Speranza
Or robbing Peter (Wason) to pay Paul (Grice).
It all started, for
Newstead, when he submitted for the Journal of Memory
and Language that
brilliant essay,
"Griceian implicatures and syllogistic reasoning" and it
was accepted!
Grice used to say, "Grice saves; but, mind, there's no
free lunch".
The implicature was that if you, like Peter Wason and Paul
Grice himself
did (Robbing Peter To Pay Paul) take "⊃" to stand for the
'if' in the 'if'
utterance of Wason's AD47 card selection task, you may
SAVE (problems that
may arise if you take a different sort of 'formal
device' to represent
something apparently as
naïf as "if" sounds
like.
But that was precisely Strawson (also called Peter, like Wason,
coincidentally, "Peter without a lesson," as I call him -- since at least
Peter Wason
is taking the horseshoe properly) and his mistake.
Now,
in the case of Wason's 'if' utterance involved in the AD47 card
selection
task, Leda Cosmides called it "abstract" -- she's no philosopher but
we can
get her drift.
Seriously, it's not so much about the 'subtle grammatical
shift' (or nuance
or conversational implicature) but about how you turn that 'grammar' into logic. Grice, echoing
Russell, used to say that 'grammar' is a 'pretty good guide' to 'logical
form', and I think in
THIS case he did mean 'pretty pretty' (as opposed to
the pretty in pretty complex).
For when we see the abstract 'if'
utterance as
p⊃q
--surely there are dismissing 'formal devices'
that Grice didn't in his
"Logic and Conversation" lectures,
where he
lists "∀" to stand for "all", "∃" to stand for "some (at least
one)" and
"ix" to stand for "the".
The Wason subject will first approach the task
syntactically -- and he may
fail at that level.
He will then
approach the task 'semantically'.
And he will test the task
pragmatically. He may wonder: "Is it really
believable that Wason is in
doubt about the truth value of the 'if' utterance?
Don't think so. Is he
teasing me, or trying to tease me? Isn’t it more
likely that Wason just
typed down a true "if" statement — the more so since the
background "if"
utterance (‘letters on one side, numbers on the other side’
) must also be
taken to be true, if one follows Grice's cooperative
principle ("be
truthful" -- his conversational category of Qualitas).
But back to Step
1 and 2 (syntax-cum-pragmatics), the Wason subject may
feel that the 'if'
utterance needs some sort of predicate, or
quantifiational, logic, and that
its logical form requires the use of predicates and
quantifiers, notably
because of the occurrence of expressions like "one side"
and "other
side".
If, like Grice, you are enamoured with System Q (that Myro created
in
Grice's honour), the way to provide the correct logical form (the middle
and
second Witters hated that phrase!) formalise Wason's 'iffy' utterance
in
predicate or quantificational logic should use the following
predicates:
V for visible
I for invisible
O for vowel
E for even
number
We now need propositions:
i. Ox
will read as "x is
a vowel".
ii. Ex
will read as "x is an even number".
Next
we need a 'relational logic' alla Russell, for the introduction of
the
predicate 'visible'. For it's not just 'visible' we want, but the ability
to formalise, 'x is on the visible side of card y'. Let
iii. V(x, y)
represent that, where V stands for a dyadic relation).
And
finally we need again 'relational logic' to represent, 'x is on the
INvisible side of card y'. Let
iv. I(x, y) -- x is on the invisible
side of card y.
symbolise that, where again "I" stands for a dyadic
relation.
Now, Wason's iffy utterance can be given the proper logical
form:
∀c(∃x(V(x, c) ∧ O(x)) ⊃ ∃y(I(y, c) ∧ E(y))) ∀c(∃x(I(x, c) ∧ O(x))
⊃ ∃
y(V(y, c) ∧ E(y)))
After teaching Paul Strawson for a few terms
at St. John's, Grice was
appalled to see that his tutee still committed a
few mistakes. It is these
mistakes (in Strawson's "Introduction to Logical
Theory") that moved Grice to
accept the invitation at Harvard to give the
"Logic and Conversation"
lectures. In the "Prolegomena" Grice explicitly
quotes verbatim from Strawson's
essay on 'if' as a mistake by 'ordinary
language philosophers' who dismiss
pragmatic phenomena -- and that can't
stand the horseshoe's implicatures!
Similarly, and a few years later,
Peter (same first name as Strawson) Wason
ends up finding that some of his
subjects go astray at this point,
replacing the second statement containing
⊃ by a bi-conditional (a different
formal device altogether), or worse, by
a reversed conditional.
Pinker knew this when he says that 'logical'
words in language are
'ambiguous'. He uses that ambiguous 'ambiguous' when
he means is 'Griceian in
nature': utterances containing them have a precise
logical form and trigger
implicatures that can go over Wason's subjects's
heads (metaphorically)
(although Pinker uses 'mind' LITERALLY!)
Pinker's list of 'logical words' in the paragraph preceding his précis
of
Wason's test, one may think he quotes just to reference the PhD by
Cosmides
for the Department of Psychology and Social Relations (Her advisor
was
Sheldon H. White, not Pinker, granted. From 1982 until 2003, Pinker
taught at
the Department of Brain and Cognitive Sciences at MIT, and
eventually became
the director of the Center for Cognitive
Neuroscience, taking a one-year
sabbatical at the University of California,
Santa Barbara, in 1995–96 (to
which Cosmides is associated). In 2003,
Pinker became the Johnstone Family
Professor of Psychology at
Harvard).
In any case, Pinker's list goes:
"not", "and", "if",
"same", "equivalent", and "opposite".
So, he wouldn't be surprised by a
richer logical form to the Wason task
than the mere
p⊃q
--
because, while "⊃", note that the expanded logical form in predicate
logic
makes use of "and" ("∧") and one can think of shorter expansions that
use
"not" (~) if not "opposite", "equivalent" and "opposite".
To sum up, a
certain prejudice (or 'bias') against a logically-based
account of
reasoning (as Grice offers in "Aspects of reason", borrowing some
ideas
from his own "Logic and Conversation") cuts off the insights of
psychology
from a few applications. Those psychologists like Wason who explore
reasoning -- or worse some of his critics and some of his followers,
although
hardly the philosophical bunch of them -- seem allergic to formal
semantics
as are psychologists of reasoning. This 'bias' may be largely due
to past
simplistic attempts to apply formal theories in a monolithic way.
But since, after Grice, logic has become less monolithic (and open the
gate to implicature -- as he said, "Implicature happens"), psychologists of
reasoning cannot afford to continue avoiding an enriched approach to
logical
form like the
rats!
References
Bloom, B. S., and
Broder, L. J. Problem solving processes of college
students. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Byrne, R. M. J. Suppressing valid
inferences with conditionals. Cognition,
31.
Cara, F., and Girotto,
V. Relevance theory explains the selection task.
Cognition,
57.
Cheng, P., and Holyoak, K. Pragmatic reasoning schemas. Cognitive
Psychology, 17.
Cosmides, L. The logic of social exchange: Has
natural selection shaped how
humans reason? Studies with the Wason selection
task. Cognition, 31.
Cosmides, L., and Tooby, J. Cognitive adaptations
for social exchange. In
J. Barkow, L. Cosmides, & J. Tooby (Eds.),
The adapted mind:
Evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture,
New York: Oxford University
Press.
Cummins, D. Evidence for the
innateness of deontic reasoning. Mind and
Language, 11.
Evans, J.
Interpretation and ‘matching bias’ in a reasoning task.
Quarterly Journal
of Experimental Psychology, 24.
Evans, J., Newstead, S., & Byrne,
R. In S. Newstead & R. Byrne
(Eds.), Human reasoning: The
psychology of deduction. Hove: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Evans, J., and Over,
D. Rationality and reasoning. Hove: Psychology Press.
Fiddick, L.,
Cosmides, L., and Tooby, J. The role of domain-specific
representations and
inferences in the Wason selection task. Cognition, 75.
Fillenbaum, S. How
to do some things with it. In Cotton & Klatzky
(Eds.), Semantic
functions in cognition. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Gabbay, D. A
general theory of structured consequence relations. In P.
Schroeder-Heister
and K. Došen (Eds.), Substructural logics. Oxford: Clarendon
Press.
Gebauer, G., & Laming, D. Rational choices in Wason’s
selection task.
Psychological Research, 60.
Gigerenzer, G. and Hug,
K. Domain-specific reasoning: Social contracts,
cheating, and perspective
change. Cognition, 43.
Girotto, V., Kemmelmeier, M., van der Henst, J.-B.
Inept reasoners of
pragmatic virtuosos? Relevance in the deontic selection
task. Cognition, 81.
Grice, H. P. Indicative conditionals.
-- Logic
and conversation. In P. Cole and J. Morgan (Eds.), Syntax and
semantics:
Vol. 3. Speech acts. London: Academic Press.
-- Studies in the way of
words.
-- Retrospective epilogue
-- Aspects of reason.
Griggs, R.
A., and Cox, J. R. The elusive thematic materials effect in
Wason’s
selection task. British Journal of Psychology, 73.
Goodman, N. Fact,
fiction and forecast. London University Press.
Henle, M. On the relation
between logic and thinking. Psychological Review,
69.
Hill, C.,
& Parry, K. Autonomous and pragmatic models of literacy:
Reading
assessment in adult education. Linguistics and Education, 1.
Hodges, W.
The logical content of theories of deduction. Commentary on
Johnson-Laird
& Byrne Deduction. Behavioural and Brain Sciences, 16.
Hughes,
M. The use of negative information in concept attainment. Ph.D.
thesis,
University of London.
Johnson-Laird, P., and Byrne, R. Conditionals: A
theory of meaning,
pragmatics and inference. Psychological Review.
Johnson-Laird, P., Legrenzi, P., Girotto, V., & Legrenzi, M.
Illusions
in reasoning about consistency. Science, 288.
Johnson-Laird, P., Legrenzi, P., and Legrenzi, S. Reasoning and a sense
of
reality. British Journal of Psychology, 63.
Johnson-Laird, P.,
& Savary, F. Illusory inferences: A novel class of
erroneous
deductions. Cognition, 71.
Kirby, K.. Probabilities and utilities of
fictional outcomes in Wason’s
selection task. Cognition, 51.
Manktelow, K., and Over, D. Inference and understanding: A
philosophical
perspective. London: Routledge.
Margolis, H.
Patterns, thinking, and cognition: A theory of judgement.
University of
Chicago Press.
Newstead, S. Griceian implicatures and syllogistic
reasoning. Journal of
Memory and Language, 34.
Oaksford, M., and
Chater, N. A rational analysis of the selection task as
optimal data
selection. Psychological Review, 101.
Platt, R., & Griggs, R.
Facilitation in the abstract selection task:
The effects of attentional and
instructional factors. Quarterly Journal of
Experimental Psychology 46.
Rips, L. The psychology of proof. Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press.
Stanovich, K., & West. Individual differences in
reasoning:
Implications for the rationality debate? Behavioural and Brain
Sciences, 23.
Stenning, K. Seeing reason. Image and language in learning
how to think.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Stenning, K., and
Cox, R. Rethinking deductive tasks: Relating
interpretation and reasoning
through individual differences.
Stenning, K., and Oberlander, J. A
cognitive theory of graphical and
linguistic reasoning: logic and
implementation. Cognitive Science, 19, 97–140.
Stenning, K., and van
Lambalgen, M. Semantics and psychology: Wason’s
selection task as a case
study. Journal of Logic, Language and Information 10
Stenning, K., and
van Lambalgen, M. A working memory model of relations
between
interpretation and reasoning.
Stenning, K., and Yule, P. Image and
language in human reasoning: A
syllogistic illustration. Cognitive
Psychology, 34
Stenning, K., Yule, P., and Cox, R. Quantifier
interpretation and
syllogistic reasoning. In G. W. Cattrell (Ed.),
Proceedings of the 18th Annual
Conference of the Cognitive Science Society,
Erlbaum: Maweh, N.J.
Strawson, P. F. Introduction to logical
theory.
-- "If" and "->" in PGRICE, Philosophical grounds of
rationality:
intentions, categories, ends. Oxford:
Clarendon.
VanderDoes and vanLambalgen. A logic of vision. Linguistics
and Philosophy
23.
vanDuyne, P. Realism and linguistic complexity.
British Journal of
Psychology, 65.
Wason, P. C. Reasoning about a
rule. Quarterly Journal of Experimental
Psychology, 20.
Wason, P. C.
Problem solving. In R. Gregory (Ed.), Oxford companion to the
mind.
Wason, P. C. and D. Green, Reasoning and mental representation.
Quarterly
Journal of Experimental Psychology, 36
Wason, P., and
Johnson-Laird, P. Proving a disjunctive rule. Quarterly
Journal of
Experimental Psychology, 21.
Wetherick, N. E. On the representativeness
of some experiments in
cognition. Bulletin of the British Psychological
Society, 23.
Sunday, February 28, 2016
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment