liberal democracy poetic works and many features of private
life are carefully regulated, and atheism is punished with death but it is remarkable that Plato, after having
made no concessions to popular participation in the Republic, devoted so much
energy to finding a proper place for it in his final work. Plato’s thoughts about
metaphysics also continued to evolve, and perhaps the most serious problem in
interpreting his work as a whole is the problem of grasping the direction of
these further developments. One notorious obstacle to understanding his later
metaphysics is presented by the Parmenides, for here we find an unanswered
series of criticisms of the theory of Forms. For example, it is said that if
there is reason to posit one Form of Largeness to select an arbitrary example
then there is an equally good reason to posit an unlimited number of Forms of
this type. The “first” Form of Largeness must exist because according to Plato
whenever a number of things are large, there is a Form of Largeness that makes
them large; but now, the argument continues, if we consider this Form together
with the other large things, we should recognize still another Form, which
makes the large things and Largeness itself large. The argument can be pursued
indefinitely, but it seems absurd that there should be an unlimited number of
Forms of this one type. In antiquity the argument was named the Third Man,
because it claims that in addition to a second type of object called “man” the Form of Man there is even a third. What is Plato’s
response to this and other objections to his theory? He says in the Parmenides
that we must continue to affirm the existence of such objects, for language and
thought require them; but instead of responding directly to the criticisms, he
embarks on a prolonged examination of the concept of unity, reaching apparently
conflicting conclusions about it. Whether these contradictions are merely
apparent and whether this treatment of unity contains a response to the earlier
critique of the Forms are difficult matters of interpretation. But in any case
it is clear that Plato continues to uphold the existence of unchanging
realities; the real difficulty is whether and how he modifies his earlier views
about them. In the Timaeus, there seem to be no modifications at all a fact that has led some scholars to believe,
in spite of some stylometric evidence to the contrary, that this work was
written before Plato composed the critique of the Forms in the Parmenides. This
dialogue presents an account of how a divine but not omnipotent craftsman
transformed the disorderly materials of the universe into a harmonious cosmos
by looking to the unchanging Forms as paradigms and creating, to the best of
his limited abilities, constantly fluctuating images of those paradigms. The
created cosmos is viewed as a single living organism governed by its own
divinely intelligent soul; time itself came into existence with the cosmos,
being an image of the timeless nature of the Forms; space, however, is not
created by the divine craftsman but is the characterless receptacle in which
all change takes place. The basic ingredients of the universe are not earth,
air, fire, and water, as some thinkers held; rather, these elements are
composed of planes, which are in turn made out of elementary triangular shapes.
The Timaeus is an attempt to show that although many other types of objects
besides the Forms must be invoked in order to understand the orderly nature of
the changing universe souls, triangles,
space the best scientific explanations
will portray the physical world as a purposeful and very good approximation to
a perfect pattern inherent in these unchanging and eternal objects. But Forms
do not play as important a role in the Philebus, a late dialogue that contains
Plato’s fullest answer to the question, What is the good? He argues that
neither pleasure not intelligence can by itself be identified with the good,
since no one would be satisfied with a life that contained just one of these
but totally lacked the other. Instead, goodness is identified with proportion,
beauty, and truth; and intelligence is ranked a superior good to pleasure
because of its greater kinship to these three. Here, as in the middle
dialogues, Plato insists that a proper understanding of goodness requires a
metaphysical grounding. To evaluate the role of pleasure in human life, we need
a methodology that applies to all other areas of understanding. More
specifically, we must recognize that everything can be placed in one of four
categories: the limited, the unlimited, the mixture of these two, and the
intelligent creation of this mixture. Where Forms are to be located in this
scheme is unclear. Although metaphysics is invoked to answer practical
questions, as in the Republic, it is not precisely the same metaphysics as
before. Though we naturally think of Plato primarily as a writer of
philosophical works, he regards the written word as inferior to spoken
interchange as an instrument for learning and teaching. The drawbacks inherent
in written composition are most fully set forth in the Phaedrus. There is no
doubt that in the Academy he participated fully in philosophical debate, and on
at least one occasion he lectured to a general audience. We are told by
Aristoxenus, a pupil of Aristotle, that many in Plato’s audience were baffled
and disappointed by a lecture in which he maintained that Good is one. We can
safely assume that in conversation Plato put forward important philosophical
ideas that nonetheless did not find their way into his writings. Aristotle
refers in Physics IV.2 to one of Plato’s doctrines as unwritten, and the
enigmatic positions he ascribes to Plato in Metaphysics I.6 that the Forms are to be explained in terms
of number, which are in turn generated from the One and the dyad of great and
small seem to have been expounded solely
in discussion. Some scholars have put great weight on the statement in the
Seventh Letter that the most fundamental philosophical matters must remain
unwritten, and, using later testimony about Plato’s unwritten doctrines, they
read the dialogues as signs of a more profound but hidden truth. The
authenticity of the Seventh Letter is a disputed question, however. In any
case, since Aristotle himself treats the middle and late dialogues as
undissembling accounts of Plato’s philosophy, we are on firm ground in adopting
the same approach. H. P. Grice, “Commentary on Plato’s Republic,” H. P. Grice,
“Semantics as footnotes to Cratylus.” H. P. Grice, “Plato and Cassirer,
Aristotle and I.”
playgroup: Grice: “Strictly,
a playgroup is institutional – I wouldn’t say that Tom and Jerry form a playgroup
if they played chess together only once!” -- The motivation for the three
playgroups were different. Austin’s first playgroup was for fun. Grice never
attended. Austin’s new playgroup, or ‘second’ playgroup, if you must, was a
sobriquet Grice gave because it was ANYTHING BUT. Grice’s playgroup upon
Austin’s death was for fun, like the ‘first’ playgroup. Since Grice
participated in the second and third, he expanded. The second playgroup was for
‘philosophical hacks’ who needed ‘para-philosophy.’ The third playgroup was for
fun fun. While Austin belonged to the first and the second playgroups, there
were notorious differences. In the first playgroup, he was not the master, and
his resentment towards Ayer can be seen in “Sense and Sensibilia.” The second playgroup
had Austin as the master. It is said that the playgroup survived Austin’s
demise with Grice’s leadership – But Grice’s playgroup was still a different
thing – some complained about the disorderly and rambling nature – Austin had
kept a very tidy organisation and power structure. Since Grice does NOT mention
his own playgroup, it is best to restrict playgroup as an ironic sobriquet by
Grice to anything but a playgroup, conducted after the war by Austin, by
invitation only, to full-time university lecturers in philosophy. Austin would
hold a central position, and Austin’s motivation was to ‘reach’ agreement.
Usually, when agreement was not reached, Austin could be pretty impolite. Grice
found himself IN THE PLAYGROUP. He obviously preferred a friendlier atmosphere,
as his own group later testified. But he was also involved in philosophical
activity OTHER than the play group. Notably his joint endeavours with Strawson,
Warnock, Pears, and Thomson. For some reason he chose each for a specific area:
Warnock for the philosophy of perception (Grice’s implicaturum is that he would
not explore meta-ethics with Warnock – he wouldn’t feel like, nor Warnock
would). Philosophy of action of all things, with J. F. Thomson. Philosophical
psychology with D. F. Pears – so this brings Pears’s observations on intending,
deciding, predicting, to the fore. And ontology with P. F. Strawson. Certainlty
he would not involve with Strawson on endless disagreements about the alleged
divergence or lack thereof between truth-functional devices and their
vernacular counterparts! Grice also mentions collaboration with Austin in
teaching – “an altogether flintier experience,” as Warnock knows and “Grice can
testify.” – There was joint seminars with A. M. Quinton, and a few others. One
may add the tutorials. Some of his tutees left Griceian traces: A. G. N. Flew,
David Bostock, J. L. Ackrill, T. C. Potts. The term was meant ironically. The playgroup
activities smack of military or civil service! while this can be safely called Grice’s
playgroup, it was founded by Austin at All Souls, where it had only seven
members. After the war, Grice joined in. The full list is found elsewhere. With
Austin’s death, Grice felt the responsibility to continue with it, and plus, he
enjoyed it! In alphabetical order. It is this group that made history. J. L. Austin, A. G. N. Flew, P. L. Gardiner,
H. P. Grice, S. N. Hampshire, R. M. Hare, H. L. A. Hart, P. H. Nowell-Smith, G. A. Paul, D. F. Pears,
P. F. Strawson, J. F. Thomson, J. O. Urmson, G. J. Warnock, A. D. Woozley.
Grice distinguishes it very well from Ryle’s group, and the group of
neo-Wittgensteinians. And those three groups were those only involved with
‘ordinary language.’
Plekhanov, Georgy Valentinovich 18568, a
leading theoretician of the Russian revolutionary movement and the father of
Russian Marxism. Exiled from his native Russia for most of his adult life, in 3
he founded in Switzerland the first Russian Marxist association the Emancipation of Labor, a forerunner of
the Russian Social Democratic Workers’ party. In philosophy he sought to
systematize and disseminate the outlook of Marx and Engels, for which he
popularized the name ‘dialectical materialism’. For the most part an orthodox
Marxist in his understanding of history, Plekhanov argued that historical
developments cannot be diverted or accelerated at will; he believed that Russia
was not ready for a proletarian revolution in the first decades of the
twentieth century, and consequently he opposed the Bolshevik faction in the
Plato, commentaries on Plekhanov, Georgy Valentinovich 713 713 split 3 of the Social Democratic party.
At the same time he was not a simplistic economic determinist: he accepted the
role of geographical, psychological, and other non-economic factors in
historical change. In epistemology, Plekhanov agreed with Kant that we cannot
know things in themselves, but he argued that our sensations may be conceived
as “hieroglyphs,” corresponding point by point to the elements of reality
without resembling them. In ethics, too, Plekhanov sought to supplement Marx
with Kant, tempering the class analysis of morality with the view that there
are universally binding ethical principles, such as the principle that human
beings should be treated as ends rather than means. Because in these and other
respects Plekhanov’s version of Marxism conflicted with Lenin’s, his philosophy
was scornfully rejected by doctrinaire Marxist-Leninists during the Stalin
era.
Plotinus, Greco-Roman Neoplatonist
philosopher. Born in Egypt, though doubtless of Grecian ancestry, he studied
Platonic philosophy in Alexandria with Ammonius Saccas 23243; then, after a
brief adventure on the staff of the Emperor Gordian III on an unsuccessful
expedition against the Persians, he came to Rome in 244 and continued teaching
philosophy there until his death. He enjoyed the support of many prominent
people, including even the Emperor Gallienus and his wife. His chief pupils
were Amelius and Porphyry, the latter of whom collected and edited his
philosophical essays, the Enneads so called because arranged by Porphyry in six
groups of nine. The first three groups concern the physical world and our
relation to it, the fourth concerns Soul, the fifth Intelligence, and the sixth
the One. Porphyry’s arrangement is generally followed today, though a
chronological sequence of tractates, which he also provides in his introductory
Life of Plotinus, is perhaps preferable. The most important treatises are I.1;
I.2; I.6; II.4; II.8; III.23; III.6; III.7; IV.34; V.1; V.3; VI.45; VI.7; VI.8;
VI.9; and the group III.8, V.8, V.5, and II.9 a single treatise, split up by
Porphyry, that is a wide-ranging account of Plotinus’s philosophical position,
culminating in an attack on gnosticism. Plotinus saw himself as a faithful
exponent of Plato see especially Enneads V.1, but he is far more than that.
Platonism had developed considerably in the five centuries that separate Plato
from Plotinus, taking on much from both Aristotelianism and Stoicism, and
Plotinus is the heir to this process. He also adds much himself.
pluralism, a philosophical perspective on
the world that emphasizes diversity rather than homogeneity, multiplicity
rather than unity, difference rather than sameness. The philosophical
consequences of pluralism were addressed by Grecian antiquity in its
preoccupation with the problem of the one and the many. The proponents of
pluralism, represented principally by Empedocles, Anaxagoras, and the Atomists
Leucippus and Democritus, maintained that reality was made up of a multiplicity
of entities. Adherence to this doctrine set them in opposition to the monism of
the Eleatic School Parmenides, which taught that reality was an impermeable
unity and an unbroken solidarity. It was thus that pluralism came to be defined
as a philosophical alternative to monism. In the development of Occidental
thought, pluralism came to be contrasted not only with monism but also with
dualism, the philosophical doctrine that there are two, and only two, kinds of
existents. Descartes, with his doctrine of two distinct substances extended non-thinking substance versus
non-extended thinking substance is
commonly regarded as having provided the clearest example of philosophical
dualism. Pluralism thus needs to be understood as marking out philosophical
alternatives to both monism and dualism. Pluralism as a metaphysical doctrine
requires that we distinguish substantival from attributive pluralism.
Substantival pluralism views the world as containing a multiplicity of
substances that remain irreducible to each other. Attributive pluralism finds
the multiplicity of kinds not among the furniture of substances that make up
the world but rather among a diversity of attributes and distinguishing
properties. However, pluralism came to be defined not only as a metaphysical
doctrine but also as a regulative principle of explanation that calls upon
differing explanatory principles and conceptual schemes to account for the
manifold events of nature and the varieties of human experience. Recent
philosophical thought has witnessed a resurgence of interest in pluralism. This
was evident in the development of
pragmatism, where pluralism received piquant expression in James’s A
Pluralistic Universe 9. More recently pluralism was given a voice in the
thought of the later Vitters, with its heavy accent on the plurality of
language games displayed in our ordinary discourse. Also, in the current
developments of philosophical postmodernism Jean-François Lyotard, one finds an
explicit pluralistic orientation. Here the emphasis falls on the multiplicity
of signifiers, phrase regimens, genres of discourse, and narrational
strategies. The alleged unities and totalities of thought, discourse, and
action are subverted in the interests of reclaiming the diversified and
heterogeneous world of human experience. Pluralism in contemporary thought
initiates a move into a postmetaphysical age. It is less concerned with
traditional metaphysical and epistemological issues, seeking answers to
questions about the nature and kinds of substances and attributes; and it is
more attuned to the diversity of social practices and the multiple roles of
language, discourse, and narrative in the panoply of human affairs.
pluralitive logic, also called pleonetetic
logic, the logic of ‘many’, ‘most’, ‘few’, and similar terms including ‘four
out of five’, ‘over 45 percent’ and so on. Consider 1 ‘Almost all F are G’ 2
‘Almost all F are not G’ 3 ‘Most F are G’ 4 ‘Most F are not G’ 5 ‘Many F are G’
6 ‘Many F are not G’ 1 i.e., ‘Few F are not G’ and 6 are contradictory, as are
2 and 5 and 3 and 4. 1 and 2 cannot be true together i.e., they are contraries,
nor can 3 and 4, while 5 and 6 cannot be false together i.e., they are
subcontraries. Moreover, 1 entails 3 which entails 5, and 2 entails 4 which
entails 6. Thus 16 form a generalized “square of opposition” fitting inside the
standard one. Sometimes 3 is said to be true if more than half the F’s are G,
but this makes ‘most’ unnecessarily precise, for ‘most’ does not literally mean
‘more than half’. Although many pluralitive terms are vague, their
interrelations are logically precise. Again, one might define ‘many’ as ‘There
are at least n’, for some fixed n, at least relative to context. But this not
only erodes the vagueness, it also fails to work for arbitrarily large and
infinite domains. ‘Few’, ‘most’, and ‘many’ are binary quantifiers, a type of
generalized quantifier. A unary quantifier, such as the standard quantifiers
‘some’ and ‘all’, connotes a second-level property, e.g., ‘Something is F’
means ‘F has an instance’, and ‘All F’s are G’ means ‘F and not G has no
instance’. A generalized quantifier connotes a second-level relation. ‘Most F’s
are G’ connotes a binary relation between F and G, one that cannot be reduced
to any property of a truth-functional compound of F and G. In fact, none of the
standard pluralitive terms can be defined in first-order logic.
plurality of causes, as used by J. S.
Mill, more than one cause of a single effect; i.e., tokens of different event
types causing different tokens of the same event type. Plurality of causes is
distinct from overdetermination of an event by more than one actual or
potential token cause. For example, an animal’s death has a plurality of
causes: it may die of starvation, of bleeding, of a blow to the head, and so
on. Mill thought these cases were important because he saw that the existence
of a plurality of causes creates problems for his four methods for determining
causes. Mill’s method of agreement is specifically vulnerable to the problem:
the method fails to reveal the cause of an event when the event has more than
one type of cause, because the method presumes that causes are necessary for
their effects. Actually, plurality of causes is a commonplace fact about the
world because very few causes are necessary for their effects. Unless the
background conditions are specified in great detail, or the identity of the
effect type is defined very narrowly, almost all cases involve a plurality of
causes. For example, flipping the light switch is a necessary cause of the
light’s going on, only if one assumes that there will be no short circuit
across the switch, that the wiring will remain as it is, and so on, or if one
assumes that by ‘the light’s going on’ one means the light’s going on in the
normal way.
Po-hu tung “White Tiger Hall
Consultations”, an important Chin. Confucian work of the later Han dynasty,
resulting from discussions at the imperial palace in A.D. 79 on the classics
and their commentaries. Divided into forty-three headings, the text sums up the
dominant teachings of Confucianism by affirming the absolute position of the
monarch, a cosmology and moral psychology based on the yinyang theory, and a
comprehensive social and political philosophy. While emphasizing benevolent
government, it legitimizes the right of the ruler to use force to quell
disorder. A system of “three bonds and six relationships” defines the
hierarchical structure of society. Human nature, identified with the yang
cosmic force, must be cultivated, while feelings yin are to be controlled
especially by rituals and education. The Confucian orthodoxy affirmed also
marks an end to the debate between the Old Text school and the New Text school
that divided earlier Han scholars.
poiesis Grecian, ‘production’, behavior
aimed at an external end. In Aristotle, poiesis is opposed to praxis action. It
is characteristic of crafts e.g.
building, the end of which is houses. It is thus a kinesis process. For
Aristotle, exercising the virtues, since it must be undertaken for its own
sake, cannot be poiesis. The knowledge involved in virtue is therefore not the
same as that involved in crafts. R.C.
Poincaré: j. h., philosopher of science.
Born into a prominent family in Nancy, he showed extraordinary talent in
mathematics from an early age. He studied at the École des Mines and worked as
a mining engineer while completing his doctorate in mathematics 1879. In 1, he
was appointed professor at the of Paris,
where he lectured on mathematics, physics, and astronomy until his death. His
original contributions to the theory of differential equations, algebraic
topology, and number theory made him the leading mathematician of his day. He
published almost five hundred technical papers as well as three widely read
books on the philosophy of science: Science and Hypothesis 2, The Value of
Science 5, and Science and Method 8. Poincaré’s philosophy of science was
shaped by his approach to mathematics. Geometric axioms are neither synthetic a
priori nor empirical; they are more properly understood as definitions. Thus,
when one set of axioms is preferred over another for use in physics, the choice
is a matter of “convention”; it is governed by criteria of simplicity and
economy of expression rather than by which geometry is “correct.” Though
Euclidean geometry is used to describe the motions of bodies in space, it makes
no sense to ask whether physical space “really” is Euclidean. Discovery in
mathematics resembles discovery in the physical sciences, but whereas the
former is a construction of the human mind, the latter has to be fitted to an
order of nature that is ultimately independent of mind. Science provides an
economic and fruitful way of expressing the relationships between classes of
sensations, enabling reliable predictions to be made. These sensations reflect
the world that causes them; the limited objectivity of science derives from
this fact, but science does not purport to determine the nature of that
underlying world. Conventions, choices that are not determinable by rule, enter
into the physical sciences at all levels. Such principles as that of the
conservation of energy may appear to be empirical, but are in fact postulates
that scientists have chosen to treat as implicit definitions. The decision
between alternative hypotheses also involves an element of convention: the
choice of a particular curve to represent a finite set of data points, e.g.,
requires a judgment as to which is simpler. Two kinds of hypotheses, in
particular, must be distinguished. Inductive generalizations from observation
“real generalizations” are hypothetical in the limited sense that they are
always capable of further precision. Then there are theories “indifferent
hypotheses” that postulate underlying entities or structures. These entities
may seem explanatory, but strictly speaking are no more than devices useful in
calculation. For atomic theory to explain, atoms would have to exist. But this
cannot be established in the only way permissible for a scientific claim, i.e.
directly by experiment. Shortly before he died, Poincaré finally allowed that
Perrin’s experimental verification of Einstein’s predictions regarding Brownian
motion, plus his careful marshaling of twelve other distinct experimental
methods of calculating Avogadro’s number, constituted the equivalent of an experimental
proof of the existence of atoms: “One can say that we see them because we can
count them. . . . The atom of the chemist is now a reality.”
polarity, the relation between distinct
phenomena, terms, or concepts such that each inextricably requires, though it
is opposed to, the other, as in the relation between the north and south poles
of a magnet. In application to terms or concepts, polarity entails that the
meaning of one involves the meaning of the other. This is conceptual polarity.
Terms are existentially polar provided an instance of one cannot exist unless
there exists an instance of the other. The second sense implies the first.
Supply and demand and good and evil are instances of conceptual polarity. North
and south and buying and selling are instances of existential polarity. Some
polar concepts are opposites, such as truth and falsity. Some are correlative,
such as question and answer: an answer is always an answer to a question; a
question calls for an answer, but a question can be an answer, and an answer
can be a question. The concept is not restricted to pairs and can be extended
to generate mutual interdependence, multipolarity.
Polish logic, logic as researched,
elucidated, and taught in Poland, 939. Between the two wars colleagues Jan
Lukasiewicz, Tadeusz Kotarbigki, and Stanislaw Lesniewski, assisted by
students-become-collaborators such as Alfred Tarski, Jerzy Slupecki, Stanislaw
Jaskowski, and Boleslaw Sobocigski, together with mathematicians in Warsaw and
philosophical colleagues elsewhere, like Kasimir Ajdukiewicz and Tadeusz
Czezowski, made Warsaw an internationally known center of research in logic,
metalogic, semantics, and foundations of mathematics. The Warsaw “school” also
dominated Polish philosophy, and made Poland the country that introduced modern
logic even in secondary schools. All three founders took their doctorates in
Lvov under Kasimir Twardowski 18668, mentor of leading thinkers of independent
Poland between the wars. Arriving from Vienna to take the chair of philosophy
at twenty-nine, Twardowski had to choose between concentrating on his own
research and organizing the study of philosophy in Poland. Dedicating his life
primarily to the community task, he became the founder of modern Polish
philosophy. Twardowski’s informal distinction between distributive and
collective conceptions influenced classification of philosophy and the
sciences, and anticipated Lesniewski’s formal axiomatizations in ontology and
mereology, respectively. Another common inheritance important in Polish logic
was Twardowski’s stress on the processproduct ambiguity. He applied this
distinction to disambiguate ‘meaning’ and refine his teacher Brentano’s account
of mental acts as meaningful “intentional” events, by differentiating 1 what is
meant or “intended” by the act, its objective noema or noematic “intentional
object,” from 2 its corresponding noetic meaning or subjective “content,” the
correlated characteristic or structure by which it “intends” its “object” or
“objective” i.e., means that:
suchand-such is so. Twardowski’s teaching
especially this careful analysis of “contents” and “objects” of mental
acts contributed to Meinong’s theory of
objects, and linked it, Husserl’s phenomenology, and Anton Marty’s
“philosophical grammar” with the “descriptive psychology” of their common
teacher, the Aristotelian and Scholastic empiricist Brentano, and thus with
sources of the analytic movements in Vienna and Cambridge. Twardowski’s
lectures on the philosophical logic of content and judgment prepared the ground
for scientific semantics; his references to Boolean algebra opened the door to
mathematical logic; and his phenomenological idea of a general theory of
objects pointed toward Lesniewski’s ontology. Twardowski’s maieutic character,
integrity, grounding in philosophical traditions, and arduous training lectures
began at six a.m., together with his realist defense of the classical
Aristotelian correspondence theory of truth against “irrationalism,” dogmatism,
skepticism, and psychologism, influenced his many pupils, who became leaders of
Polish thought in diverse fields. But more influential than any doctrine was
his rigorist ideal of philosophy as a strict scientific discipline of criticism
and logical analysis, precise definition, and conceptual clarification. His was
a school not of doctrine but of method. Maintaining this common methodological
inheritance in their divergent ways, and encouraged to learn more mathematical
logic than Twardowski himself knew, his students in logic were early influenced
by Frege’s and Husserl’s critique of psychologism in logic, Husserl’s logical
investigations, and the logical reconstruction of classical mathematics by
Frege, Schröder, Whitehead, and Russell. As lecturer in Lvov from 8 until his
appointment to Warsaw in 5, Lukasiewicz introduced mathematical logic into
Poland. To Lesniewski, newly arrived from studies in G.y as an enthusiast for
Marty’s philosophy of language, Lukasiewicz’s influential 0 Critique of
Aristotle’s principle of contradiction was a “revelation” in 1. Among other
things it revealed paradoxes like Russell’s, which preoccupied him for the next
eleven years as, logically refuting Twardowski’s Platonist theory of
abstraction, he worked out his own solutions and, influenced also by Leon Chwistek,
outgrew the influence of Hans Cornelius and Leon Petraz´ycki, and developed his
own “constructively nominalist” foundations. In 9 Kotarbisski and Lesniewski
joined Lukasiewicz in Warsaw, where they attracted students like Tarski,
Sobocigski, and Slupecki in the first generation, and Andrzej Mostowski and
Czeslaw Lejewski in the next. When the war came, the survivors were scattered
and the metalogicians Morchaj Wajsberg, Moritz Presburger, and Adolf Lindenbaum
were killed or “disappeared” by the Gestapo. Lukasiewicz concentrated
increasingly on history of logic especially in reconstructing the logic of
Aristotle and the Stoics and deductive problems concerning syllogistic and
propositional logic. His idea of logical probability and development of three-
or manyvalued and modal calculi reflected his indeterminist sympathies in
prewar exchanges with Kotarbigski and Lesniewski on the status of truths
eternal, sempiternal, or both?, especially as concerns future contingencies.
Lesniewski concentrated on developing his logical systems. He left elaboration
of many of his seminal metalogical and semantic insights to Tarski, who,
despite a divergent inclination to simplify metamathematical deductions by
expedient postulation, shared with Lesniewski, Lukasiewicz, and Ajdukiewicz the
conviction that only formalized languages can be made logically consistent
subjects and instruments of rigorous scientific investigation. Kotarbigski drew
on Lesniewski’s logic of predication to defend his “reism” as one possible application
of Lesniewski’s ontology, to facilitate his “concretist” program for
translating abstractions into more concrete terms, and to rationalize his
“imitationist” account of mental acts or dispositions. Inheriting Twardowski’s
role as cultural leader and educator, Kotarbigski popularized the logical
achievements of his colleagues in e.g. his substantial 9 treatise on the theory
of knowledge, formal logic, and scientific methodology; this work became
required reading for serious students and, together with the lucid textbooks by
Lukasiewicz and Ajdukiewicz, raised the level of philosophical discussion in
Poland. Jaskowski published a system of “natural deduction” by the
suppositional method practiced by Lesniewski since 6. Ajdukiewicz based his
syntax on Lesniewski’s logical grammar, and by his searching critiques
influenced Kotarbigski’s “reist” and “concretist” formulations. Closest in
Poland to the logical positivists of the Vienna Circle, Ajdukiewicz brought new
sophistication to the philosophy of language and of science by his examination
of the role of conventions and meaning postulates in scientific theory and
language, distinguishing axiomatic, deductive, and empirical rules of meaning.
His evolving and refined conventionalist analyses of theories, languages,
“world perspectives,” synonymy, translation, and analyticity, and his
philosophical clarification by paraphrase anticipated views of Carnap, Feigl,
and Quine. But the Polish thinkers, beyond their common methodological
inheritance and general adherence to extensional logic, subscribed to little
common doctrine, and in their exchanges with the Vienna positivists remained
“too sober” said Lukasiewicz to join in sweeping antimetaphysical manifestos.
Like Twardowski, they were critics of traditional formulations, who sought not
to proscribe but to reform metaphysics, by reformulating issues clearly enough
to advance understanding. Indeed, except for Chwistek, the mathematician Jan
Slezygski, and the historians I. M. Bochegski, Z. A. Jordan, and Jan Salamucha,
in addition to the phenomenologist Roman Ingarden, the key figures in Polish
logic were all philosophical descendants of Twardowski.
political philosophy, the study of the
nature and justification of coercive institutions. Coercive institutions range
in size from the family to the nation-state and world organizations like the
United Nations. They are institutions that at least sometimes employ force or
the threat of force to control the behavior of their members. Justifying such
coercive institutions requires showing that the authorities within them have a
right to be obeyed and that their members have a corresponding obligation to
obey them, i.e., that these institutions have legitimate political authority
over their members. Classical political philosophers, like Plato and Aristotle,
were primarily interested in providing a justification for city-states like
Athens or Sparta. But historically, as larger coercive institutions became
possible and desirable, political philosophers sought to justify them. After
the seventeenth century, most political philosophers focused on providing a
justification for nationstates whose claim to legitimate authority is
restricted by both geography and nationality. But from time to time, and more
frequently in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, some political
philosophers have sought to provide a justification for various forms of world
government with even more extensive powers than those presently exercised by
the United Nations. And quite recently, feminist political philosophers have
raised important challenges to the authority of the family as it is presently
constituted. Anarchism from Grecian an archos, ‘no government’ rejects this
central task of political philosophy. It maintains that no coercive institutions
are justified. Proudhon, the first self-described anarchist, believed that
coercive institutions should be replaced by social and economic organizations
based on voluntary contractual agreement, and he advocated peaceful change
toward anarchism. Others, notably Blanqui and Bakunin, advocated the use of
violence to destroy the power of coercive institutions. Anarchism inspired the
anarcho-syndicalist movement, Makhno and his followers during the Russian Civil
War, the anarchists during the Civil War, and the anarchist gauchistes
during the 8 “May Events” in France. Most political philosophers, however, have
sought to justify coercive institutions; they have simply disagreed over what
sort of coercive institutions are justified. Liberalism, which derives from the
work of Locke, is the view that coercive institutions are justified when they
promote liberty. For Locke, liberty requires a constitutional monarchy with
parliamentary government. Over time, however, the ideal of liberty became
subject to at least two interpretations. The view that seems closest to Locke’s
is classical liberalism, which is now more frequently called political
libertarianism. This form of liberalism interprets constraints on liberty as
positive acts i.e., acts of commission that prevent people from doing what they
otherwise could do. According to this view, failing to help people in need does
not restrict their liberty. Libertarians maintain that when liberty is so
interpreted only a minimal or night-watchman state that protects against force,
theft, and fraud can be justified. In contrast, in welfare liberalism, a form
of liberalism that derives from the work of T. H. Green, constraints on liberty
are interpreted to include, in addition, negative acts i.e., acts of omission
that prevent people from doing what they otherwise could do. According to this
view, failing to help people in need does restrict their liberty. Welfare
liberals maintain that when liberty is interpreted in this fashion, coercive
institutions of a welfare state requiring a guaranteed social minimum and equal
opportunity are justified. While no one denies that when liberty is given a
welfare liberal interpretation some form of welfare state is required, there is
considerable debate over whether a minimal state is required when liberty is
given a libertarian interpretation. At issue is whether the liberty of the poor
is constrained when they are prevented from taking from the surplus possessions
of the rich what they need for survival. If such prevention does constrain the
liberty of the poor, it could be argued that their liberty should have priority
over the liberty of the rich not to be interfered with when using their surplus
possessions for luxury purposes. In this way, it could be shown that even when
the ideal of liberty is given a libertarian interpretation, a welfare state,
rather than a minimal state, is justified. Both libertarianism and welfare
liberalism are committed to individualism. This view takes the rights of
individuals to be basic and justifies the actions of coercive institutions as
promoting those rights. Communitarianism, which derives from the writings of
Hegel, rejects individualism. It maintains that rights of individuals are not
basic and that the collective can have rights that are independent of and even
opposed to what liberals claim are the rights of individuals. According to
communitarians, individuals are constituted by the institutions and practices
of which they are a part, and their rights and obligations derive from those
same institutions and practices. Fascism is an extreme form of communitarianism
that advocates an authoritarian state with limited rights for individuals. In
its National Socialism Nazi variety, fascism was also antiSemitic and
militarist. In contrast to liberalism and communitarianism, socialism takes
equality to be the basic ideal and justifies coercive institutions insofar as
they promote equality. In capitalist societies where the means of production
are owned and controlled by a relatively small number of people and used
primarily for their benefit, socialists favor taking control of the means of
production and redirecting their use to the general welfare. According to Marx,
the principle of distribution for a socialist society is: from each according
to ability, to each according to needs. Socialists disagree among themselves,
however, over who should control the means of production in a socialist
society. In the version of socialism favored by Lenin, those who control the
means of production are to be an elite seemingly differing only in their ends
from the capitalist elite they replaced. In other forms of socialism, the means
of production are to be controlled democratically. In advanced capitalist
societies, national defense, police and fire protection, income redistribution,
and environmental protection are already under democratic control. Democracy or
“government by the people” is thought to apply in these areas, and to require
some form of representation. Socialists simply propose to extend the domain of
democratic control to include control of the means of production, on the ground
that the very same arguments that support democratic control in these
recognized areas also support democratic control of the means of production. In
addition, according to Marx, socialism will transform itself into communism
when most of the work that people perform in society becomes its own reward,
making differential monetary reward generally unnecessary. Then distribution in
society can proceed according to the principle, from each according to ability,
to each according to needs. It so happens that all of the above political views
have been interpreted in ways that deny that women have the same basic rights
as men. By contrast, feminism, almost by definition, is the political view that
women and men have the same basic rights. In recent years, most political
philosophers have come to endorse equal basic rights for women and men, but
rarely do they address questions that feminists consider of the utmost
importance, e.g., how responsibilities and duties are to be assigned in family
structures. Each of these political views must be evaluated both internally and
externally by comparison with the other views. Once this is done, their
practical recommendations may not be so different. For example, if welfare
liberals recognize that the basic rights of their view extend to distant
peoples and future generations, they may end up endorsing the same degree of
equality socialists defend. Whatever their practical requirements, each of
these political views justifies civil disobedience, even revolution, when
certain of those requirements have not been met. Civil disobedience is an
illegal action undertaken to draw attention to a failure by the relevant
authorities to meet basic moral requirements, e.g., the refusal of Rosa Parks
to give up her seat in a bus to a white man in accord with the local ordinance
in Montgomery, Alabama, in 5. Civil disobedience is justified when illegal
action of this sort is the best way to get the relevant authorities to bring
the law into better correspondence with basic moral requirements. By contrast,
revolutionary action is justified when it is the only way to correct a radical
failure of the relevant authorities to meet basic moral requirements. When
revolutionary action is justified, people no longer have a political obligation
to obey the relevant authorities; that is, they are no longer morally required
to obey them, although they may still continue to do so, e.g. out of habit or
fear. Recent contemporary political philosophy has focused on the
communitarianliberal debate. In defense of the communitarian view, Alasdair
MacIntyre has argued that virtually all forms of liberalism attempt to separate
rules defining right action from conceptions of the human good. On this
account, he contends, these forms of liberalism must fail because the rules
defining right action cannot be adequately grounded apart from a conception of
the good. Responding to this type of criticism, some liberals have openly
conceded that their view is not grounded independently of some conception of
the good. Rawls, e.g., has recently made clear that his liberalism requires a
conception of the political good, although not a comprehensive conception of
the good. It would seem, therefore, that the debate between communitarians and
liberals must turn on a comparative evaluation of their competing conceptions
of the good. Unfortunately, contemporary communitarians have not yet been very
forthcoming about what particular conception of the good their view
requires.
political theory, reflection concerning
the empirical, normative, and conceptual dimensions of political life. There
are no topics that all political theorists do or ought to address, no required
procedures, no doctrines acknowledged to be authoritative. The meaning of
‘political theory’ resides in its fluctuating uses, not in any essential
property. It is nevertheless possible to identify concerted tendencies among
those who have practiced this activity over twenty-five centuries. Since approximately
the seventeenth century, a primary question has been how best to justify the
political rule of some people over others. This question subordinated the issue
that had directed and organized most previous political theory, namely, what
constitutes the best form of political regime. Assuming political association
to be a divinely ordained or naturally necessary feature of the human estate,
earlier thinkers had asked what mode of political association contributes most
to realizing the good for humankind. Signaling the variable but intimate
relationship between political theory and political practice, the change in
question reflected and helped to consolidate acceptance of the postulate of
natural human equality, the denial of divinely or naturally given authority of
some human beings over others. Only a small minority of postseventeenth-century
thinkers have entertained the possibility, perhaps suggested by this postulate,
that no form of rule can be justified, but the shift in question altered the political
theory agenda. Issues concerning consent, individual liberties and rights,
various forms of equality as integral to justice, democratic and other controls
on the authority and power of government
none of which were among the first concerns of ancient or medieval
political thinkers moved to the center
of political theory. Recurrent tendencies and tensions in political theory may
also be discerned along dimensions that cross-cut historical divisions. In its
most celebrated representations, political theory is integral to philosophy.
Systematic thinkers such as Plato and Aristotle, Augustine and Aquinas, Hobbes
and Hegel, present their political thoughts as supporting and supported by
their ethics and theology, metaphysics and epistemology. Political argumentation
must satisfy the same criteria of logic, truth, and justification as any other;
a political doctrine must be grounded in the nature of reality. Other political
theorists align themselves with empirical science rather than philosophy. Often
focusing on questions of power, they aim to give accurate accounts and
factually grounded assessments of government and politics in particular times
and places. Books IVVI of Aristotle’s Politics inaugurate this conception of
political theory; it is represented by Montesquieu, Marx, and much of
utilitarianism, and it is the numerically predominant form of academic
political theorizing in the twentieth century. Yet others, e.g., Socrates,
Machiavelli, Rousseau, and twentieth-century thinkers such as Rawls, mix the
previously mentioned modes but understand themselves as primarily pursuing the
practical objective of improving their own political societies.
polysyllogism, a series of syllogisms
connected by the fact that the conclusion of one syllogism becomes a premise of
another. The syllogism whose conclusion is used as a premise in another
syllogism within the chain is called the prosyllogism; the syllogism is which
the conclusion of another syllogism within the chain is used as a premise is
called the episyllogism. To illustrate, take the standard form of the simplest
polysyllogism: a 1 Every B is A 2 Every C is B 3 , Every C is A b 4 Every C is
A 5 Every D is C 6 , Every D is A. The first member a of this polysyllogism is
the prosyllogism, since its conclusion, 3, occurs as a premise, 4, in the
second argument. This second member, b, is the episyllogism, since it employs
as one of its premises 4 the conclusion 3 of the first syllogism. It should be
noted that the terms ‘prosyllogism’ and ‘episyllogism’ are correlative terms.
Moreover, a polysyllogism may have more than two members.
Pomponazzi, Pietro 14621525, philosopher, an Aristotelian who taught at
the universities of Padua and Bologna. In De incantationibus “On Incantations,”
1556, he regards the world as a system of natural causes that can explain
apparently miraculous phenomena. Human beings are subject to the natural order
of the world, yet divine predestination and human freedom are compatible De
fato, “On Fate,” 1567. Furthermore, he distinguishes between what is proved by
natural reason and what is accepted by faith, and claims that, since there are
arguments for and against the immortality of the human individual soul, this
belief is to be accepted solely on the basis of faith De immortalitate animae,
“On the Immortality of the Soul,” He defended his view of immortality in the
Apologia 1518 and in the Defensorium 1519. These three works were reprinted as
Tractatus acutissimi 1525. Pomponazzi’s work was influential until the
seventeenth century, when Aristotelianism ceased to be the main philosophy
taught at the universities. The eighteenth-century freethinkers showed new
interest in his distinction between natural reason and faith. P.Gar. pons
asinorum Latin, ‘asses’ bridge’, a methodological device based upon Aristotle’s
description of the ways in which one finds a suitable middle term to
demonstrate categorical propositions. Thus, to prove the universal affirmative,
one should consider the characters that entail the predicate P and the
characters entailed by the subject S. If we find in the two groups of
characters a common member, we can use it as a middle term in the syllogistic
proof of say ‘All S are P’. Take ‘All men are mortal’ as the contemplated
conclusion. We find that ‘organism’ is among the characters entailing the
predicate ‘mortal’ and is also found in the group of characters entailed by the
subject ‘men’, and thus it may be used in a syllogistic proof of ‘All men are
mortal’. To prove negative propositions we must, in addition, consider
characters incompatible with the predicate, or incompatible with the subject.
Finally, proofs of particular propositions require considering characters that
entail the subject.
Popper, Karl Raimund, Austrian-born
British philosopher best known for contributions to philosophy of science and
to social and political philosophy. Educated at the of Vienna Ph.D., 8, he taught philosophy in
New Zealand for a decade before becoming a reader and then professor in logic
and scientific method at the London School of Economics 669. He was knighted in
5, elected a fellow of the Royal Society in 6, and appointed Companion of
Honour in 2 see his autobiography, Unended Quest, 6. In opposition to logical
positivism’s verifiability criterion of cognitive significance, Popper proposes
that science be characterized by its method: the criterion of demarcation of
empirical science from pseudo-science and metaphysics is falsifiability Logik
der Forschung, 4, tr. as The Logic of Scientific Discovery, 9. According to
falsificationism, science grows, and may even approach the truth, not by
amassing supporting evidence, but through an unending cycle of problems,
tentative solutions unjustifiable
conjectures and error elimination; i.e.,
the vigorous testing of deductive consequences and the refutation of
conjectures that fail Conjectures and Refutations, 3. Since conjectures are not
inferences and refutations are not inductive, there is no inductive inference
or inductive logic. More generally, criticism is installed as the hallmark of
rationality, and the traditional justificationist insistence on proof,
conclusive or inconclusive, on confirmation, and on positive argument, is
repudiated. Popper brings to the central problems of Kant’s philosophy an
uncompromising realism and objectivism, the tools of modern logic, and a
Darwinian perspective on knowledge, thereby solving Hume’s problem of induction
without lapsing into irrationalism Objective Knowledge, 2. He made
contributions of permanent importance also to the axiomatization of probability
theory The Logic of Scientific Discovery, 9; to its interpretation, especially
the propensity interpretation Postscript to The Logic of Scientific Discovery,
3 vols. 283; and to many other problems The Self and Its Brain, with John C.
Eccles, 7. Popper’s social philosophy, like his epistemology, is
anti-authoritarian. Since it is a historicist error to suppose that we can
predict the future of mankind The Poverty of Historicism, 7, the prime task of
social institutions in an open society
one that encourages criticism and allows rulers to be replaced without
violence must be not large-scale utopian
planning but the minimization, through piecemeal reform, of avoidable
suffering. This way alone permits proper assessment of success or failure, and thus
of learning from experience The Open Society and Its Enemies, 5.
Porphyry, Grecian Neoplatonist
philosopher, second to Plotinus in influence. He was born in Tyre, and is thus
sometimes called Porphyry the Phoenician. As a young man he went to Athens,
where he absorbed the Platonism of Cassius Longinus, who had in turn been
influenced by Ammonius Saccas in Alexandria. Porphyry went to Rome in 263,
where he became a disciple of Plotinus, who had also been influenced by
Ammonius. Porphyry lived in Rome until 269, when, urged by Plotinus to pons
asinorum Porphyry 722 722 travel as a
cure for severe depression, he traveled to Sicily. He remained there for
several years before returning to Rome to take over Plotinus’s school. He
apparently died in Rome. Porphyry is not noted for original thought. He seems
to have dedicated himself to explicating Aristotle’s logic and defending
Plotinus’s version of Neoplatonism. During his years in Sicily, Porphyry wrote
his two most famous works, the lengthy Against the Christians, of which only
fragments survive, and the Isagoge, or “Introduction.” The Isagoge, which
purports to give an elementary exposition of the concepts necessary to
understand Aristotle’s Categories, was tr. into Latin by Boethius and routinely
published in the Middle Ages with Latin editions of Aristotle’s Organon, or
logical treatises. Its inclusion in that format arguably precipitated the
discussion of the so-called problem of universals in the twelfth century.
During his later years in Rome, Porphyry collected Plotinus’s writings, editing
and organizing them into a scheme of his own
not Plotinus’s design, six groups
of nine treatises, thus called the Enneads. Porphyry prefaced his edition with
an informative biography of Plotinus, written shortly before Porphyry’s own
death.
Port-Royal Logic, originally entitled “La
logique, ou L’art de penser,” a treatise on logic, language, and method
composed by Antoine Arnauld and Pierre Nicole 162595, possibly with the help of
Pascal, all of whom were solitaires associated with the convent at
Port-Royal-des-Champs, the spiritual and intellectual center of Jansenism. Originally written as an
instruction manual for the son of the Duc de Luynes, the Logic was soon expanded
and published the first edition appeared in 1662, but it was constantly being
modified, augmented, and rewritten by its authors; by 1685 six editions in had appeared. The work develops the
linguistic theories presented by Arnauld and Claude Lancelot in the Grammaire
générale et raisonnée 1660, and reflects the pedagogical principles embodied in
the curriculum of the “little schools” run by PortRoyal. Its content is also
permeated by the Cartesianism to which Arnauld was devoted. The Logic’s
influence grew beyond Jansenist circles, and it soon became in
seventeenth-century France a standard manual for rigorous thinking. Eventually,
it was adopted as a textbook in schools.
The authors declare their goal to be to make thought more precise for better
distinguishing truth from error
philosophical and theological and
to develop sound judgment. They are especially concerned to dispel the errors
and confusions of the Scholastics. Logic is “the art of directing reason to a
knowledge of things for the instruction of ourselves and others.” This art consists
in reflecting on the mind’s four principal operations: conceiving, judging,
reasoning, and ordering. Accordingly, the Logic is divided into four sections:
on ideas and conception, on judgments, on reasoning, and on method..
positive and negative freedom,
respectively, the area within which the individual is self-determining and the
area within which the individual is left free from interference by others. More
specifically, one is free in the positive sense to the extent that one has
control over one’s life, or rules oneself. In this sense the term is very close
to that of ‘autonomy’. The forces that can prevent this self-determination are
usually thought of as internal, as desires or passions. This conception of
freedom can be said to have originated with Plato, according to whom a person
is free when the parts of the soul are rightly related to each other, i.e. the
rational part of the soul rules the other parts. Other advocates of positive
freedom include Spinoza, Rousseau, Kant, and Hegel. One is free in the negative
sense if one is not prevented from doing something by another person. One is
prevented from doing something if another person makes it impossible for one to
do something or uses coercion to prevent one from doing something. Hence persons
are free in the negative sense if they are not made unfree in the negative
sense. The term ‘negative liberty’ was coined by Bentham to mean the absence of
coercion. Advocates of negative freedom include Hobbes, Locke, and Hume.
possible worlds, alternative worlds in
terms of which one may think of possibility. The idea of thinking about
possibility in terms of such worlds has played an important part, both in
Leibnizian philosophical theology and in the development of modal logic and
philosophical reflection about it in recent decades. But there are important
differences in the forms the idea has taken, and the uses to which it has been
put, in the two contexts. Leibniz used it in his account of creation. In his
view God’s mind necessarily and eternally contains the ideas of infinitely many
worlds that God could have created, and God has chosen the best of these and
made it actual, thus creating it. Similar views are found in the thought of
Leibniz’s contemporary, Malebranche. The possible worlds are thus the complete
alternatives among which God chose. They are possible at least in the sense
that they are logically consistent; whether something more is required in order
for them to be coherent as worlds is a difficult question in Leibniz
interpretation. They are complete in that they are possible totalities of
creatures; each includes a whole possible universe, in its whole spatial extent
and its whole temporal history if it is spatially and temporally ordered. The
temporal completeness deserves emphasis. If “the world of tomorrow” is “a
better world” than “the world of today,” it will still be part of the same
“possible world” the actual one; for the actual “world,” in the relevant sense,
includes whatever actually has happened or will happen throughout all time. The
completeness extends to every detail, so that a milligram’s difference in the
weight of the smallest bird would make a different possible world. The
completeness of possible worlds may be limited in one way, however. Leibniz
speaks of worlds as aggregates of finite things. As alternatives for God’s
creation, they may well not be thought of as including God, or at any rate, not
every fact about God. For this and other reasons it is not clear that in
Leibniz’s thought the possible can be identified with what is true in some
possible world, or the necessary with what is true in all possible worlds. That
identification is regularly assumed, however, in the recent development of what
has become known as possible worlds semantics for modal logic the logic of
possibility and necessity, and of other conceptions, e.g. those pertaining to
time and to morality, that have turned out to be formally analogous. The basic
idea here is that such notions as those of validity, soundness, and
completeness can be defined for modal logic in terms of models constructed from
sets of alternative “worlds.” Since the late 0s many important results have
been obtained by this method, whose best-known exponent is Saul Kripke. Some of
the most interesting proofs depend on the idea of a relation of accessibility
between worlds in the set. Intuitively, one world is accessible from another if
and only if the former is possible in or from the point of view of the latter.
Different systems of modal logic are appropriate depending on the properties of
this relation e.g., on whether it is or is not reflexive and/or transitive
and/or symmetrical. The purely formal results of these methods are well
established. The application of possible worlds semantics to conceptions
occurring in metaphysically richer discourse is more controversial, however.
Some of the controversy is related to debates over the metaphysical reality of
various sorts of possibility and necessity. Particularly controversial, and
also a focus of much interest, have been attempts to understand modal claims de
re, about particular individuals as such e.g., that I could not have been a
musical performance, in terms of the identity and nonidentity of individuals in
different possible worlds. Similarly, there is debate over the applicability of
a related treatment of subjunctive conditionals, developed by Robert Stalnaker
and David Lewis, though it is clear that it yields interesting formal results.
What is required, on this approach, for the truth of ‘If it were the case that
A, then it would be the case that B’, is that, among those possible worlds in
which A is true, some world in which B is true be more similar, in the relevant
respects, to the actual world than any world in which B is false. One of the
most controversial topics is the nature of possible worlds themselves.
Mathematical logicians need not be concerned with this; a wide variety of sets
of objects, real or fictitious, can be viewed as having the properties required
of sets of “worlds” for their purposes. But if metaphysically robust issues of
modality e.g., whether there are more possible colors than we ever see are to
be understood in terms of possible worlds, the question of the nature of the
worlds must be taken seriously. Some philosophers would deny any serious
metaphysical role to the notion of possible worlds. At the other extreme, David
Lewis has defended a view of possible worlds as concrete totalities, things of
the same sort as the whole actual universe, made up of entities like planets,
persons, and so forth. On his view, the actuality of the actual world consists
only in its being this one, the one that we are in; apart from its relation to
us or our linguistic acts, the actual is not metaphysically distinguished from
the merely possible. Many philosophers find this result counterintuitive, and
the infinity of concrete possible worlds an extravagant ontology; but Lewis
argues that his view makes possible attractive reductions of modality both
logical and causal, and of such notions as that of a proposition, to more
concrete notions. Other philosophers are prepared to say there are non-actual
possible worlds, but that they are entities of a quite different sort from the
actual concrete universe sets of
propositions, perhaps, or some other type of “abstract” object. Leibniz himself
held a view of this kind, thinking of possible worlds as having their being
only in God’s mind, as intentional objects of God’s thought.
post-modern – H. P. Grice plays with the
‘modernists,’ versus the ‘neo-traditionalists.’ Since he sees a
neotraditionalist like Strawson (neotraditionalist, like neocon, is a joke) and
a modernist like Whitehead as BOTH making the same mistake, it is fair to see
Grice as a ‘post-modernist’ -- of or relating to a complex set of reactions to
modern philosophy and its presuppositions, as opposed to the kind of agreement
on substantive doctrines or philosophical questions that often characterizes a
philosophical movement. Although there is little agreement on precisely what
the presuppositions of modern philosophy are, and disagreement on which
philosophers exemplify these presuppositions, postmodern philosophy typically
opposes foundationalism, essentialism, and realism. For Rorty, e.g., the
presuppositions to be set aside are foundationalist assumptions shared by the
leading sixteenth-, seventeenth-, and eighteenth-century philosophers. For
Nietzsche, Heidegger, Foucault, and Derrida, the contested presuppositions to
be set aside are as old as metaphysics itself, and are perhaps best exemplified
by Plato. Postmodern philosophy has even been characterized, by Lyotard, as
preceding modern philosophy, in the sense that the presuppositions of
philosophical modernism emerge out of a disposition whose antecedent,
unarticulated beliefs are already postmodern. Postmodern philosophy is
therefore usefully regarded as a complex cluster concept that includes the
following elements: an anti- or post- epistemological standpoint;
anti-essentialism; anti-realism; anti-foundationalism; opposition to
transcendental arguments and transcendental standpoints; rejection of the
picture of knowledge as accurate representation; rejection of truth as
correspondence to reality; rejection of the very idea of canonical
descriptions; rejection of final vocabularies, i.e., rejection of principles,
distinctions, and descriptions that are thought to be unconditionally binding
for all times, persons, and places; and a suspicion of grand narratives,
metanarratives of the sort perhaps best illustrated by dialectical materialism.
In addition to these things postmodern philosophy is “against,” it also opposes
characterizing this menu of oppositions as relativism, skepticism, or nihilism,
and it rejects as “the metaphysics of presence” the traditional, putatively
impossible dream of a complete, unique, and closed explanatory system, an
explanatory system typically fueled by binary oppositions. On the positive
side, one often finds the following themes: its critique of the notion of the
neutrality and sovereignty of reason
including insistence on its pervasively gendered, historical, and
ethnocentric character; its conception of the social construction of wordworld
mappings; its tendency to embrace historicism; its critique of the ultimate
status of a contrast between epistemology, on the one hand, and the sociology
of knowledge, on the other hand; its dissolution of the notion of the
autonomous, rational subject; its insistence on the artifactual status of
divisions of labor in knowledge acquisition and production; and its ambivalence
about the Enlightenment and its ideology. Many of these elements or elective
affinities were already surfacing in the growing opposition to the spectator
theory of knowledge, in Europe and in the English-speaking world, long before
the term ‘postmodern’ became a commonplace. In Anglophone philosophy this took
the early form of Dewey’s and pragmatism’s opposition to positivism, early
Kuhn’s redescription of scientific practice, and Vitters’s insistence on the
language-game character of representation; critiques of “the myth of the given”
from Sellars to Davidson and Quine; the emergence of epistemology naturalized;
and the putative description-dependent character of data, tethered to the
theory dependence of descriptions in Kuhn, Sellars, Quine, and Arthur Fine perhaps in all constructivists in the
philosophy of science. In Europe, many of these elective affinities surfaced
explicitly in and were identified with poststructuralism, although traces are
clearly evident in Heidegger’s and later in Derrida’s attacks on Husserl’s
residual Cartesianism; the rejection of essential descriptions
Wesensanschauungen in Husserl’s sense; Saussure’s and structuralism’s attack on
the autonomy and coherence of a transcendental signified standing over against
a selftransparent subject; Derrida’s deconstructing the metaphysics of
presence; Foucault’s redescriptions of epistemes; the convergence between - and
English-speaking social constructivists; attacks on the language of enabling
conditions as reflected in worries about the purchase of necessary and
sufficient conditions talk on both sides of the Atlantic; and Lyotard’s many
interventions, particularly those against grand narratives. Many of these
elective affinities that characterize postmodern philosophy can also be seen in
the virtually universal challenges to moral philosophy as it has been
understood traditionally in the West, not only in G. and philosophy, but in the reevaluation of “the
morality of principles” in the work of MacIntyre, Williams, Nussbaum, John
McDowell, and others. The force of postmodern critiques can perhaps best be
seen in some of the challenges of feminist theory, as in the work of Judith
Butler and Hélène Cixous, and gender theory generally. For it is in gender
theory that the conception of “reason” itself as it has functioned in the
shared philosophical tradition is redescribed as a conception that, it is often
argued, is engendered, patriarchal, homophobic, and deeply optional. The term
‘postmodern’ is less clear in philosophy, its application more uncertain and
divided than in some other fields, e.g., postmodern architecture. In
architecture the concept is relatively clear. It displaces modernism in
assignable ways, emerges as an oppositional force against architectural
modernism, a rejection of the work and tradition inaugurated by Walter Gropius,
Henri Le Corbusier, and Mies van der Rohe, especially the International Style.
In postmodern architecture, the modernist principle of abstraction, of
geometric purity and simplicity, is displaced by multivocity and pluralism, by
renewed interest in buildings as signs and signifiers, interest in their
referential potential and resources. The modernist’s aspiration to buildings
that are timeless in an important sense is itself read by postmodernists as an
iconography that privileges the brave new world of science and technology, an
aspiration that glorifies uncritically the industrial revolution of which it is
itself a quintessential expression. This aspiration to timelessness is
displaced in postmodern architecture by a direct and self-conscious openness to
and engagement with history. It is this relative specificity of the concept
postmodern architecture that enabled Charles Jencks to write that “Modern
Architecture died in St. Louis Missouri on July 15, 2 at 3:32 P.M.”
Unfortunately, no remotely similar sentence can be written about postmodern
philosophy.
Potentia -- dunamis, also dynamis Grecian,
‘power’, ‘capacity’, as used by pre-Socratics such as Anaximander and
Anaxagoras, one of the elementary character-powers, such as the hot or the
cold, from which they believed the world was constructed. Plato’s early theory
of Forms borrowed from the concept of character-powers as causes present in
things; courage, e.g., is treated in the Laches as a power in the soul.
Aristotle also used the word in this sense to explain the origins of the
elements. In the Metaphysics especially Book IX, Aristotle used dunamis in a
different sense to mean ‘potentiality’ in contrast to ‘actuality’ energeia or
entelecheia. In the earlier sense of dunamis, matter is treated as
potentiality, in that it has the potential to receive form and so be actualized
as a concrete substance. In the later Aristotelian sense of dunamis, dormant
abilities are treated as potentialities, and dunamis is to energeia as sleeping
is to waking, or having sight to seeing.
Potentia -- dynamic logic, a branch of logic in which, in addition to
the usual category of formulas interpretable as propositions, there is a
category of expressions interpretable as actions. Dynamic logic originally
called the modal logic of programs emerged in the late 0s as one step in a long
tradition within theoretical computer science aimed at providing a way to
formalize the analysis of programs and their action. A particular concern here
was program verification: what can be said of the effect of a program if
started at a certain point? To this end operators [a] and ‹a were introduced
with the following intuitive readings: [a]A to mean ‘after every terminating
computation according to a it is the case that A’ and ‹aA to mean ‘after some
terminating computation according to a it is the case that A’. The logic of
these operators may be seen as a generalization of ordinary modal logic: where
modal logic has one box operator A and one diamond operator B, dynamic logic
has one box operator [a] and one diamond operator ‹a for every program
expression a in the language. In possible worlds semantics for modal logic a
model is a triple U, R, V where U is a universe of points, R a binary relation,
and V a valuation assigning to each atomic formula a subset of U. In dynamic
logic, a model is a triple U, R, V where U and V are as before but R is a
family of binary relations Ra, one for every program expression a in the
language. Writing ‘Xx A’, where x is a point in U, for ‘A is true at x’ in the
model in question, we have the following characteristic truth conditions
truth-functional compounds are evaluated by truth tables, as in modal logic: Xx
P if and only if x is a point in VP, where P is an atomic formula, Xx[a]A if
and only if, for all y, if x is Ra- related to y then Xy A, Xx ‹a if and only
if, for some y, x is Ra-related to y and Xy A. Traditionally, dynamic logic
will contain machinery for rendering the three regular operators on programs:
‘!’ sum, ‘;’ composition, and ‘*’ Kleene’s star operation, as well as the test
operator ‘?’, which, operating on a proposition, will yield a program. The
action a ! b consists in carrying out a or carrying out b; the action a;b in
first carrying out a, then carrying out b; the action a* in carrying out a some
finite number of times not excluding 0; the action ?A in verifying that A. Only
standard models reflect these intuitions: Ra ! b % Ra 4 Rb, Ra;b % Ra _ Rb, Ra*
% Ra*, R?A % {x,x : Xx A} where ‘*’ is the ancestral star The smallest
propositional dynamic logic PDL is the set of formulas true at every point in
every standard model. Note that dynamic logic analyzes non-deterministic
action this is evident at the level of
atomic programs p where Rp is a relation, not necessarily a function, and also
in the definitions of Ra + b and Ra*. Dynamic logic has been extended in
various ways, e.g., to first- and second-order predicate logic. Furthermore,
just as deontic logic, tense logic, etc., are referred to as modal logic in the
wide sense, so extensions of dynamic logic in the narrow sense such as process
logic are often loosely referred to as dynamic logic in the wide sense. Dyad
dynamic logic 250 250 The philosophical
interest in dynamic logic rests with the expectation that it will prove a
fruitful instrument for analyzing the concept of action in general: a
successful analysis would be valuable in itself and would also be relevant to
other disciplines such as deontic logic and the logic of imperatives.
potency, for Aristotle, a kind of capacity
that is a correlative of action. We require no instruction to grasp the
difference between ‘X can do Y’ and ‘X is doing Y’, the latter meaning that the
deed is actually being done. That an agent has a potency to do something is not
a pure prediction so much as a generalization from past performance of
individual or kind. Aristotle uses the example of a builder, meaning someone
able to build, and then confronts the Megaric objection that the builder can be
called a builder only when he actually builds. Clearly one who is doing
something can do it, but Aristotle insists that the napping carpenter has the
potency to hammer and saw. A potency based on an acquired skill like carpentry
derives from the potency shared by those who acquire and those who do not
acquire the skill. An unskilled worker can be said to be a builder “in
potency,” not in the sense that he has the skill and can employ it, but in the
sense that he can acquire the skill. In both acquisition and employment, ‘potency’
refers to the actual either the actual
acquisition of the skill or its actual use. These post-structuralism potency
726 726 potentiality, first practical
attitude 727 correlatives emerged from Aristotle’s analysis of change and
becoming. That which, from not having the skill, comes to have it is said to be
“in potency” to that skill. From not having a certain shape, wood comes to have
a certain shape. In the shaped wood, a potency is actualized. Potency must not
be identified with the unshaped, with what Aristotle calls privation. Privation
is the negation of P in a subject capable of P. Parmenides’ identification of
privation and potency, according to Aristotle, led him to deny change. How can
not-P become P? It is the subject of not-P to which the change is attributed
and which survives the change that is in potency to X.
poverty of the stimulus, a psychological
phenomenon exhibited when behavior is stimulusunbound, and hence the immediate
stimulus characterized in straightforward physical terms does not completely
control behavior. Human beings sort stimuli in various ways and hosts of
influences seem to affect when, why, and how we respond our background beliefs, facility with
language, hypotheses about stimuli, etc. Suppose a person visiting a museum
notices a painting she has never before seen. Pondering the unfamiliar
painting, she says, “an ambitious visual synthesis of the music of Mahler and
the poetry of Keats.” If stimulus painting controls response, then her
utterance is a product of earlier responses to similar stimuli. Given poverty
of the stimulus, no such control is exerted by the stimulus the painting. Of
course, some influence of response must be conceded to the painting, for
without it there would be no utterance. However, the utterance may well
outstrip the visitor’s conditioning and learning history. Perhaps she had never
before talked of painting in terms of music and poetry. The linguist Noam
Chomsky made poverty of the stimulus central to his criticism of B. F. Skinner’s
Verbal Behavior 7. Chomsky argued that there is no predicting, and certainly no
critical stimulus control of, much human behavior.
power, a disposition; an ability or
capacity to yield some outcome. One tradition which includes Locke
distinguishes active and passive powers. A knife has the active power to slice
an apple, which has the passive power to be sliced by the knife. The
distinction seems largely grammatical, however. Powers act in concert: the
power of a grain of salt to dissolve in water and the water’s power to dissolve
the salt are reciprocal and their manifestations mutual. Powers or dispositions
are sometimes thought to be relational properties of objects, properties
possessed only in virtue of objects standing in appropriate relations to other
objects. However, if we distinguish, as we must, between a power and its
manifestation, and if we allow that an object could possess a power that it
never manifested a grain of salt remains soluble even if it never dissolves, it
would seem that an object could possess a power even if appropriate reciprocal
partners for its manifestation were altogether non-existent. This appears to
have been Locke’s view An Essay concerning Human Understanding, 1690 of
“secondary qualities” colors, sounds, and the like, which he regarded as powers
of objects to produce certain sorts of sensory experience in observers.
Philosophers who take powers seriously disagree over whether powers are
intrinsic, “built into” properties this view, defended by C. B. Martin, seems
to have been Locke’s, or whether the connection between properties and the
powers they bestow is contingent, dependent perhaps upon contingent laws of
nature a position endorsed by Armstrong. Is the solubility of salt a
characteristic built into the salt, or is it a “second-order” property
possessed by the salt in virtue of i the salt’s possession of some “firstorder”
property and ii the laws of nature? Reductive analyses of powers, though
influential, have not fared well. Suppose a grain of salt is soluble in water.
Does this mean that if the salt were placed in water, it would dissolve? No.
Imagine that were the salt placed in water, a technician would intervene,
imposing an electromagnetic field, thereby preventing the salt from dissolving.
Attempts to exclude “blocking” conditions
by appending “other things equal” clauses perhaps face charges of circularity: in nailing down
what other things must be equal we find ourselves appealing to powers. Powers
evidently are fundamental features of our world.
practical reason, the capacity for
argument or demonstrative inference, considered in its application to the task
of prescribing or selecting behavior. Some philosophical concerns in this area
pertain to the actual thought processes by which plans of action are formulated
and carried out in practical situations. A second major issue is what role, if
any, practical reason plays in determining norms of conduct. Here there are two
fundamental positions. Instrumentalism is typified by Hume’s claim that reason
is, and ought only to be, the slave of the passions. According to
instrumentalism, reason by itself is incapable of influencing action directly.
It may do so indirectly, by disclosing facts that arouse motivational impulses.
And it fulfills an indispensable function in discerning meansend relations by
which our objectives may be attained. But none of those objectives is set by
reason. All are set by the passions the
desiderative and aversive impulses aroused in us by what our cognitive
faculties apprehend. It does not follow from this alone that ethical motivation
reduces to mere desire and aversion, based on the pleasure and pain different
courses of action might afford. There might yet be a specifically ethical
passion, or it might be that independently based moral injunctions have in
themselves a special capacity to provoke ordinary desire and aversion.
Nevertheless, instrumentalism is often associated with the view that pleasure
and pain, happiness and unhappiness, are the sole objects of value and
disvalue, and hence the only possible motivators of conduct. Hence, it is
claimed, moral injunctions must be grounded in these motives, and practical
reason is of interest only as subordinated to inclination. The alternative to
instrumentalism is the view championed by Kant, that practical reason is an
autonomous source of normative principles, capable of motivating behavior
independently of ordinary desire and aversion. On this view it is the passions
that lack intrinsic moral import, and the function of practical reason is to
limit their motivational role by formulating normative principles binding for
all rational agents and founded in the operation of practical reason itself.
Theories of this kind usually view moral principles as grounded in consistency,
and an impartial respect for the autonomy of all rational agents. To be morally
acceptable, principles of conduct must be universalizable, so that all rational
agents could behave in the same way without their conduct either destroying
itself or being inconsistently motivated. There are advantages and
disadvantages to each of these views. Instrumentalism offers a simpler account
of both the function of practical reason and the sources of human motivation.
But it introduces a strong subjective element by giving primacy to desire,
thereby posing a problem of how moral principles can be universally binding.
The Kantian approach offers more promise here, since it makes
universalizability essential to any type of behavior being moral. But it is
more complex, and the claim that the deliverances of practical reason carry
intrinsic motivational force is open to challenge.
practical reasoning, the inferential
process by which considerations for or against envisioned courses of action are
brought to bear on the formation and execution of intention. The content of a
piece of practical reasoning is a practical argument. Practical arguments can
be complex, but they are often summarized in syllogistic form. Important issues
concerning practical reasoning include how it relates to theoretical reasoning,
whether it is a causal process, and how it can be evaluated. Theories of
practical reasoning tend to divide into two basic categories. On one sort of
view, the intrinsic features of practical reasoning exhibit little or no
difference from those of theoretical reasoning. What makes practical reasoning
practical is its subject matter and motivation. Hence the following could be a
bona fide practical syllogism: Exercise would be good for me. Jogging is
exercise. Therefore, jogging would be good for me. This argument has practical
subject matter, and if made with a view toward intention formation it would be
practical in motivation also. But it consists entirely of propositions, which
are appropriate contents for belief-states. In principle, therefore, an agent
could accept its conclusion without intending or even desiring to jog.
Intention formation requires a further step. But if the content of an intention
cannot be a proposition, that step could not count in itself as practical
reasoning unless such reasoning can employ the contents of strictly practical
mental states. Hence many philosophers call for practical syllogisms such as:
Would that I exercise. Jogging is exercise. Therefore, I shall go jogging. Here
the first premise is optative and understood to represent the content of a
desire, and the conclusion is the content of a decision or act of intention
formation. These contents are not true or false, and so are not propositions.
Theories that restrict the contents of practical reasoning to propositions have
the advantage that they allow such reasoning to be evaluated in terms of
familiar logical principles. Those that permit the inclusion of optative
content entail a need for more complex modes of evaluation. However, they bring
more of the process of intention formation under the aegis of reason; also,
they can be extended to cover the execution of intentions, in terms of
syllogisms that terminate in volition. Both accounts must deal with cases of
self-deception, in which the considerations an agent cites to justify a
decision are not those from which it sprang, and cases of akrasia, where the
agent views one course of action as superior, yet carries out another. Because
mental content is always abstract, it cannot in itself be a nomic cause of
behavior. But the states and events to which it belongs desires, beliefs, etc. can count as causes, and are so treated in
deterministic explanations of action. Opponents of determinism reject this
step, and seek to explain action solely through the teleological or justifying
force carried by mental content. Practical syllogisms often summarize very
complex thought processes, in which multiple options are considered, each with
its own positive and negative aspects. Some philosophers hold that when
successfully concluded, this process issues in a judgment of what action would
be best all things considered i.e., in
light of all relevant considerations. Practical reasoning can be evaluated in
numerous ways. Some concern the reasoning process itself: whether it is timely
and duly considers the relevant alternatives, as well as whether it is well
structured logically. Other concerns have to do with the products of practical
reasoning. Decisions may be deemed irrational if they result in incompatible intentions,
or conflict with the agent’s beliefs regarding what is possible. They may also
be criticized if they conflict with the agent’s best interests. Finally, an
agent’s intentions can fail to accord with standards of morality. The
relationship among these ways of evaluating intentions is important to the
foundations of ethics.
practition, Castaneda’s term for the
characteristic content of practical thinking. Each practition represents an
action as something to be done, say, as intended, commanded, recommended, etc.,
and not as an accomplishment or prediction. Thus, unlike propositions,
practitions are not truth-valued, but they can be components of valid arguments
and so possess values akin to truth; e.g., the command ‘James, extinguish your
cigar!’ seems legitimate given that James is smoking a cigar in a crowded bus.
Acknowledging practitions is directly relevant to many other fields.
praedicamenta singular: praedicamentum, in
medieval philosophy, the ten Aristotelian categories: substance, quantity,
quality, relation, where, when, position i.e., orientation e.g., “upright”, having, action, and
passivity. These were the ten most general of all genera. All of them except
substance were regarded as accidental. It was disputed whether this tenfold classification
was intended as a linguistic division among categorematic terms or as an
ontological division among extralinguistic realities. Some authors held that
the division was primarily linguistic, and that extralinguistic realities were
divided according to some but not all the praedicamenta. Most authors held that
everything in any way real belonged to one praedicamentum or another, although
some made an exception for God. But authors who believed in complexe
significabile usually regarded them as not belonging to any
praedicamentum.
pragmatic contradiction, a contradiction
that is generated by pragmatic rather than logical implication. A logically
implies B if it is impossible for B to be false if A is true, whereas A
pragmatically implies B if in most but not necessarily all contexts, saying ‘A’
can reasonably be taken as indicating that B is true. Thus, if I say, “It’s
raining,” what I say does not logically imply that I believe that it is
raining, since it is possible for it to be raining without my believing it is.
Nor does my saying that it is raining logically imply that I believe that it
is, since it is possible for me to say this without believing it. But my saying
this does pragmatically imply that I believe that it is raining, since normally
my saying this can reasonably be taken to indicate that I believe it.
Accordingly, if I were to say, “It’s raining but I don’t believe that it’s
raining,” the result would be a pragmatic contradiction. The first part “It’s
raining” does not logically imply the negation of the second part “I don’t
believe that it’s raining” but my saying the first part does pragmatically
imply the negation of the second part.
pragmatism, a philosophy that stresses the
relation of theory to praxis and takes the continuity of experience and nature
as revealed through the outcome of directed action as the starting point for
reflection. Experience is the ongoing transaction of organism and environment,
i.e., both subject and object are constituted in the process. When intelligently
ordered, initial conditions are deliberately transformed according to
ends-inview, i.e., intentionally, into a subsequent state of affairs thought to
be more desirable. Knowledge is therefore guided by interests or values. Since
the reality of objects cannot be known prior to experience, truth claims can be
justified only as the fulfillment of conditions that are experimentally
determined, i.e., the outcome of inquiry. As a philosophic movement, pragmatism
was first formulated by Peirce in the early 1870s in the Metaphysical Club in
Cambridge, Massachusetts; it was announced as a distinctive position in James’s
8 address to the Philosophical Union at the
of California at Berkeley, and further elaborated according to the
Chicago School, especially by Dewey, Mead, and Jane Addams 18605. Emphasis on
the reciprocity of theory and praxis, knowledge and action, facts and values,
follows from its postDarwinian understanding of human experience, including
cognition, as a developmental, historically contingent, process. C. I. Lewis’s
pragmatic a priori and Quine’s rejection of the analytic synthetic distinction
develop these insights further. Knowledge is instrumental a tool for organizing experience
satisfactorily. Concepts are habits of belief or rules of action. Truth cannot
be determined solely by epistemological criteria because the adequacy of these
criteria cannot be determined apart from the goals sought and values
instantiated. Values, which arise in historically specific cultural situations,
are intelligently appropriated only to the extent that they satisfactorily
resolve problems and are judged worth retaining. According to pragmatic
theories of truth, truths are beliefs that are confirmed in the course of
experience and are therefore fallible, subject to further revision. True
beliefs for Peirce represent real objects as successively confirmed until they
converge on a final determination; for James, leadings that are worthwhile; and
according to Dewey’s theory of inquiry, the transformation of an indeterminate
situation into a determinate one that leads to warranted assertions. Pragmatic
ethics is naturalistic, pluralistic, developmental, and experimental. It
reflects on the motivations influencing ethical systems, examines the
individual developmental process wherein an individual’s values are gradually
distinguished from those of society, situates moral judgments within
problematic situations irreducibly individual and social, and proposes as
ultimate criteria for decision making the value for life as growth, determined
by all those affected by the actual or projected outcomes. The original
interdisciplinary development of pragmatism continues in its influence on the
humanities. Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., member of the Metaphysical Club, later
justice of the U.S. Supreme Court, developed a pragmatic theory of law.
Peirce’s Principle of Pragmatism, by which meaning resides in conceivable
practical effects, and his triadic theory of signs developed into the field of
semiotics. James’s Principles of Psychology 0 not only established experimental
psychology in North America, but shifted philosophical attention away from
abstract analyses of rationality to the continuity of the biological and the
mental. The reflex arc theory was reconstructed into an interactive loop of
perception, feeling, thinking, and behavior, and joined with the selective
interest of consciousness to become the basis of radical empiricism. Mead’s
theory of the emergence of self and mind in social acts and Dewey’s analyses of
the individual and society influenced the human sciences. Dewey’s theory of
education as community-oriented, based on the psychological developmental
stages of growth, and directed toward full participation in a democratic
society, was the philosophical basis of progressive education.
praxis from Grecian prasso, ‘doing’,
‘acting’, in Aristotle, the sphere of thought and action that comprises the
ethical and political life of man, contrasted with the theoretical designs of
logic and epistemology theoria. It was thus that ‘praxis’ acquired its general
definition of ‘practice’ through a contrastive comparison with ‘theory’.
Throughout the history of Western philosophy the concept of praxis found a
place in a variety of philosophical vocabularies. Marx and the neoMarxists
linked the concept with a production paradigm in the interests of historical
explanation. Within such a scheme of things the activities constituting the
relations of production and exchange are seen as the dominant features of the
socioeconomic history of humankind. Significations of ‘praxis’ are also
discernible in the root meaning of pragma deed, affair, which informed the
development of pragmatism. In more
recent times the notion of praxis has played a prominent role in the formation
of the school of critical theory, in which the performatives of praxis are seen
to be more directly associated with the entwined phenomena of discourse,
communication, and social practices. The central philosophical issues addressed
in the current literature on praxis have to do with the theorypractice
relationship and the problems associated with a value-free science. The general
thrust is that of undermining or subverting the traditional bifurcation of
theory and practice via a recognition of praxis-oriented endeavors that
antedate both theory construction and the construal of practice as a mere
application of theory. Both the project of “pure theory,” which makes claims
for a value-neutral standpoint, and the purely instrumentalist understanding of
practice, as itself shorn of discernment and insight, are jettisoned. The
consequent philosophical task becomes that of understanding human thought and
action against the backdrop of the everyday communicative endeavors, habits,
and skills, and social practices that make up our inheritance in the
world.
Praxis school, a school of philosophy
originating in Zagreb and Belgrade which, from 4 to 4, published the
international edition of the leading postwar Marxist journal Praxis. During the
same period, it organized the Korcula Summer School, which attracted scholars
from around the Western world. In a reduced form the school continues each
spring with the Social Philosophy Course in Dubrovnik, Croatia. The founders of
praxis philosophy include Gajo Petrovic Zagreb, Milan Kangrga Zagreb, and
Mihailo Markovic Belgrade. Another wellknown member of the group is Svetozar
Stojanovic Belgrade, and a second-generation leader is Gvozden Flego Zagreb.
The Praxis school emphasized the writings of the young Marx while subjecting
dogmatic Marxism to one of its strongest criticisms. Distinguishing between
Marx’s and Engels’s writings and emphasizing alienation and a dynamic concept
of the human being, it contributed to a greater understanding of the
interrelationship between the individual and society. Through its insistence on
Marx’s call for a “ruthless critique,” the school stressed open inquiry and
freedom of speech in both East and West. Quite possibly the most important and
original philosopher of the group, and certainly Croatia’s leading
twentieth-century philosopher, was Gajo Petrovic 793. He called for 1
understanding philosophy as a radical critique of all existing things, and 2
understanding human beings as beings of praxis and creativity. This later led
to a view of human beings as revolutionary by nature. At present he is probably
best remembered for his Marx in the Mid-Twentieth Century and Philosophie und
Revolution. Milan Kangrga b.3 also emphasizes human creativity while insisting
that one should understand human beings as producers who humanize nature. An
ethical problematic of humanity can pragmatism, ethical Praxis school 731 731 be realized through a variety of
disciplines that include aesthetics, philosophical anthropolgy, theory of knowledge,
ontology, and social thought. Mihailo Markovic b.3, a member of the Belgrade
Eight, is best known for his theory of meaning, which leads him to a theory of
socialist humanism. His most widely read work in the West is From Affluence to
Praxis: Philosophy and Social Criticism.
Pre-analytic, considered but naive;
commonsensical; not tainted by prior explicit theorizing; said of judgments
and, derivatively, of beliefs or intuitions underlying such judgments.
Preanalytic judgments are often used to test philosophical theses. All things considered,
we prefer theories that accord with preanalytic judgments to those that do not,
although most theorists exhibit a willingness to revise preanalytic assessments
in light of subsequent inquiry. Thus, a preanalytic judgment might be thought
to constitute a starting point for the philosophical consideration of a given
topic. Is justice giving every man his due? It may seem so, preanalytically.
Attention to concrete examples, however, may lead us to a different view. It is
doubtful, even in such cases, that we altogether abandon preanalytic judgments.
Rather, we endeavor to reconcile apparently competing judgments, making
adjustments in a way that optimizes overall coherence.
principle of economy of rational effort --
cheapest-cost avoider, in the economic analysis of law, the party in a dispute
that could have prevented the dispute, or minimized the losses arising from it,
with the lowest loss to itself. The term encompasses several types of behavior.
As the lowest-cost accident avoider, it is the party that could have prevented
the accident at the lowest cost. As the lowest-cost insurer, it is the party
that could been have insured against the losses arising from the dispute. This
could be the party that could have purchased insurance at the lowest cost or
self-insured, or the party best able to appraise the expected losses and the
probability of the occurrence. As the lowest-cost briber, it is the party least
subject to transaction costs. This party is the one best able to correct any
legal errors in the assignment of the entitlement by purchasing the entitlement
from the other party. As the lowest-cost information gatherer, it is the party
best able to make an informed judgment as to the likely benefits and costs of
an action. Principle of economy of
rational effort: Coase theorem, a non-formal insight by R. Coase: 1: assuming
that there are no transaction costs involved in exchanging rights for money,
then no matter how rights are initially distributed, rational agents will buy
and sell them so as to maximize individual returns. In jurisprudence this
proposition has been the basis for a claim about how rights should be
distributed even when as is usual transaction costs are high: the law should
confer rights on those who would purchase them were they for sale on markets
without transaction costs; e.g., the right to an indivisible, unsharable
resource should be conferred on the agent willing to pay the highest price for
it.
principium. Grice. Principle
of conversational helpfulness. “I call it ‘principle,’ echoing Boethius.”Mention should also he made of Boethius’ conception, that
there are certain principles, sentences which have no demonstration — probatio
— which he calls principales propositiones or probationis principia. Here is
the fragment from his Commentary on Topics treating of principles; El iliac
quidem (propositiones) quarum nulla probatio est, maximae ac principales
vocantur, quod his illas necesse est approbari, quae ut demonstrari valeant,
non recusant/ est auteni maxima proposiiio ut liaec « si de aequalibus aequalia
demas, quae derelinquitur aequalia sunt », ita enim hoc per se notion est, ut
aliud notius quo approbari valeat esse non possit; quae proposi- tiones cum
(idem sui natura propria gerant, non solum alieno ad (idem non egent argumento,
oerum ceteris quoque probationis sclent esse principium; igitur per se notae
propositiones, quibus nihil est notius, indemonstrabiles ac maxime et
principales vocantur (“Indeed those sentences that have no demonstration are
called maximum or principal [sentences], because they are not rejected since
they are necessary to those that have to be demonstrated and which are valid
for making a demonstration ; but a maximum sentence such as « if from equal
[quantifies], equal [quantities] are taken, what is left are equal
[quantities]*, is self- evident, and there is nothing which can be better known
self-evidently valid, and self- demonstrating, therefore they are sentences
containing their certitude in their very nature and not only do they need no additional
argument to demonstrate their certitude, but are also the principles of
demonstration of the other [sentences]; so they are, self-evident sen- tences,
nothing being better known than they are, and are called undemonstrable or
maxi- mum and principal”). Boethius’ idea coincides with Aristotle’s; deduction
must start from somewhere, we must begin with something unproved. The
Stagirite, how- ever, gave an explanation of the existence of principles and
the possibility of their being grasjied by the active intellect, whereas with
Boethius princi- ples appear as severed from the sentences demonstrated in a
more formal manner: there are two kinds of sentences: some which are
demonstrable and others which need no demonstration
praedicabile: As in qualia being the plural of quale and universalia
being the plural of universale, predicabilia is Boethius’s plural for the
‘predicabile’ -- something Grice knew by heart from giving seminars at Oxfrod
on Aristotle’s categories with Austin and Strawson. He found the topic boring
enough to give the seminar ALONE!
prædicatum: vide Is there a praedicatum in Blackburn’s one-off
predicament. He draws a skull and communicates that there is danger. The
drawsing of the skull is not syntactically structured. So it is difficult to
isolate the ‘praedicatum.’ That’s why Grice leaves matters of the praedicatum’
to reductive analyses at a second stage of his programme, where one wants to
apply, metabolically, ‘communicate’ to what an emissum does. The emissum of the
form, The S is P, predicates P of S.
Vide subjectification, and subjectum. Of especial interest to Grice and
Strawson. Lewis and Short have “praedīco,” which they render as “to say or
mention before or beforehand, to premise.” Grice as a modista is interested in
parts of speech: nomen (onoma) versus verbum (rhema) being the classical, since
Plato. The mediaeval modistae like Alcuin adapted Aristotle, and Grice follows
suit. Of particular relevance are the ‘syncategoremata,’ since Grice was
obsessed with particles, and we cannot say that ‘and’ is a predicate! This
relates to the ‘categorema.’ Liddell and Scott have “κατηγόρ-ημα,” which they
render as “accusation, charge,” Gorg.Pal.22; but in philosophy, as “predicate,”
as per Arist.Int.20b32, Metaph.1053b19, etc.; -- “οὐκ εὔοδον τὸ ἁπλοῖν
ἐστι κ.” Epicur.Fr.18. – and as “head of predicables,” in
Arist.Metaph.1028a33,Ph.201a1, Zeno Stoic.1.25, etc.; περὶ κατηγορημάτων
Sphaer.ib.140. The term syncategorema comes from a passage of Priscian in
his Institutiones grammatice II , 15. “coniunctae
plenam faciunt orationem, alias autem partes, κατηγορήματα, hoc est consignificantia, appellabant.”
A distinction is made between two types of word classes ("partes
orationis," singular, "pars orationis") distinguished by
philosophers since Plato, viz. nouns (nomen, onoma) and verbs (verbum, rhema)
on the one hand, and a 'syncategorema or consignificantium. A
consignificantium, just as the unary functor "non," and any of the
three dyadic functors, "et," "vel" (or "aut") and
"si," does not have a definitive meaning on its own -- cf. praepositio,
cited by Grice, -- "the meaning of 'to,' the meaning of 'of,'" --
rather, they acquire meaning in combination or when con-joined to one or more
categorema. It is one thing to say that we employ a certain part of speech when
certain conditions are fulfilled and quite another to claim that the role in
the language of that part of speech is to say, even in an extended sense, that
those conditions are fulfilled. In Logic, the verb 'kategoreo' is 'predicate of
a person or thing,' “τί τινος” Arist.Cat.3a19,al., Epicur.Fr.250; κυρίως,
καταχρηστικῶς κ., Phld.Po.5.15; “ἐναντίως ὑπὲρ τῶν αὐτῶν” Id.Oec.p.60 J.: —more
freq. in Pass., to be predicated of . . , τινος Arist.Cat.2a21, APr. 26b9, al.;
“κατά τινος” Id.Cat.2a37; “κατὰ παντὸς ἢ μηδενός” Id.APr.24a15: less freq. “ἐπί
τινος” Id.Metaph.998b16, 999a15; so later “ἐφ᾽ ἑνὸς οἴονται θεοῦ ἑκάτερον τῶν
ὀνομάτων -εῖσθαι” D.H.2.48; “περί τινος” Arist. Top.140b37; “τὸ κοινῇ -ούμενον
ἐπὶ πᾶσιν” Id.SE179a8: abs., τὸ κατηγορούμενον the
predicate, opp. τὸ ὑποκείμενον (the subject), Id.Cat.1b11,
cf.Metaph.1043a6, al.; κατηγορεῖν καὶ -εῖσθαι to be subject and predicate,
Id.APr.47b1. BANC.
prejudices: the life and opinions of H. P. Grice, by H.
P. Grice! PGRICE had been in the works for a while. Knowing this, Grice is able
to start his auto-biography, or memoir, to which he later adds a specific reply
to this or that objection by the editors. The reply is divided in neat
sections. After a preamble displaying his gratitude for the volume in
his honour, Grice turns to his prejudices and predilections; which become,
the life and opinions of H. P. Grice. The third section is a reply to the
editorss overview of his work. This reply itself is itself subdivided into
questions of meaning and rationality, and questions of Met. , philosophical
psychology, and value. As the latter is repr. in “Conception” it is possible to
cite this sub-section from the Reply as a separate piece. Grice originally
entitles his essay in a brilliant manner, echoing the style of an English
non-conformist, almost: Prejudices and predilections; which become, the life
and opinions of H. P. Grice. With his Richards, a nice Welsh surNames, Grice is
punning on the first Names of both Grandy and Warner. Grice is especially
concerned with what Richards see as an ontological commitment on Grices
part to the abstract, yet poorly individuated entity of a proposition. Grice
also deals with the alleged insufficiency in his conceptual analysis of
reasoning. He brings for good measure a point about a potential regressus ad
infinitum in his account of a chain of intentions involved in meaning that p
and communicating that p. Even if one of the drafts is titled festschrift, not
by himself, this is not strictly a festschrift in that Grices Names is hidden
behind the acronym: PGRICE. Notably on the philosophy of perception. Also in
“Conception,” especially that tricky third lecture on a metaphysical foundation
for objective value. Grice is supposed to reply to the individual
contributors, who include Strawson, but does not. I cancelled the implicaturum!
However, we may identify in his oeuvre points of contacts of his own views with
the philosophers who contributed, notably Strawson. Most of this material is
reproduced verbatim, indeed, as the second part of his Reply to Richards, and
it is a philosophical memoir of which Grice is rightly proud. The life and
opinions are, almost in a joke on Witters, distinctly separated. Under Life,
Grice convers his conservative, irreverent rationalism making his early initial
appearance at Harborne under the influence of his non-conformist father, and
fermented at his tutorials with Hardie at Corpus, and his associations with
Austins play group on Saturday mornings, and some of whose members he lists
alphabetically: Austin, Gardiner, Grice, Hampshire, Hare, Hart, Nowell-Smith,
Paul, Pears, Strawson, Thomson, Urmson, and Warnock. Also, his joint
philosophising with Austin, Pears, Strawson, Thomson, and Warnock. Under
Opinions, Grice expands mainly on ordinary-language philosophy and his
Bunyanesque way to the City of Eternal Truth. Met. , Philosophical
Psychology, and Value, in “Conception,” is thus part of his Prejudices and
predilections. The philosophers Grice quotes are many and varied, such as
Bosanquet and Kneale, and from the other place, Keynes. Grice spends some
delightful time criticising the critics of ordinary-language philosophy such as
Bergmann (who needs an English futilitarian?) and Gellner. He also quotes from
Jespersen, who was "not a philosopher but wrote a philosophy of
grammar!" And Grice includes a reminiscence of the bombshells brought from
Vienna by the enfant terrible of Oxford philosophy Freddie Ayer, after being
sent to the Continent by Ryle. He recalls an air marshal at a dinner with
Strawson at Magdalen relishing on Cook Wilsons adage, What we know we know. And
more besides! After reminiscing for Clarendon, Grice will go on to reminisce
for Harvard University Press in the closing section of the Retrospective
epilogue. Refs.: The main source is “Reply to Richards,” and references to
Oxonianism, and linguistic botanising, BANC.
prelatum --
anaphora: a device of reference or
cross-reference in which a term called an anaphor, typically a pronoun, has its
semantic properties determined by a term or noun phrase called the anaphor’s
antecedent that occurs earlier. Sometimes the antecedent is a proper name or
other independently referring expression, as in ‘Jill went up the hill and then
she came down again’. In such cases, the anaphor refers to the same object as
its antecedent. In other cases, the anaphor seems to function as a variable
bound by an antecedent quantifier, as in ‘If any miner bought a donkey, he is
penniless’. But anaphora is puzzling because not every example falls neatly
into one of these two groups. Thus, in ‘John owns some sheep and Harry
vaccinates them’ an example due to Gareth Evans the anaphor is arguably not
bound by its antecedent ‘some sheep’. And in ‘Every miner who owns a donkey
beats it’ a famous type of case discovered by Geach, the anaphor is arguably
neither bound by ‘a donkey’ nor a uniquely referring expression.
predicables, also praedicabilia, sometimes called the
quinque voces five words, in medieval philosophy, genus, species, difference,
proprium, and accident, the five main ways general predicates can be
predicated. The list comes from Porphyry’s Isagoge. It was debated whether it
applies to linguistic predicates only or also to extralinguistic universals.
Things that have accidents can exist without them; other predicables belong
necessarily to whatever has them. The Aristotelian/Porphyrian notion of
“inseparable accident” blurs this picture. Genus and species are natural kinds;
other predicables are not. A natural kind that is not a narrowest natural kind
is a genus; one that is not a broadest natural kind is a species. Some genera
are also species. A proprium is not a species, but is coextensive with one. A
difference belongs necessarily to whatever has it, but is neither a natural
kind nor coextensive with one.
Pre-existence, existence of the individual soul or
psyche prior to its current embodiment, when the soul or psyche is taken to be
separable and capable of existing independently from its embodiment. The
current embodiment is then often described as a reincarnation of the soul.
Plato’s Socrates refers to such a doctrine several times in the dialogues,
notably in the myth of Er in Book X of the Republic. The doctrine is
distinguished from two other teachings about the soul: creationism, which holds
that the individual human soul is directly created by God, and traducianism,
which held that just as body begets body in biological generation, so the soul
of the new human being is begotten by the parental soul. In Hinduism, the cycle
of reincarnations represents the period of estrangement and trial for the soul
or Atman before it achieves release moksha.
prescriptivism, the theory that evaluative judgments
necessarily have prescriptive meaning. Associated with noncognitivism and moral
antirealism, prescriptivism holds that moral language is such that, if you say
that you think one ought to do a certain kind of act, and yet you are not
committed to doing that kind of act in the relevant circumstances, then you
either spoke insincerely or are using the word ‘ought’ in a less than
full-blooded sense. Prescriptivism owes its stature to Hare. One of his
innovations is the distinction between “secondarily evaluative” and “primarily
evaluative” words. The prescriptive meaning of secondarily evaluative words,
such as ‘soft-hearted’ or ‘chaste’, may vary significantly while their
descriptive meanings stay relatively constant. Hare argues the reverse for the
primarily evaluative words ‘good’, ‘bad’, ‘right’, ‘wrong’, ‘ought’, and
‘must’. For example, some people assign to ‘wrong’ the descriptive meaning
‘forbidden by God’, others assign it the descriptive meaning ‘causes social
conflict’, and others give it different descriptive meanings; but since all use
‘wrong’ with the same prescriptive meaning, they are using the same concept. In
part to show how moral judgments can be prescriptive and yet have the same
logical relations as indicative sentences, Hare distinguished between phrastics
and neustics. The phrastic, or content, can be the same in indicative and
prescriptive sentences; e.g., ‘Sam’s leaving’ is the phrastic not only of the
indicative ‘Sam will leave’ but also of the prescription ‘Sam ought to leave’.
Hare’s Language of Morals 2 specified that the neustic indicates mood, i.e.,
whether the sentence is indicative, imperative, interrogative, etc. However, in
an article in Mind 9 and in Sorting Out Ethics 7, he used ‘neustic’ to refer to
the sign of subscription, and ‘tropic’ to refer to the sign of mood. Prescriptivity
is especially important if moral judgments are universalizable. For then we can
employ golden rulestyle moral reasoning.
pre-Socratics: cf. pre-Griceians. the early Grecian
philosophers who were not influenced by Socrates. Generally they lived before
Socrates, but some are contemporary with him or even younger. The
classification though not the term goes back to Aristotle, who saw Socrates’
humanism and emphasis on ethical issues as a watershed in the history of
philosophy. Aristotle rightly noted that philosophers prior to Socrates had
stressed natural philosophy and cosmology rather than ethics. He credited them
with discovering material principles and moving causes of natural events, but
he criticized them for failing to stress structural elements of things formal
causes and values or purposes final causes. Unfortunately, no writing of any
pre-Socratic survives in more than a fragmentary form, and evidence of their
views is thus often indirect, based on reports or criticisms of later writers.
In order to reconstruct pre-Socratic thought, scholars have sought to collect
testimonies of ancient sources and to identify quotations from the preSocratics
in those sources. As modern research has revealed flaws in the interpretations
of ancient witnesses, it has become a principle of exegesis to base
reconstructions of their views on the actual words of the pre-Socratics
themselves wherever possible. Because of the fragmentary and derivative nature
of our evidence, even basic principles of a philosopher’s system sometimes
remain controversial; nevertheless, we can say that thanks to modern methods of
historiography, there are many points we understand better than ancient
witnesses who are our secondary sources. Our best ancient secondary source is
Aristotle, who lived soon after the pre-Socratics and had access to most of
their writings. He interprets his predecessors from the standpoint of his own
theory; but any historian must interpret philosophers in light of some
theoretical background. Since we have extensive writings of Aristotle, we understand his system and can filter out his
own prejudices. His colleague Theophrastus was the first professional historian
of philosophy. Adopting Aristotle’s general framework, he systematically
discussed pre-Socratic theories. Unfortunately his work itself is lost, but
many fragments and summaries of parts of it remain. Indeed, virtually all
ancient witnesses writing after Theophrastus depend on him for their general
understanding of the early philosophers, sometimes by way of digests of his
work. When biography became an important genre in later antiquity, biographers
collected facts, anecdotes, slanders, chronologies often based on crude a
priori assumptions, lists of book titles, and successions of school directors,
which provide potentially valuable information. By reconstructing ancient
theories, we can trace the broad outlines of pre-Socratic development with some
confidence. The first philosophers were the Milesians, philosophers of Miletus
on the Ionian coast of Asia Minor, who in the sixth century B.C. broke away
from mythological modes of explanation by accounting for all phenomena, even
apparent prodigies of nature, by means of simple physical hypotheses. Aristotle
saw the Milesians as material monists, positing a physical substrate of water, or the apeiron, or air; but their
material source was probably not a continuing substance that underlies all
changes as Aristotle thought, but rather an original stuff that was transformed
into different stuffs. Pythagoras migrated from Ionia to southern Italy,
founding a school of Pythagoreans who believed that souls transmigrated and
that number was the basis of all reality. Because Pythagoras and his early
followers did not publish anything, it is difficult to trace their development
and influence in detail. Back in Ionia, Heraclitus criticized Milesian
principles because he saw that if substances changed into one another, the
process of transformation was more important than the substances that appeared
in the cycle of changes. He thus chose the unstable substance fire as his
material principle and stressed the unity of opposites. Parmenides and the
Eleatic School criticized the notion of notbeing that theories of physical
transformations seemed to presuppose. One cannot even conceive of or talk of
not-being; hence any conception that presupposes not-being must be ruled out.
But the basic notions of coming-to-be, differentiation, and indeed change in
general presuppose not-being, and thus must be rejected. Eleatic analysis leads
to the further conclusion, implicit in Parmenides, explicit in Melissus, that
there is only one substance, what-is. Since this substance does not come into
being or change in any way, nor does it have any internal differentiations, the
world is just a single changeless, homogeneous individual. Parmenides’ argument
seems to undermine the foundations of natural philosophy. After Parmenides
philosophers who wished to continue natural philosophy felt compelled to grant
that coming-to-be and internal differentiation of a given substance were
impossible. But in order to accommodate natural processes, they posited a
plurality of unchanging, homogeneous elements
the four elements of Empedocles, the elemental stuffs of Anaxagoras, the
atoms of Democritus that by arrangement
and rearrangement could produce the cosmos and the things in it. There is no
real coming-to-be and perishing in the world since the ultimate substances are
everlasting; but some limited kind of change such as chemical combination or mixture
or locomotion could account for changing phenomena in the world of experience.
Thus the “pluralists” incorporated Eleatic principles into their systems while
rejecting the more radical implications of the Eleatic critique. Pre-Socratic
philosophers developed more complex systems as a response to theoretical
criticisms. They focused on cosmology and natural philosophy in general,
championing reason and nature against mythological traditions. Yet the
pre-Socratics have been criticized both for being too narrowly scientific in
interest and for not being scientific experimental enough. While there is some
justice in both criticisms, their interests showed breadth as well as
narrowness, and they at least made significant conceptual progress in providing
a framework for scientific and philosophical ideas. While they never developed
sophisticated theories of ethics, logic, epistemology, or metaphysics, nor
invented experimental methods of confirmation, they did introduce the concepts
that ultimately became fundamental in modern theories of cosmic, biological,
and cultural evolution, as well as in atomism, genetics, and social contract
theory. Because the Socratic revolution turned philosophy in different
directions, the pre-Socratic line died out. But the first philosophers supplied
much inspiration for the sophisticated fourthcentury systems of Plato and
Aristotle as well as the basic principles of the great Hellenistic schools,
Epicureanism, Stoicism, and Skepticism.
presupposition, 1 a relation between sentences or
statements, related to but distinct from entailment and assertion; 2 what a
speaker takes to be understood in making an assertion. The first notion is
semantic, the second pragmatic. The semantic notion was introduced by Strawson
in his attack on Russell’s theory of descriptions, and perhaps anticipated by
Frege. Strawson argued that ‘The present king of France is bald’ does not
entail ‘There is a present king of France’ as Russell held, but instead
presupposes it. Semantic presupposition can be defined thus: a sentence or
statement S presupposes a sentence or statement SH provided S entails SH and
the negation of S also entails SH . SH is a condition of the truth or falsity
of S. Thus, since ‘There is a present king of France’ is false, ‘The present
king of France is bald’ is argued to be neither true nor false. So construed,
presupposition is defined in terms of, but is distinct from, entailment. It is
also distinct from assertion, since it is viewed as a precondition of the truth
or falsity of what is asserted. The pragmatic conception does not appeal to
truth conditions, but instead contrasts what a speaker presupposes and what
that speaker asserts in making an utterance. Thus, someone who utters ‘The
present king of France is bald’ presupposes
believes and believes that the audience believes that there is a present king of France, and
asserts that this king is bald. So conceived, presuppositions are beliefs that
the speaker takes for granted; if these beliefs are false, the utterance will
be inappropriate in some way, but it does not follow that the sentence uttered
lacks a truth-value. These two notions of presupposition are logically
independent. On the semantic characterization, presupposition is a relation
between sentences or statements requiring that there be truth-value gaps. On
the pragmatic characterization, it is speakers rather than sentences or
statements that have presuppositions; no truth-value gaps are required. Many
philosophers and linguists have argued for treating what have been taken to be
cases of semantic presupposition, including the one discussed above, as
pragmatic phenomena. Some have denied that semantic presuppositions exist. If
not, intuitions about presupposition do not support the claims that natural
languages have truth-value gaps and that we need a three-valued logic to
represent the semantics of natural language adequately. Presupposition is also
distinct from implicaturum. If someone reports that he has just torn his coat
and you say, “There’s a tailor shop around the corner,” you conversationally
implicate that the shop is open. This is not a semantic presupposition because
if it is false that the shop is open, there is no inclination to say that your
assertion was neither true nor false. It is not a pragmatic presupposition
because it is not something you believe the hearer believes.
pretheoretical, independent of theory. More
specifically, a proposition is pretheoretical, according to some philosophers,
if and only if it does not depend for its plausibility or implausibility on
theoretical considerations or considerations of theoretical analysis. The term
‘preanalytic’ is often used synonymously with ‘pretheoretical’, but the former
is more properly paired with analysis rather than with theory. Some philosophers
characterize pretheoretical propositions as “intuitively” plausible or
implausible. Such propositions, they hold, can regulate philosophical
theorizing as follows: in general, an adequate philosophical theory should not
conflict with intuitively plausible propositions by implying intuitively
implausible propositions, and should imply intuitively plausible propositions.
Some philosophers grant that theoretical considerations can override
“intuitions” in the sense of intuitively
plausible propositions when overall
theoretical coherence or reflective equilibrium is thereby enhanced.
prescriptum: prescriptivism. According to Grice’s prescriptive
meta-ethics, by uttering ‘p,’ the emissor may intend his recipient to entertain
a desiderative state of content ‘p.’ In which case, the emissor is
‘prescribing’ a course of conduct. As opposed to the ‘descriptum,’ which just
depicts a ‘state’ of affairs that the emissor wants to inform his recipient
about. Surely there are for Grice at
least two different modes, the buletic, which tends towards the prescriptive,
and the doxastic, which is mostly ‘descriptive.’ One has to be careful because
Grice thinks that what a philosopher like Strawson does with ‘descriptive’
expression (like ‘true,’ ‘know’ and ‘good’) and talk of pseudo-descriptive. What
is that gives the buletic a ‘prescritive’ or deontic ring to it? This is Kant’s
question. Grice kept a copy of Foots on morality as a system of hypothetical
imperatives. “So Somervillian Oxonian it hurts!”. Grice took virtue ethics more
seriously than the early Hare. Hare will end up a virtue ethicist, since he
changed from a meta-ethicist to a moralist embracing a hedonistic version of
eudaemonist utilitarianism. Grice was more Aristotelianly conservative! Unlike
Hares and Grices meta-ethical sensitivities (as members of the Oxonian school
of ordinary-language philosophy), Foot suggests a different approach to ethics.
Grice admired Foots ability to make the right conceptual distinction. Foot
is following a very Oxonian tradition best represented by the work of
Warnock. Of course, Grice was over-familiar with the virtue vs. vice
distinction, since Hardie had instilled it on him at Corpus! For Grice,
virtue and vice (and the mesotes), display an interesting logical grammar,
though. Grice would say that rationality is a virtue; fallacious reasoning is a
vice. Some things Grice takes more of a moral standpoint about. To cheat
is neither irrational nor unreasonble: just plain repulsive. As
such, it would be a vice ‒ mind not getting caught in its grip! Grice is
concerned with vice in his account of akrasia or incontinentia. If agent A
KNOWS that doing x is virtuous, yet decides to do ~x, which is vicious, A is
being akratic. For Grice, akratic behaviour applies both in the buletic or
boulomaic realm and in the doxastic realm. And it is part of the
philosopher’s job to elucidate the conceptual intricacies attached to
it. 1. prima-facie (p⊃!q)
V probably (p⊃q). 2.
prima-facie ((A and B) ⊃!p) V probably ( (A and B) ⊃p). 3. prima-facie
((A and B and C) ⊃!p)
V probably ( (A and B and C,) ⊃p). 4. prima-facie ((all things before P V!p) V
probably ((all things before P) ⊃ p). 5. prima-facie ((all things are
considered ⊃ !p)
V probably (all things are considered, ⊃ p). 6. !q V .q 7. Acc. Reasoning P
wills that !q V Acc. Reasoning P that judges q. Refs.: The main sources under
‘meta-ethics,’ above, BANC.
Price, Richard 172391, Welsh Dissenting minister,
actuary, and moral philosopher. His main work, A Review of the Principal
Question in Morals 1758, is a defense of rationalism in ethics. He argued that
the understanding immediately perceives simple, objective, moral qualities of
actions. The resulting intuitive knowledge of moral truths is accompanied by
feelings of approval and disapproval responsible for moral motivation. He also
wrote influential papers on life expectancy, public finance, and annuities;
communicated to the Royal Society the paper by his deceased friend Thomas Bayes
containing Bayes’s theorem; and defended the
and revolutions. Burke’s
Reflections on the Revolution in France is a response to one of Price’s
sermons.
Prichard: h. a. – H. P. Grice called himself a
neo-Prichardian, but then “I used to be a neo-Stoutian before that!” -- English
philosopher and founder of the Oxford school of intuitionism. An Oxford fellow
and professor, he published Kant’s Theory of Knowledge 9 and numerous essays,
collected in Moral Obligation 9, 8 and in Knowledge and Perception 0. Prichard
was a realist in his theory of knowledge, following Cook Wilson. He held that
through direct perception in concrete cases we obtain knowledge of universals
and of necessary connections between them, and he elaborated a theory about our
knowledge of material objects. In “Does Moral Philosophy Rest on a Mistake?” 2
he argued powerfully that it is wrong to think that a general theory of
obligation is possible. No single principle captures the various reasons why
obligatory acts are obligatory. Only by direct perception in particular cases
can we see what we ought to do. With this essay Prichard founded the Oxford
school of intuitionism, carried on by, among others, Ross.
Priestley, J.: British philosopher. In 1774 he prepared
oxygen by heating mercuric oxide. Although he continued to favor the phlogiston
hypothesis, his work did much to discredit that idea. He discovered many gases,
including ammonia, sulfur dioxide, carbon monoxide, and hydrochloric acid.
While studying the layer of carbon dioxide over a brewing vat, he conceived the
idea of dissolving it under pressure. The resulting “soda water” was famous
throughout Europe. His Essay on Government 1768 influenced Jefferson’s ideas in
the Declaration of Independence. The
essay also contributed to the utilitarianism of Bentham, supplying the phrase
“the greatest happiness of the greatest number.” Priestley modified the
associationism of Locke, Hume, and Hartley, holding that a sharp distinction
must be drawn between the results of association in forming natural
propensities and its effects on the development of moral ideas. On the basis of
this distinction, he argued, against Hume, that differences in individual moral
sentiments are results of education, through the association of ideas, a view
anticipated by Helvétius. Priestley served as minister to anti-Establishment
congregations. His unpopular stress on individual freedom resulted in his move
to Pennsylvania, where he spent his last years.
prime mover, the original source and cause of motion
change in the universe an idea that was
developed by Aristotle and became important in Judaic, Christian, and Islamic
thought about God. According to Aristotle, something that is in motion a
process of change is moving from a state of potentiality to a state of
actuality. For example, water that is being heated is potentially hot and in
the process of becoming actually hot. If a cause of change must itself actually
be in the state that it is bringing about, then nothing can produce motion in
itself; whatever is in motion is being moved by another. For otherwise
something would be both potentially and actually in the same state. Thus, the
water that is potentially hot can become hot only by being changed by something
else the fire that is actually hot. The prime mover, the original cause of
motion, must itself, therefore, not be in motion; it is an unmoved mover.
Aquinas and other theologians viewed God as the prime mover, the ultimate cause
of all motion. Indeed, for these theologians the argument to establish the
existence of a first mover, itself unmoved, was a principal argument used in
their efforts to prove the existence of God on the basis of reason. Many modern
thinkers question the argument for a first mover on the ground that it does not
seem to be logically impossible that the motion of one thing be caused by a
second thing whose motion in turn is caused by a third thing, and so on without
end. Defenders of the argument claim that it presupposes a distinction between
two different causal series, one temporal and one simultaneous, and argue that
the objection succeeds only against a temporal causal series.
PRIMA PHILOSOPHIA -- first philosophy, in Aristotle’s
Metaphysics, the study of being qua being, including the study of theology as
understood by him, since the divine is being par excellence. Descartes’s
Meditations on First Philosophy was concerned chiefly with the existence of
God, the immortality of the soul, and the nature of matter and of the mind.
Prince Maurice’s
parrot: The ascription of
‘that’-clause in the report of a communicatum by a pirot of stage n-1 may be a
problem by a priot in stage n. Do we want to say that the parrot communicates
that he finds Prince Maurice an idiot? While some may not be correct that
Griciean principles can be explained on practical, utilitarian grounds, Grice’s
main motivation is indeed to capture the ‘rational’ capacity. Since I think I
may be confident, that, whoever should see a creature of his own shape or make,
though it had no more reason all its life than a cat or a parrot, would call
him still a man; or whoever should hear a cat or a parrot discourse, reason,
and philosophize, would call or think it nothing but a cat or a parrot; and
say, the one was a dull irrational man, and the other a very intelligent
rational parrot. A relation we have in an author of great note, is sufficient
to countenance the supposition of a rational parrot. His words are: "I had
a mind to know, from Prince Maurice's own mouth, the account of a common, but
much credited story, that I had heard so often from many others, of an old
parrot he had in Brazil, during his government there, that spoke, and asked,
and answered common questions, like a reasonable creature: so that those of his
train there generally concluded it to be witchery or possession; and one of his
chaplains, who lived long afterwards in Holland, would never from that time
endure a parrot, but said they all had a devil in them. I had heard many
particulars of this story, and as severed by people hard to be discredited,
which made me ask Prince Maurice what there was of it. He said, with his usual
plainness and dryness in talk, there was something true, but a great deal false
of what had been reported. I desired to know of him what there was of the
first. He told me short and coldly, that he had heard of such an old parrot
when he had been at Brazil; and though he believed nothing of it, and it was a
good way off, yet he had so much curiosity as to send for it: that it was a
very great and a very old one; and when it came first into the room where the
prince was, with a great many Dutchmen about him, it said presently, What a
company of white men are here! They asked it, what it thought that man was,
pointing to the prince. It answered, Some General or other. When they brought
it close to him, he asked it, D'ou venez-vous? It answered, De Marinnan. The
Prince, A qui estes-vous? The Parrot, A un Portugais. The Prince, Que fais-tu
la? Parrot, Je garde les poulles. The Prince laughed, and said, Vous gardez les
poulles? The Parrot answered, Oui, moi; et je scai bien faire; and made the
chuck four or five times that people use to make to chickens when they call
them. I set down the words of this worthy dialogue in French, just as Prince
Maurice said them to me. I asked him in what language the parrot spoke, and he
said in Brazilian. I asked whether he understood Brazilian; he said No, but he
had taken care to have two interpreters by him, the one a Dutchman that spoke
Brazilian, and the other a Brazilian that spoke Dutch; that he asked them
separately and privately, and both of them agreed in telling him just the same
thing that the parrot had said. I could not but tell this odd story, because it
is so much out of the way, and from the first hand, and what may pass for a
good one; for I dare say this Prince at least believed himself in all he told
me, having ever passed for a very honest and pious man: I leave it to
naturalists to reason, and to other men to believe, as they please upon it;
however, it is not, perhaps, amiss to relieve or enliven a busy scene sometimes
with such digressions, whether to the purpose or no." I have taken care
that the reader should have the story at large in the author's own words,
because he seems to me not to have thought it incredible; for it cannot be
imagined that so able a man as he, who had sufficiency enough to warrant all
the testimonies he gives of himself, should take so much pains, in a place
where it had nothing to do, to pin so close, not only on a man whom he mentions
as his friend, but on a Prince in whom he acknowledges very great honesty and
piety, a story which, if he himself thought incredible, he could not but also
think ridiculous. The Prince, it is plain, who vouches this story, and our
author, who relates it from him, both of them call this talker a parrot: and I
ask any one else who thinks such a story fit to be told, whether, if this
parrot, and all of its kind, had always talked, as we have a prince's word for
it this one did,- whether, I say, they would not have passed for a race of
rational animals; but yet, whether, for all that, they would have been allowed
to be men, and not parrots? For I presume it is not the idea of a thinking or
rational being alone that makes the idea of a man in most people's sense: but
of a body, so and so shaped, joined to it: and if that be the idea of a man,
the same successive body not shifted all at once, must, as well as the same
immaterial spirit, go to the making of the same man.
principle of
economy of rational effort: (principium
oeconomiae effortis rationalis). Cf. his metaphor of the hamburger. Grice knew
that ‘economy’ is vague. It relates to the ‘open house.’ But is a crucial
concept. It is not the principle of parsimony of rational effort. It is not the
principle of ‘minimisaation’ of rational effort. It is the principle of the
‘economy’ of rational effort. ‘Economy’ is already a value-oriented word, since
it is a branch of politics and meta-ethics. oecŏnŏmĭcus , a, um, adj., =
οἰκονομικός. I. Of or relating to domestic economy; subst.: oecŏnŏmĭcus , i,
m., a work of Xenophon on domestic economy. in eo libro, qui Oeconomicus
inscribitur, Cic. Off. 2, 24, 87; Gell. 15, 5, 8.— II. Of or belonging to a proper
(oratorical) division or arrangement; orderly, methodical: “oeconomica totius
causae dispositio,” Quint. 7, 10, 11. οἰκονομ-ικός
, ή, όν, A.practised in the management of a household or family, opp.
πολιτικός, Pl.Alc.1.133e, Phdr.248d, X.Oec.1.3, Arist.Pol.1252a8, etc. : Sup.,
[κτημάτων] τὸ βέλτιστον καὶ-ώτατον, of man, Phld.Oec.p.30 J. : hence, thrifty,
frugal, economical, X.Mem.4.2.39, Phylarch.65 J. (Comp.) : ὁ οἰ. title of
treatise on the duties of domestic life, by Xenophon ; and τὰ οἰ. title of treatise
on public finance, ascribed to Aristotle, cf. X.Cyr.8.1.14 : ἡ -κή (sc. τέχνη)
domestic economy, husbandry, Pl.Plt.259c, X.Mem. 3.4.11, etc. ; οἰ. ἀρχή
defined as ἡ τέκνων ἀρχὴ καὶ γυναικὸς καὶ τῆς οἰκίας πάσης, Arist.Pol.1278b38 ;
applied to patriarchal rule, ib.1285b32. Adv.“-κῶς” Ph.2.426, Plu.2.1126a ;
also in literary sense, in a well ordered manner, Sch.Th.1.63. Grice’s
conversational maximin. Blackburn draws a skull to communicate that there is
danger. The skull complete with the rest of the body will not do. So abiding by
this principle has nothing to do with an arbitrary convention. Vide principle
of least conversational effort. Principle of conversational least effort. No
undue effort (candour), no unnecessary trouble (self-love) if doing A involves
too much conversational effort, never worry: you will be DEEMED to have made
the effort. Invoked by Grice in “Prejudices and predilections; which become,
the life and opinions of H. P. Grice.” When Grice qualifies this as ‘rational’
effort, what other efforts are there? Note that the lexeme ‘effort’ does NOT
feature in the formulation of the principle itself. Grice confesses to be strongly
inclined to assent to the principle of economy of rational conversational effort
or the principle of economy of conversational effort, or the principle of
economy of conversational expenditure, or the principle of minimisation of
rational expenditure, or the principle of minimization of conversational
expenditure, or the principle of minimisation of rational cost, or the
conversational maximin. The principle of least cost. The principle of economy
of rational expenditure states that, where there is a ratiocinative procedure
for arriving rationally at certain outcome, a procedure which, because it is
ratiocinative, involves an expenditure of time and energy, if there is a NON-ratiocinative,
and so more economical procedure which is likely, for the most part, to reach
the same outcome as the ratiocinative procedure, provided the stakes are not
too high, it is rational to employ the cheaper though somewhat less reliable
non-ratiocinative procedure as a substitute for ratiocination. Grice thinks
this principle would meet with genitorial approval, in which case the genitor
would install it for use should opportunity arise. This applies to the charge
of overcomplexity and ‘psychological irreality’ of the reasoning involved in
the production and design of the maximally efficient conversational move and
the reasoning involved in the recognition of the implicaturum by the addressee.
In “Epilogue” he goes by yet another motto, Do not multiply rationalities
beyond necessity: The principle of conversational rationality, as he calls it
in the Epilogue, is a sub-principle of a principle of rationality simpiciter,
not applying to a pursuit related to ‘communication,’ as he puts it.
principium individuationis, the cause or basis of
individuality in individuals; what makes something individual as opposed to
universal, e.g., what makes the cat Minina individual and thus different from
the universal, cat. Questions regarding the principle of individuation were
first raised explicitly in the early Middle Ages. Classical authors largely
ignored individuation; their ontological focus was on the problem of
universals. The key texts that originated the discussion of the principle of
individuation are found in Boethius. Between Boethius and 1150, individuation
was always discussed in the context of more pressing issues, particularly the
problem of universals. After 1150, individuation slowly emerged as a focus of
attention, so that by the end of the thirteenth century it had become an
independent subject of discussion, especially in Aquinas and Duns Scotus. Most
early modern philosophers conceived the problem of individuation epistemically
rather than metaphysically; they focused on the discernibility of individuals
rather than the cause of individuation, as in Descartes. With few exceptions,
such as Karl Popper, the twentieth century has followed this epistemic approach
e. g. P. F. Strawson.
principle of bivalence, the principle that any
significant statement is either true or false. It is often confused with the
principle of excluded middle. Letting ‘Tp’ stand for ‘p is true’ and ‘Tp’ for
‘p is false’ and otherwise using standard logical notation, bivalence is ‘Tp 7
T-p’ and excluded middle is ‘T p 7 -p’. That they are different principles is
shown by the fact that in probability theory, where ‘Tp’ can be expressed as
‘Prp % 1’, bivalence ‘Pr p % 1 7 Pr ~p % 1’ is not true for all values of p e.g. it is not true where ‘p’ stands for
‘given a fair toss of a fair die, the result will be a six’ a statement with a
probability of 1 /6, where -p has a probability of 5 /6 but excluded middle ‘Prp 7 -p % 1’ is true
for all definite values of p, including the probability case just given. If we
allow that some significant statements have no truth-value or probability and
distinguish external negation ‘Tp’ from internal negation ‘T-p’, we can
distinguish bivalence and excluded middle from the principle of
non-contradiction, namely, ‘-Tp • T-p’, which is equivalent to ‘-Tp 7 -T-p’.
Standard truth-functional logic sees no difference between ‘p’ and ‘Tp’, or
‘-Tp’ and ‘T-p’, and thus is unable to distinguish the three principles. Some
philosophers of logic deny there is such a difference.
principle of contradiction, also called principle of
non-contradiction, the principle that a statement and its negation cannot both
be true. It can be distinguished from the principle of bivalence, and given
certain controversial assumptions, from the principle of excluded middle; but
in truth-functional logic all three are regarded as equivalent. Outside of
formal logic the principle of non-contradiction is best expressed as Aristotle
expresses it: “Nothing can both be and not be at the same time in the same
respect.”
principle of double effect, the view that there is a
morally relevant difference between those consequences of our actions we intend
and those we do not intend but do still foresee. According to the principle, if
increased literacy means a higher suicide rate, those who work for education
are not guilty of driving people to kill themselves. A physician may give a
patient painkillers foreseeing that they will shorten his life, even though the
use of outright poisons is forbidden and the physician does not intend to
shorten the patient’s life. An army attacking a legitimate military target may
accept as inevitable, without intending to bring about, the deaths of a number
of civilians. Traditional moral theologians affirmed the existence of
exceptionless prohibitions such as that against taking an innocent human life,
while using the principle of double effect to resolve hard cases and avoid
moral blind alleys. They held that one may produce a forbidden effect, provided
1 one’s action also had a good effect, 2 one did not seek the bad effect as an
end or as a means, 3 one did not produce the good effect through the bad
effect, and 4 the good effect was important enough to outweigh the bad one.
Some contemporary philosophers and Roman Catholic theologians hold that a
modified version of the principle of double effect is the sole justification of
deadly deeds, even when the person killed is not innocent. They drop any
restriction on the causal sequence, so that e.g. it is legitimate to cut off
the head of an unborn child to save the mother’s life. But they oppose capital
punishment on the ground that those who inflict it require the death of the
convict as part of their plan. They also play down the fourth requirement, on
the ground that the weighing of incommensurable goods it requires is
impossible. Consequentialists deny the principle of double effect, as do those
for whom the crucial distinction is between what we cause by our actions and
what just happens. In the most plausible view, the principle does not
presuppose exceptionless moral prohibitions, only something stronger than prima
facie duties. It is easier to justify an oblique evasion of a moral requirement
than a direct violation, even if direct violations are sometimes permissible.
So understood, the principle is a guide to prudence rather than a substitute
for it.
principle of excluded middle, the principle that the
disjunction of any significant statement with its negation is always true;
e.g., ‘Either there is a tree over 500 feet tall or it is not the case that
there is such a tree’. The principle is often confused with the principle of
bivalence.
principle of indifference, a rule for assigning a
probability to an event based on “parity of reasons.” According to the
principle, when the “weight of reasons” favoring one event is equal to the
“weight of reasons” favoring another, the two events should be assigned the
same probability. When there are n mutually exclusive and collectively
exhaustive events, and there is no reason to favor one over another, then we
should be “indifferent” and the n events should each be assigned probability
1/n the events are equiprobable, according to the principle. This principle is
usually associated with the names Bernoulli Ars Conjectandi, 1713 and Laplace
Théorie analytique des probabilités, 1812, and was so called by J. M. Keynes A
Treatise on Probability, 1. The principle gives probability both a subjective
“degree of belief” and a logical “partial logical entailment” interpretation.
One rationale for the principle says that in ignorance, when no reasons favor
one event over another, we should assign equal probabilities. It has been
countered that any assignment of probabilities at all is a claim to some
knowledge. Also, several seemingly natural applications of the principle,
involving non-linearly related variables, have led to some mathematical
contradictions, known as Bertrand’s paradox, and pointed out by Keynes.
No comments:
Post a Comment