If you try to study the 'philosophy of mind' (or philosophical psychology, as Grice prefers) of the Oxford Play Group to which Grice belonged (Grice, Austin, Strawson, Hampshire, Hare) you fail --. I do have Pears, "Questions in the philosophy of mind" (He was also a member of the group) and Hamsphire, "Philosophy of mind" volume, and a few others --. The opus magnum by Grice here is "Method in philosophical psychology". But there is nothing really that UNIFIES THEM.
In "Method" Grice refers to Ryle. Ryle, as per "The concept of mind", was labelled a 'behaviourist' or 'analytic behaviourist'. No ghost in the machine, and the rest of it. But what are Grice's criticisms?
Grice's criticisms are subtle. He does not find a good argument FOR 'analytic' behaviourism. It's not that Grice wants to rehabilitate dualism. Rather, Grice proposes to treat 'psychological concepts' as theoretical concepts. His approach follows proposals by D. K. Lewis, and before him, Aristotle ("De anima").
So, the behaviourist (under which label we can also place Wittgenstein, that Grice quotes quite a bit in "Method" -- "no psychological predicate without the behaviour that manifests it" -- from "Philosophical Investigations") is claiming that there is no need to EXPLAIN psychological concepts because there are no such.
Alla Paul, "Is there a problem about sense data?". Is there a problem about 'the concept of mind'. Only if you are confused.
The type of proposal by Grice is labelled 'functionalist', rather, alla D. K. Lewis and Aristotle. It is based on the Turing black box thing. There are
perceptual input ------ i.
and
behavioural output ---- o
In between, there is the black box, which Grice symbolises by
Ψ
---
"Ψ" is a psychological predicate. The logic is dyadic. Sort of. Consider:
"... believes ..."
or as Grice prefers, '... accepts ...' (he wants a concept that is general enough to stand for 'believes' and 'desires').
'... accepts ...' holds between an agent, A,
so that Ψ becomes
ΨA
but that's one argument. If it's dyadic there must be another argument. Here Grice introduces the 'that'-clause. What follows "... acccepts". John accepts that the cat is on the mat.
This yields the form of a psychological ascription (the ascription of a propositional attitude or psychological attitude in Russellian parlance) to be:
ΨAp
But this is the 'propositional' logic level. We need to consider 'predicate logic'. "The cat is on the mat" (Ex)Cx & Mx.
So, the minimal propositional or psychological ascription becomes:
ΨA(Ex)Cx & Mx.
But you knew that!
----
Once we are able to work with these formulae, we see the corollaries. If an utterer utters, "The cat is on the mat" (or the king of France is bald) he presupposes or implicates that he believes there is a cat (or a king of France). So we can play with these sort of 'folk-psychological' laws:
ΨA(Ex)Cx & Mx ---> ΨA(Ex)Cx
and so on.
Or consider
A accepts that p
A accepts that if p, q
Therefore, A accepts q.
The way to go here is via principles of that sort alla Loar, Mind and Meaning, or Harman, Principles of Reasoning -- both Griceans, they.
---
At this point, we see that the larger ontological issue is only of mere academic concern for Grice. His proposal requires that we are able to work with psychological attitudes of a certain rich, or rather fine-grained, type.
Skinner's, or Watson's, or Ryle's type of behaviourism would not foot the bill in that respect.
Grice was enough of a naturalist NOT to be want to disassociate 'mind' from the rest -- so anything like Chomsky's "Cartesian Linguistics" and dualisms as such were a no-no.
By the time Chomsky tried to keep up with philosophers of mind, philosophers of mind were into very convoluted types of type-token identity theories alla Smart -- that Grice also considers. In this respect, Grice comes out as a non-reductionist. And so, his criticisms of Ryle's and other types of behaviourism strikes back with a vengeance.
But Grice's rejection of 'monism' (or behaviourism) remains methodological. He wants to say that if a folk-psychological theory 'instantiates' generalisations where the psi-operator occurs, this means that there IS a level of psychological explanation that is NOT, merely, a physicalist explanation of the type that the behaviourist is committed to.
Grice will also want to say that most behaviourists are NOT physicalist enough. He would mention that most descriptions of 'behaviour' are already 'loaded' with 'psychological' notions. "He approached me". "He moved towards me". -- is one of his examples. From Wittgenstein. Even our 'behaviourist' talk is imbued with psychologis. Or so Grice thought.
The panorama vis a vis Morris, Peirce, and "Unified Science", would perhaps present yet another problem with Grice. And he would ultimately recourse to issues like the ones mentioned by J -- we don't want 'robots'. We need free-willing agents and so on. At this point he would use 'practical arguments' to show that a mechanical reduction is the standard rejection of libertarianism. But we need libertarianism. Practical arguments are for Grice metaphysical arguments. Or rather, metaphysical arguments deal with the practical side of our thought products. Just because we don't want to commit to mechanism, we prove, eschatologically, that mechanism is a sort of minimalism that we need not buy. Supposing they were selling it. Or something.
Monday, August 9, 2010
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
So you say on one hand, behaviorism holds (which certainly hints at mechanistic determinism), and oppose any hints of a Cartesian mind (or Kantian mind...sort of extending RD), yet you also say, but we need not be mechanists about it. Rather difficult to reconcile ...
ReplyDeleteI don't worship Searle but he offered a nearly funny anecdote re "bad behaviorism": what does strict determinism mean say in regard to...voting? (and other "decisions") Wouldn't a person automatically sort of choose something, just stare at the ticket and then, bot-like, just swipe at it? Whats the difference between the doctor's vote, and the transient's for that matter....something like..deliberation is occurring, JL--that inference seems "rather warranted". A person reflects on the issues, and makes...decisions. That doesn't necessarily mean...the free Mind floats in some platonic or theological abode. But it might imply ...nature (and human neurology) has more mysteries than many a behaviorist thinks. Another reason I haven't quite put Kant's First Critique in the paper shredder as of yet (or...the scrawls of his twisted son Hegel...)
That said, Im not down with the "belief" philosophasters. Beliefs of a sort may exist...but they're not like...easily demarcated. Or, shall we say, it's like decisions (the real issue, I believe). We infer decisions...as with voting, or asking what the steno pool decided on for lunch (note that most decisions are ...compelled, or coerced however....Trixie decides between burgers or tacos or tofu...she doesn't decide to not be hungry however....) . The belief chat however seems more vague...similarly for memories, and "qualia" in a sense. But that doesn't mean it doesn't exist (as the behaviorists insisted). It means ...philosophy can't really discuss it--tho cogsci has started to
Thanks for the input. I'll consider the issues in a blog post with 'free will' in title or something like that I hope.
ReplyDelete