Speranza
Commentary on I. Adornetti,
"Why Philosophical Pragmatics Needs Clinical Pragmatics"
The study provides applications of Grice to clinical psychology, with extensive references.
Adoretti aims to show how
clinical pragmatics (the study of pragmatic
deficits) can fruitfully inform
the classical theoretical models proposed
by philosophical pragmatics.
In the
first part of the essay Adornetti argues that
theories proposed in the domain of
philosophical pragmatics, as those
elaborated by Herbert Paul Grice, are not
plausible from a cognitive point
of view and that for this reason they cannot
be useful to understand
pragmatic deficits.
In the second part, Adornetti shows that
Relevance Theory
overcomes this limitation (being consistent with the data
about actual
mind’s functioning), but I also argue that it offers a
restricted view of
human communication which has to be integrated with a
model of
language use that takes into account a central pragmatic
property:
coherence of discourse.
Keywords: cognitive plausibility,
discourse coherence, executive
functions, pragmatic impairments, relevance
theory.
Pragmatics, since its dawn as a branch
of the sciences of language, has been the
subject of numerous debates about
the nature and definition of its object of
study.
While scholars of syntax
and semantics agree, at least on a general level,
on what should be their
field of study, among scholars of pragmatics there is no
general consensus on
what constitutes the domain of study of their discipline.
The absence of such
a consensus is evident, for example, in the various
definitions of pragmatics
that it can be find among the authors who deal with it.
For example, some, assuming language centrality, define pragmatics in general
terms as “the study of the use of language”, and more specifically as “the
study of how contextual factors
interact with linguistic meaning in the
interpretation of utterances”.
Other
authors, instead, focusing their
attention on non-linguistic features (gaze,
gestures, postures, etc),
describe pragmatic behavior as not dependent on the
use of language
(Dronkers, Ludy, & Redfern, 1998).
In some others cases,
scholars
distinguish, at least implicitly, between linguistic and
non-linguistic
pragmatics by using terms such as ‘pragmatic language
impairment’ (Bishop,
2000) or ‘pragmatic language disorders’ (Martin & MacDonald, 2003).
In recent decades, the definition of pragmatics has been
strongly influenced
by the results from the field of clinical pragmatics: the
study of clinical cases
has offered valuable new sources of data with respect
to traditional issues in
philosophical and linguistic pragmatics (e.g.
Cummings, 2009; Perkins,
2007).
At the basis of this kind of methodological
approach there is the idea
that through the study of deficits it is possible
to identify capacities and
processes that underlie pragmatic behavior: here
the maximum is that we
become aware of the nature of a mechanism or process
by examining what
happens when it goes wrong. From this perspective,
therefore, it is possible to
propose a model of pragmatics that respects the
cognitive plausibility (the
interpretive model should be compatible with the
knowledge about the
functioning of our mind). In this paper I assume as
working definition of
clinical pragmatics the following proposed by Cummings
(2009, p. 6):
Clinical pragmatics is the study of the various ways in which
an individual’s use
of language to achieve communicative purposes can be
disrupted. The cerebral
injury, pathology or other anomaly that causes this
disruption has its onset in
the developmental period or during adolescence or
adulthood.
Developmental
and acquired pragmatic disorders have diverse
aetiologies and may be the
consequence of, related to or perpetuated by a
range of cognitive and linguistic
factors.
Adornetti's aim is to show that our
understanding of pragmatics can be informed
and extended by the study of
pragmatic impairments. In the next section I aim
to discuss the advantages of
such an approach compared to some theories
proposed in the area of
philosophical pragmatics.
Although
classical pragmatic theory as those proposed by the Oxford philosopher such
Herbert Paul Grice has had a remarkable impact on the study
of
pragmatic impairments, understanding of communication deficits has not
always
been particularly well served by these theories.
This is due to a
large
extent to the fact that these theories provide a means of describing
pragmatics
and pragmatic impairments that is rarely adequate for clinicians
(for a
discussion, see Perkins, 2007).
Austin’s Speech Act Theory, for
example,
although used to test communication in several clinical populations,
including
adult with aphasia (Wilcox & Davis, 1977) and children with
Asperger’s
syndrome (Ziatas, Durkin, & Pratt, 2003) and autism (Loveland
et al., 1988),
shows some limitations (Allan, 1998) that can be problematic
for clinicians. As
an example, consider the following transcript, spoken by a
man with traumatic
brain injury (TBI).
I have got faults and. my biggest
fault is.
I do enjoy sport .
It’s something that I’ve always done.
I’ve done
it all my life.
I’ve nothing but respect for my mother and father and my
sister. and basically sir.
I’ve only come to this conclusion this last two
months. and as far as I’m concerned
my sister doesn’t exist.
From
Perkins,
Body & Parker, 1995, p. 305).
As you can see, each single utterance is
well formed and has the
illocutionary form of a statement.
However,
considered as a whole, this piece of
language appears inappropriate from a
pragmatic point of view.
Indeed, it lacks
coherence: it is characterized by
sudden and irrelevant topic shifts.
So,
according to Speech Act Theory,
utterances produced by TBI subject are not
problematic, although they are
ineffective from a more general communicative
perspective. Here the problem
is that Speech Act Theory has tended to focus
on single isolated sentences
independent from discourse context (Geiss,
1995), but (as I will discuss more
specifically in the last paragraph) a central
property of pragmatics is
coherence that pertains to the level of the discourse
rather than of the
single sentence.
*********************************************
Herbert Paul Grice’s Theory has served
as a
conceptual framework for understanding pragmatic impairment and has
been
used for studying communicative problems of some clinical
populations,
including adults with aphasia and right hemisphere damage
(Ahlsén, 1993;
Bloom et al, 1999; Stemmer, Giroux & Joannatte, 1994) or
children with
autism (Surian et al., 1996).
********************
However, the application of
theory of
Conversational
Implicature proved problematic to study pragmatic deficits,
and its
application is not always easy and straightforward.
The main problem of
this
failure is that Gricean Theory (but the same is true, at a general level,
for
philosophical pragmatics) doesn’t explain the underlying causes of
pragmatic
behavior and pragmatic deficit.
However, the need to distinguish
between such
levels, that of description and that of explanation, seems
particularly
outstanding.
As an illustration of this, consider the following
transcripts
discussed by Perkins (2007, p. 31).
a.
Prompt:
the man who
sits on the bench next to the oak tree is our mayor
Gary:
amen
b.
Adult: can you think of anymore?
Matthew: a remote-controlled
cactus
Transcripts (a) is the response of Gary, an 8 year old boy, to a task
where the
subject is required to repeat the sentence heard.
Transcripts (b) shows a piece of
conversation between Matthew, aged 8, and an adult who has
been asking
names for pets.
Gary’s and Matthew’s response may be apparently
described in
a similar way.
They are examples of pragmatically anomalous
behavior as they
appear to violate the Gricean maxim of relevance.
However,
only Matthew’s response is a genuine case of pragmatic impairment.
Indeed, as
Perkins (2007) shows, the underlying causes in each case are quite different.
Gary’s irrelevant
response is due to his problems with verbal memory and
syntactic
comprehension.
The sentence
The man who sits on the bench next to
the oak tree is our mayor.
is both too long and too syntactically complex for
him.
On
the other hand, Matthew has normal syntax and verbal memory, but has
a
diagnosis of autistic spectrum disorder.
His problems in social cognition
are
responsible for his incapacity to take proper account of prior and
surrounding
context during conversation.
Here the distinction is
between primary and secondary pragmatic disorders.
Clinicians and
theorists
use the term ‘secondary’ to describe an individual’s pragmatic
disorder that is not related to any
impairment of pragmatic competence as
such – the disorder is secondary to an impairment of
structural language.
Instead, an individual with a primary pragmatic disorder has intact
structural
The
arguments discussed lead us to highlight an important issue.
The idea
that
the development of a theoretical model about the nature of
communication
cannot be separated from the reference to empirical data. In
our case, the idea
is that the elaboration of a pragmatic theory should be
constrained by clinical
data. The analysis of the deficits permits building
theoretical models (founded
in human cognition) that can explain the actual
communication processes
rather than describe them in the abstract.
Now,
although the existence of a
deficit does not constitute in itself evidence to
support that a certain
processing system is involved in a given function, in
my opinion the study of
the deficit, and therefore the reference to the
functioning of cognition, remains
an indispensable tool (while not sufficient
alone) to test the empirical
plausibility of a theoretical model. The issue
of pragmatic impairments opens
the way to question the relationship between
pragmatic theory and the theory
of cognition. In the next section I discuss
such a question using other frameworks.
There is is a
perspective on the nature of communication
strongly related to theories on
the architecture of the mind.
Unlike Speech Act
theory and Conversational
Implicature, this framework characterizes pragmatics referring
to cognitive processing
rather than contextualized action or usage principle.
This framework, in fact, tries to
give an account of the processing systems at the base of
human communication:
the scholars who work within this perspective of
research explicitly seek to
respect cognitive plausibility to explain
communication processes. In such a
perspective assumptions about the nature
of communication are subject to
confirmation or refutation and reformulation
in the light of experimental
work concerning the nature of cognition. The methods
adopted are, in fact, those of cognitive
psychology: in addition to purely
philosophical or linguistic arguments, the
appeal of cognitive plausibility
binds authors to construct models of
communication processes in line with the
evidence produced by experimental
language skills, but may fail to understand
the significance of context features for his choice of
linguistic utterance
(Cummings, 2009).
studies on
the deficit or with interpretations that come from
evolutionary
psychology.
Following Herbert Paul Grice’s intuition, according to which
an essential feature of most
human communication, both verbal and non-verbal,
is the expression and
recognition of intentions (Grice, 1957), a framework sees
communication as an inferential pragmatic process in which the
generation and
the detection of communicators' intentions is central.
More in
detail, it is proposed an ostensive-inferential model of human
communication
according to which the speaker provides just an evidence (e.g.,
an utterance) of
his intention to convey a certain meaning and the listener
comprehends
speaker’s meaning by producing a series of inferences that are
governed by
that evidence.
In this communicative process two intentions are
involved:
1. the informative intention,
by which the speaker informs the
listener of
something (the ostensive stimulus has to attract the attention of
the
recipients);
2. the communicative intention
by which the speaker
intends to inform the
listener of his own communicative intention (the
ostensive stimulus has to
lead the attention of the recipients on the
speaker’s intention).
Communication has a positive outcome when the recipient
explicitly
recognizes the communicative intention of the speaker (therefore
his
communicative behavior). To this end, the ostensive stimulus (behavior,
verbal
utterance, etc.) must capture the attention of the recipient and
direct the
attention on speaker’s intentions.
But, what does it make an
ostensive stimulus
worth attending to? Some have argued that
the answer to this
question is based on a theoretical notion of relevance.
They wrote:
Relevance, as we see it, is a potential property of external
stimuli (e.g.
utterances, actions) or internal representations (e.g.
thoughts, memories)
which provide input to cognitive processes.
The relevance
of an input for an
individual at a given time is a positive function of the
cognitive benefits that he
would gain from processing it, and a negative
function of the processing effort
needed to achieve these benefits.
2 The reference to evolutionary psychology is due
to the fact that humans do have
an automatic tendency to maximise relevance, not because we have a
choice in
the matter […] but because of the way our cognitive systems have
evolved, it is said.
Relevance is a guiding principle of communication. From this
perspective,
the basic assumption of each conversational interaction is that
speakers and
listeners have tried to make their contributions as relevant as
possible and that
each one is interpreting the contributions of others taking
relevance in mind.
However, the principle of relevance is also intended to
apply to the domain of
cognition in general.
The idea
is that relevance is a
feature of human cognition: human mind is geared
toward the maximization of
relevance:
the human cognitive system has
developed in such a way that our perceptual
mechanisms tend automatically to
pick out potentially relevant stimuli, our
memory retrieval mechanisms tend
automatically to activate potentially relevant
assumptions, and our
inferential mechanisms tend spontaneously to process
them in the most
productive way
Since we have said that this is a model of pragmatics that adheres to how the
mind works, it is
important to analyze connections between this framework and theory of
human cognition.
At
a general level, identification of the others’ intentions is
made possible by
a specific cognitive system, Theory of Mind (ToM) module.
This term is used
to describe the ability to attribute mental states such as
beliefs,
intentions, and feelings to others and to explain and to predict the
actions
that derive from them (Baron-Cohen, 1995). This framework sees
pragmatics
as a specific component - a “relevance-based comprehension
module” – of the
ToM module with its own proprietary concepts and
procedures distinct from
general ToM module. From this point of view,
communication, and more specifically
verbal comprehension, is a form of
mindreading.
Happé (1993) identifies
different levels of mindreading capacity
that could be conceived as a
continuum ranging from a basic capacity to
represent others’ mental state
(i.e. representational ability) to the potentially
infinite representation of
mental states about other mental states (i.e.
metarepresentational ability).
According to Happé, representational ability
appears to be sufficient to
understand metaphor, while metarepresentational
ability is needed to
appreciate irony.
The condition most commonly associated with mindreading
deficit is
autism (Baron-Cohen, 1995; 2001). Since this framework sees communication as
an
exercise of mindreading, it has been a useful framework to
analyze
communicative deficits of autistic people (e.g., Dennis, Lazenby
& Lockyer
2001; Frith 1989; Happé 1995; Wearing, 2010). For example,
a
mindreading deficit may be
responsible for the incapacity of autistic subjects to
understand indirect
requests. Consider the following transcripts:
T: can you turn the page
over?
C: yes (non sign of continuing) (from Perkins, 2007, p. 67).
This is
a piece of an interaction between C, a 4-year-old child with
autistic
spectrum disorder, and T, a speech and language therapist. C seems
unable to
infer that T’s utterance is intended as a request and is not just a
question.
Another example of this kind of pragmatic impairment in autism is
offered by
figure 1 that shows the response of a child with autism who was
given a paper
with seven rectangles drawn on it and given the request to
“write the days of
the week in these seven boxes” (Perkins & Firth,
1991).
It is evident that the
child’s response could be ascribed to a
misreading of the speaker’s intention.
The Days of the Week
Fig. 1. The
response of a child with autism to the request ‘write the days of the week
in
these seven boxes’.
As we have seen so far, some characterize pragmatics
as “inferential comprehension” oriented to relevance
detection.
This means
that the “relevance principle” characterizes, from a
pragmatic point of view,
the essence of language. My opinion is that such a
conception represents a too
limited view of human communication (a view that
is heavily focused on the
aspects of language comprehension and therefore on
the role of the hearer).
More specifically, I believe that it is opportune to
put together with Relevance
Theory an interpretative model that takes into
account another fundamental
pragmatic property, coherence, which has a key
role in discourse processing
(clinical data show that it is a property that
pertains, primarily, to the
dimension of language production). In next
section I aim to show why
coherence is a central property of human
communication and what kind of
devices make it possible.
Relevance is not the only principle that governs human
communication.
As
highlighted, for example by Giora (1997, 1998), «speakers
and hearers are
not constrained only by the search for relevance. In
addition, coherence
considerations constrain communication and play a major
role in discourse
structuring and understanding» (Giora, 1997, p. 31). As I
have said in a
previous sections, my idea is that coherence pertains
especially to the building
of discourse – to the production - and, for this
reason, it is an effort principally
made by the speaker. To specify this
point, I discuss briefly the case of TBI
subjects. This example allows us to
emphasize the importance of production
dimension and the fundamental
involvement of others cognitive systems,
specifically the executive functions
of planning and monitoring, beyond ToM,
in pragmatic communication.
Before
addressing this topic, I need to specify
more in detail the notion of
coherence.
Coherence is a term that refers to conceptual organizational
aspects of
discourse at the suprasentential level. The coherence of a text or
discourse
depends, at least in part, on the speaker’s ability to maintain
thematic unity
(Agar & Hobbs, 1982). When is a discourse coherent? The
dominant idea,
especially among linguists, is that the coherence of discourse
(spoken or
written) depends on the linear relations between adjacent
sentences, that is to
say on cohesion between pairs of consecutive statements
(Bellert, 1970;
Bublitz, 2011; Daneš, 1974; Halliday & Hasan, 1976;
Tanskanen, 2006).
The most influential work from this perspective is Halliday
and Hasan’s
Cohesion in English published in 1976.
Their concept of cohesion
is semantic
one. Indeed, in their opinion cohesion refers «to relations of
meaning that exist
within the text» (Halliday & Hasan, 1976, p. 4) and
«enable one part of the
text to function as the context for another»
(Halliday & Hasan, 1989, p. 489).
In a text, the relations of cohesion
are realized through grammatical and lexical
devices. Grammatical cohesion
includes elements such as reference,
substitution, ellipsis and conjunctions,
while lexical cohesion is based on
reiteration (repetition, synonymy, etc.)
and collocation (co-occurrence of
lexical item). Consider the following
text:
After the forming of the sun and the solar system, our star began its
long
existence as a so-called dwarf star. In the dwarf phase of its life, the
energy that
the sun gives off is generated in its core through the fusion of
hydrogen into
helium (from Berzlánovich 2008, p. 2).
As we can see, in this text the sentences are
connected through lexical
cohesion: the lexical cohesive relations hold among
the lexical items sun, solar
system, star, dwarf star and dwarf phase in the
text.
What is important to note for the purposes of my argument is that in
this
perspective cohesion is a necessary condition for discourse coherence
(for a
discussion see Giora, in press). Now, although the cohesive
relations
(grammatical and lexical) have an important role in the expression
and
recognition of coherence relations, my idea is that cohesion
between
consecutive sentences is not a necessary and sufficient condition for
the
coherence of utterances in the flow of speech.
With reference to this a
crucial
distinction is that between global and local coherence. Global
coherence refers
to the relationship between the content of a verbalization
with that of the
general topic of conversation; local coherence concerns the
conceptual links
between individual sentences or propositions that maintain
meaning in a text
or discourse (Glosser & Deser, 1990).
While local
coherence is made possible
by cohesion relationships, my hypothesis is that
global coherence is
independent from linguistic mechanisms (it is independent
from cohesion).
Consider the following sentences:
I bought a Ford. The car
in which President Wilson rode down the Champs
Élysées was black. Black
English has been widely discussed. The discussions
between the presidents
ended last week. A week has seven days. Every days I
feed my cat. Cats have
four legs. The cat is on the mat. Mat has three letters
(Enqvist, 1978, pp.
110-111).
In this text the sentences are connected through the mechanism
of
repetition.
However, the set of sentences, despite the abundance of
cohesive
ties, is not perceived as a coherent whole. In this text the
sentences do not
“hang together” in a reasonable way: the text lacks of
global coherence.
The example and the arguments discussed so far show that
global
coherence is a pragmatic property independent from linguistic
devices.
Indeed, my hypothesis is that coherence relies on more general
cognitive
processes such as the executive functions of action planning and
monitoring.
The processes of planning and monitoring play (even intuitively)
an important
role in building the flow of discourse. As speech is composed of
linear
sequences of words and expressions, the speaker must constantly form a
plan
of verbal expressions in order to decide what to say and how to organize
what
he says, if he wants to express himself in a coherent manner. Moreover,
during
the execution of a plan, that is, during the stage of discourse
production, it is
necessary to continue estimation of the task in order to make sure that
the
elements introduced accord with the general topic of conversation.
Empirical
evidence confirms the effective role of these executive processes
in processing
discourse coherence.
The most interesting data in this
regard comes from studies of patients with
TBI with executive dysfunctions.
These subjects have deficits in action
planning and monitoring: they are
unable to complete a goal-oriented behavior
through a series of simple
actions (e.g., Eslinger et al., 2011; Shallice 1982;
Zalla et al., 2001).
Because of this, TBI patients cannot organize and maintain
global discourse
coherence (while they have no problems at the level of local
coherence). As
an illustration of this, consider the following transcript
discussed by
Perkins (2007, p. 86) in which C, a man with TBI, is talking with
T, a speech
and language therapist, about trade unions.
C: I admit this government we’ve
got is not doing a good job but the unions are trying
to make them sound
worse than what they are
T: mm
C: they . they . cos I’m a Tory actually
but I I do vote . if there’s a . er . a communist
bloke there I will vote
communist but . it all depends what his principles are but I don’t
agree .
with the Chinese communism . and the Russian communism
T: right
C: but I
believe every . should be equal but . I’m not knocking the royal family
because
y . you need them
T: mm
C: and they they they bring people in
to see take photos
Despite the local sequential links between trade
unions–government,
government–Tory, Tory–communist,
communism–Chinese/Russian
communism, communism– equality, equality–Royal
Family, Royal Family–
tourist attraction, C shows a form of ‘topic drift’: he
is unable to monitor what
has already been talked about or to relate each
individual utterance to some
overall coherent plan or goal. In fact,
neurolinguistic experimental data show
that TBI subjects connect sentences
correctly by using cohesion ties
(grammatical devices), but they are unable
to construct and maintain the global
coherence of their verbal productions
(they cannot relate the individual
sentences to a plan or to a more general
purpose) and often introduce material
that is irrelevant to the current
context in their verbal productions (Biddle et
al., 1996; Glosser &Deser,
1990; Hough & Barrow, 2003; Marini et al.,
2011).
Because of their inability to formulate and to pursue a
communicative
goal, their discourses appear pragmatically
inappropriate.
In order to elaborate an interpretative model of
the nature of language, the
analysis and the study of clinical data appear
very important: they allow us to
propose a theoretical model that respects
the constraint of cognitive
plausibility. I have showed that philosophical
pragmatics does not respect this
constraint and, because of this, it is not
at all adequate for the study of
pragmatic deficits. A cognitive plausible
model of pragmatics is offered by
Relevance Theory. However, the clinical
data discussed here have pointed out
the necessity to go beyond relevance:
although pragmatic theory based on
relevance detection explains many aspects
of human communication, such a
theory should be integrated with a theoretical
model that takes into account
discourse coherence.
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
We
would like to thank Erica Cosentino and Francesco Ferretti for
helpful
suggestions.
REFERENCES
Agar, M., Hobbs, J. (1982).
Interpreting Discourse: Coherence and the Analysis of
Ethnographic
Interviews. Discourse Processes, 5(1), 1-32.
Ahlsén, E. (1993).
Conversational principles and aphasic communication.
Journal of
Pragmatics,
19, 57-70.
Allan, K. (1998). Speech Act Theory: an overview. In J. L. Mey
(Ed.), Concise
Encyclopedia of Pragmatics. Elsevier: Amsterdam,
927-939.
Austin, J. L. (1962). How to Do Things with Words . Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Austin, J. L. The Austin Papers, Bodleian Library, Oxford.
Baron-Cohen, S. (1995). Mindblindness: An Essay on Autism
and Theory of Mind.
Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
Why Philosophical
Pragmatics Needs Clinical Pragmatics 171
Baron-Cohen, S. (2001). Theory of
mind in normal development and autism. Prisme,
34, 174-183.
Bellert, I.
(1970). On a condition of the coherence of texts. Semiotica, 2,
335-363.
Berzlánovich, I. (2008). Lexical cohesion and the organization of
discourse
.
http://www.rug.nl/let/onderzoek/onderzoekinstituten/clcg/berzlanovich.
pdf
Biddle,
K., McCabe, A., & Bliss, L. (1996). Narrative skills following traumatic
brain
injury in children and adults. Journal of communication Disorders , 29,
447-
469.
Bishop, D. V. M. (2000). Pragmatic language impairment: a
correlate of SLI, a distinct
subgroup, or part of the autistic continuum? In
D. V. M. Bishop and L. B.
Leonard (Eds.), Speech and Language Impairments in
Children: Causes,
Characteristics, Intervention and Outcome. Hove: Psychology
Press, 99-
113.
Bloom, R. L., Pick, L. H., Borod, J. C., Rorie, K. D.,
Andelman, F., Obler, L. K.,
Sliwinski, M., Campbell, A. L., Tweedy, J. R.,
Welkowitz, J. (1999).
Psychometric aspects of verbal pragmatic ratings. Brain
and Language , 68,
553-565.
Bublitz, W. (2011). Cohesion and coherence. In
Zienkowski, J., Östman, J.,
Verschueren, J. (Eds.) Discursive Pragmatics,
John Benjamins Publishing
Company, Amsterdam / Philadelphia,
37-49.
Carston, R., Guttenplan, S., Wilson, D. (2002). Introduction: special
issue on
pragmatics and cognitive science. Mind and Language , 17,
1-2.
Cummings, L. (2009). Clinical Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Daneš, F. (1974). Functional sentence perspective and the
organization of the text. In
F. Daneš (Ed.), Papers on Functional Sentence
Perspective . Academia:
Prague, 106-128.
Dennis, M., Lazenby, AL, Lockyer,
L. (2001). Inferential language in high function
children with autism.
Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders , 31,
47-54.
Dronkers, N.
F., Ludy, C. A., Redfern, B. B. (1998). Pragmatics in the absence of
verbal
language: descriptions of a severe aphasic and a language-deprived
adult.
Journal of Neurolinguistics , 11, 179-190.
172 Humana.Mente – Issue 23 –
December 2012
Enqvist, N. E. (1978). Coherence, pseudo-coherence, and
non-coherence. In J.-O.
Östman (Ed.), Cohesion and Semantics. Åbo:
Meddelanden från Stiftelsens
för Åbo Akademi Forskningsinstitut,
109-128.
Eslinger, P., Zappalà, G., Chakara, F., Barrett A. M. (2011).
Cognitive Impairments
After TBI. In N.D. Zasler, D.I. Katz, R. D. Zafonte
(Eds.), Brain Injury
Medicine. Second Edition. New York: Demos Medical
Pub.
Frith, U. (1989). Autism: Explaining the Enigma . Blackwell:
Oxford.
Geis, M. L. (1995). Speech Acts and Conversational Interaction.
Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Giora, R. (1997), Discourse
coherence and theory of relevance: Stumbling blocks in
search of a unified
theory. Journal of Pragmatics, 27, 17-34.
Giora, R. (1998), Discourse
coherence is an independent notion: A reply to Deidre
Wilson. Journal of
Pragmatics, 29, 75-86.
Giora, R. (in press), Cohesion. In G., Khan (Ed.)
Encyclopedia of Hebrew Language
and Linguistics, Boston: Brill.
Glosser,
G., Deser, T. (1990). Patterns of discourse production among
neurological
patients with fluent language disorders. Brain and Language, 40,
67-88.
Grice, H. P. (1938). Negation. The Grice Papers, UC/Berkeley, Bancroft Library
Grice, H. P. (1948). Meaning.
Grice, H. P. (1961). The causal theory of perception
Grice, H.P. (1957). Meaning. The Philosophical Review, 66,
377-388.
Grice, H.P. (1975). Logic and conversation. In F. Cole and J. L.
Morgan (Eds.),
Syntax and Semantics, vol. III Speech Acts. New York: Academic
Press, 41-
58.
Halliday, M. A. K., Hasan, R. (1976). Cohesion in English.
Longman: London.
Halliday, M. A. K., Hasan, R. (1989). Language, context, and
text: aspects of language
in a social-semiotic perspective. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Happé, F.G.E. (1993). Communicative competence and theory
of mind in autism: a
test of relevance theory. Cognition, 48,
101-119.
Happé, F.G.E. (1995), Understanding mind and metaphors: insight from
the study of
figurative language in autism. Metaphor & Symbolic activity
, 10(4), 275-
295.
Hough, M.S., Barrow, I. (2003). Descriptive discourse
abilities of traumatic braininjured
adults. Aphasiology, 17(2),
183-191.
Why Philosophical Pragmatics Needs Clinical Pragmatics
173
Loveland, K. A., Landry, S. H., Hughes, S. O., Hall, S. K. and, McEvoy,
R. (1988).
Speech acts and the pragmatic deficits of autism. Journal of
Speech and
Hearing Research, 31, 593-604.
Marini, A., Galetto, V.,
Zampieri, E., Vorano, L., Zettin, M., Carlomagno, S. (2011).
Narrative
language in traumatic brain injury. Neuropsychologia, 49,
2904-
2910.
Martin, I., McDonald, S. (2003). Weak coherence, no theory of
mind, or executive
dysfunction? Solving the puzzle of pragmatic language
disorders. Brain and
Language, 85, 451-66.
Noveck, I., Sperber, D. (2004)
(Eds.). Experimental Pragmatics, New York:
Pallagrave.
Perkins, M. (2007).
Pragmatic Impairment. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Perkins, M.R.,
Body, R., Parker, M. (1995). Closed head injury: assessment and
remediation
of topic bias and repetitiveness. In M.R. Perkins, S. J. Howard
(Eds.), Case
Studies in Clinical Linguistics . London: Whurr, 293-320.
Perkins, M., Firth,
C. (1991). Production and comprehension of modal expressions by
children with
a pragmatic disability. First Language, 11-61.
Shallice, T. (1982). Specific
impairment of planning. Philosophical Transaction of the
Royal Society,
Biological Science , 25, 199-209.
Speranza, Join the Grice Club.
Sperber, D., Wilson, D. (1986/1995).
Relevance: Communication and Cognition,
Oxford: Blackwell.
Sperber, D.,
Wilson, D. (2002). Pragmatics, modularity and mind-reading. Mind
and
Language, 17, 3-23.
Sperber, D., Wilson, D. (2005). Pragmatics. In F.
Jackson, M. Smith (Eds.), Oxford
Handbook of Contemporary Analytic Philosophy
. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 468-501.
Stemmer, B., Giroux, F.,
Joanette, Y. (1994). Production and evaluation of requests
by right
hemisphere brain-damaged individuals. Brain and Language , 47,
1-
31.
Surian, L., Baron-Cohen, S., van der Lely, H. (1996). Are children
with autism deaf to
Gricean maxims? Cognitive Neuropsychiatry, 1(1),
55-71.
174 Humana.Mente – Issue 23 – December 2012
Tanskanen, S. K.
(2006). Collaborating towards Coherence. Lexical cohesion in
English
Discourse. Amsterdam / Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Wilcox, M. J., Davis, G.
A. (1977). Speech act analysis of aphasic communication in
individual and
group settings. In R. H. Brookshire (Ed.), Clinical
Aphasiology Conference
Proceedings . Minneapolis, MN: BRK Publishers,
166-174.
Wearing, C.
(2010), Autism, Metaphor and Relevance Theory. Mind and Language ,
25,
196-216.
Wilson, D., Sperber, D. (2004), Relevance Theory. In G. Ward and L.
Horn (Eds.)
Handbook of Pragmatics. Blackwell: Oxford, 607-632.
Zalla, T.,
Plassiart, C., Pillon B., Grafman, J., Sirigu, A. (2001). Action planning in
a
virtual context after prefrontal cortex damage. Neuropsychologia , 39,
759-
770.
Ziatas, K., Durkin, K., Pratt, C. (2003). Differences in
assertive speech acts produced
by children with autism, Asperger syndrome,
specific language impairment,
and normal development. Development and
Psychopathology , 15, 73-94
Wednesday, January 9, 2013
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment