H. P. Grice, M. A. Lit. Hum., F. B.
A, Tutorial Fellow in Philosophy, St. Johns, Oxford
NEGATION. A bit of palæo-Griceian history is in order. Sheffer,
defines ‘not’ and negation in terms of incompatibility in ‘A set of five
independent postulates for Boolean algebras, with application to logical
constants,’ Trans. American Mathematical Society. Grice does refers to ‘the
strokes.’ His use of the plural is interesting as a nod to Peirce’s minute
logic in his ‘Boolian [sic] algebra with one constant.’ There is indeed
Peirce’s stroke, or ampheck (↓), Sheffer’s stroke (|, /, ↑), and and Quine’s
stroke (†, strictly Quine’s dagger). Some philosophers prefer to refer to
Peirces Stroke as Peirce’s arrow, or strictly stressed double-edged sword. His
editors disambiguate his ampheck, distinguishing between the dyadic
functor or connective equivalent to Sheffer’s stroke and ‘nor.’ While Whitehead,
Russell, and Witters love Sheffer’s stroke, Hilbert does not: ‘‘p/p’ ist dann
gleichbedeutend mit ‘X̄.’ Grice explores primitiveness. It is possible, to
some extent, to qualify this or that device in terms of primitiveness. As
regards ‘not,’ if a communication-system did not contain a unitary negative
device, there would be many things that communicators can now communicate that
they would be then unable to communicate. He has two important caveats. That
would be the case unless, first, the communication-system contained some very
artificial-seeming connective like one or other of the strokes, and, second,
communicators put themselves to a good deal of trouble, as Plato does in ‘The
Sophist’ with ‘diaphoron,’ that Wiggins symbolises with ‘Δ,’ to find, more or
less case by case, complicated forms of expression, not necessarily
featuring a connective, but involving such expressions as ‘other than’or ‘incompatible
with.’ Grice further refers to Aristotle’s ‘apophasis’ in De Int.17a25.
Grice, always lured by the potentiality of a joint philosophical endeavour,
treasures his collaboration with Strawson that is followed by one with Austin
on Cat. and De Int. So what does Aristotle say in De Int.? Surely Aristotle
could have started by referring to Plato’s Parmenides, aptly analysed by
Wiggins. Since Aristotle is more of a don than a poet, he has to give ‘not’ a name:
‘ἀπόφασις ἐστιν ἀπόφανσίς τινος ἀπό τινος,’a predication of one
thing away from another, i.e. negation of it. This is
Grice’s reflection, in a verificationist vein, of two types of this or that
negative utterance. His immediate trigger is Ryle’s contribution on a symposium
on Bradley’s idea of an internal relation, where Grice appeals to Peirce’s
incompatibility. ‘The proposition ‘This is red’ is imcompatible with the
proposition, ‘This is not coloured.’ While he uses a souly verb or predicate
for one of them, Grice will go back to the primacy of ‘potching’ at a later stage.
A pirot potches that the obble is not fang, but feng. It is convenient to introduce
this or that soul-state, ψ, sensing that …, or perceiving that … Grice works mainly with two
scenarios, both involved with the first-person singular pronoun ‘I’ with which
he is obsessed. Grice’s first scenario concerns a proposition that implies
another proposition featuring ‘someone, viz. I,’ the first-person singular
pronoun as subject, a sensory modal verb, and an object, the proposition, it is
not the case that ‘the α is φ1.’ The denotatum of the
first-person pronoun perceives that a thing displays this or the visual
sense-datum of a colour, and the corresponding sensory modal predicate. Via a
reductive (but not reductionist) analysis, we get that, by uttering ‘It is not
the case that I see that the pillar box is blue,’ the utterer U means, i. e.
m-intends his addressee A to believe, U he sees that the pillar box is red. U’s
source, reason, ground, knowledge, or belief, upon which he bases his uttering
his utterance is U’s *indirect* mediated actual experience, belief, or
knowledge, linked to a sense-datum φ2 (red) other than φ1
(blue). Grice’s second scenario concerns a proposition explicitly featuring the
first-person singular pronoun, an introspection, involving an auditory
sense-datum of a noise. Via reductive (but not reductionist) analysis, we get
that, by uttering ‘It is not the case that I hear that the bell tolls in Gb,’ U
means that he lacks the experience of hearing that the bell tolls simpliciter.
U’s source, reason, ground, knowledge, or belief, upon which he bases his
uttering his utterance is the *direct* unmediated felt absence, or absentia, or
privatio or privation, or apophasis, verified by introspection, of the
co-relative ψ, which Grice links to the absence of the
experience, belief, or knowledge, of the sense-datum, the apophasis of the
experience, which is thereby negated. In either case, Grice’s analysans do not
feature ‘not.’ Grice turns back to the topic in seminars later at Oxford
in connection with Strawson’s cursory treatment of ‘not’ in ‘Introduction to
logical theory.’ ‘Not’ (and ~.) is the first pair, qua unary
satisfactory-value-functor (unlike this or that dyadic co-ordinate, and, or, or
the dyadic sub-ordinate if) in Grice’s list of this or that vernacular
counterpart attached to this or that formal device. Cf. ‘Smith has not ceased
from eating iron,’ in ‘Causal theory.’ In the fourth James lecture, Grice
explores a role for negation along the lines of Wilson’s Statement and
Inference.’ Grice’s ‘Vacuous Names’ contains Gentzen-type syntactic inference
rules for both ‘not’’s introduction (+, ~) and the elimination (-, ~) and the
correlative value assignation. Note that there are correlative rules for
Peirce’s arrow. Grice’s motivation is to qualify ‘not’ with a subscript
scope-indicating device on ~ for a tricky case like ‘The climber of Mt. Everest
on hands and knees is not to atttend the party in his honour.’ The logical form
becomes qualified: ‘~2(Marmaduke Bloggs is coming)1’, or
‘~2(Pegasus flies)1.’ generic formula is ~2p1,
which indicates that p is introduced prior to ~. In the earlier James lectures
he used the square bracket device. The generic formula being ‘~[p],’ where [p]
reads that p is assigned common-ground status. Cancelling the implicata may be
trickier. ‘It is not the case that I hear that the bell tolls because it is
under reparation.’ ‘That is not blue; it’s an optical illusion.’ Cf. Grice on ‘It
is an illusion. What is it?’ Cf. The king of France is not bald because there
is no king of France. In Presupposition, the fourth Urbana lecture, Grice uses
square brackets for the subscript scope indicating device. ‘Do not arrest [the
intruder]!,’ the device meant to assign common-ground status. In ‘Method in
philosophical psychology (from the banal to the bizarre),’ Grice plays with the
internalisation of a pre-theoretical concept of not within the scope of ‘ψ.’ In the Kant lectures on aspects of reasoning,
Grice explores ‘not’ within the scope of this or that mode operator, as in the
buletic utterance, ‘Do not arrest the intruder!’ Is that internal narrow scope,
‘!~p,’ or external wide scope, ‘~!p’? Grice also touches on this or that
mixed-mode utterance, and in connection with the minor problem of
presupposition within the scope of an operator other than the indicative-mode
operator. ‘Smith has not ceased from eating iron, because Smith does not exist
‒ cf. Hamlet sees that his father is on the rampants, but the sight is not
reciprocated ‒ Macbeth sees that Banquo is near him, but his vision is not
reciprocated. Grice is having in mind Hare’s defense of a non-doxastic
utterance. In his commentary in P(hilosophical) G(rounds of) R(ationality:)
I(ntentions,) C(ategories), E(nds), Grice expands on this metaphysical
construction routine of Humeian projection with the pre-intuitive
concept of ‘not,’ specifying the
different stages the intuitive concept undergoes until it becomes
fully rationally recostructed, as something like a Fregeian sense. In the
centerpiece lecture of the William James set, Grice explores Wilson’s Statement
and inference to assign a métier to ‘not,’ and succeeds in finding one. The
conversational métier of ‘not’ is explained in terms of the conversational
implicatum. By uttering ‘Smith has not been to prison yet,’ U implies that some
utterer has, somewhere, sometime, expressed an opinion to the contrary. This is
connected by Grice with the ability a rational creature has to possess to
survive. The creature has to be able, as Sheffer notes, to deny this or that.
Grices notable case is the negation of a conjunction. So it may well be that
the most rational role for ‘not’ is not primary in that it is realised once
less primitive operators are introduced. Is there a strict conceptual
distinction, as Grice suggests, between negation and privation? If privation
involves or presupposes negation, one might appeal to something like Modified
Occam’s Razor (M. O. R.), do not multiply negations beyond necessity. In his
choice of examples, Grice seems to be implicating negation for an empirically
verifiable, observational utterance, such as U does not see that the pillar box
is blue not because U does not exist, but on the basis of U’s experiencing, knowing,
believing and indeed seeing that the pillar box is red. This is a negation,
proper, or simpliciter (even if it involves a sense-datum phi2 incompatible
with sense-datum phi1. Privation, on the other hand, would be involved in
an utterance arrived via introspection, such as U does not hear that the bell
is ringing on the basis of his knowing that he is aware of the absence,
simpliciter, of an experience to that effect. Aristotle, or some later
Aristotelian, may have made the same distinction, within apophasis between
negation or negatio and privation or privatio. Or not. Of course, Grice is
ultimately looking for the rationale behind the conversational implicatum in
terms of a principle of conversational helpfulness underlying his picture of
conversation as rational co-operation. To use his pirotological jargon in
Method, in Pirotese and Griceish There is the Pirot1, who potches
that the obble is not fang, but feng. Pirot1 utters p
explicitly conveying that p. Pirot2 alternatively feels like
negating that. By uttering ~p, P2 explicitly conveys that ~p.
Pirot1 volunteers to Pirot2, ~p, explicitly
conveying that ~p. Not raining! Or No bull. You are safe. Surely a rational
creature should be capable to deny this or that, as Grice puts it in Indicative
conditionals. Interestingly, Grice does not consider, as Gazdar does, under
Palmer), he other possible unitary functors (three in a standard binary
assignation of values) – just negation, which reverses the satisfactory-value
of the radix or neustic. In terms of systematics, thus, it is convenient
to regard Grices view on negation and privation as his outlook on the operators
as this or that procedure by the utterer that endows him with this or that
basic expressive, operative power. In this case, the expressive power is
specifically related to his proficiency with not. The proficiency is co-related
with this or that device in general, whose vernacular expression will bear a
formal counterpart. Many of Grices comments addressed to this more general
topic of this or that satisfactoriness-preserving operator apply to not, and
thus raise the question about the explicitum or explicatum of not. A Griceian
should not be confused. The fact that Grice does not explicitly mention not or
negation when exploring the concept of a generic formal device does not mean
that what he says about formal device may not be particularised to apply to not
or negation. His big concession is that Whitehead and Russell (and Peano before
them) are right about the explicitum or explicatum of not being ~, even if
Grice follows Hilbert and Ackermann in dismissing Peirces arrow for pragmatic
reasons. This is what Grice calls the identity thesis to oppose to Strawsons
divergence thesis between not and ~. More formally, by uttering Not-p, U
explicitly conveys that ~p. Any divergence is explained via the implicatum. A
not utterance is horribly uninformative, and not each of them is of
philosophical interest. Grice joked with Bradley and Searles The man in the
next table is not lighting the cigarette with a twenty-dollar bill, the
denotatum of the Subjects being a Texas oilman in his country club. The odd
implicatum is usually to the effect that someone thought otherwise. In terms of
Cook Wilson, the role of not has more to do with the expressive power of a
rational creature to deny a molecular or composite utterance such as p and q
Grice comments that in the case of or, the not may be addressed,
conversationally, to the utterability of the disjunction. His example involves
the logical form Not (p or q). It is not the case that Wilson or Heath will be
prime minister. Theres always hope for Nabarro or Thorpe. The
utterer is, at the level of the implicatum, not now contradicting what his
co-conversationalist has utterered. The utterer is certainly not denying that
Wilson will be Prime Minister. It is, rather, that the utterer U wishes not to
assert or state, say, what his co-conversant has asserted, but, instead, to
substitute a different statement or claim which the utterer U regards as
preferable under the circumstances. Grice calls this substitutive disagreement.
This was a long-standing interest of Grices: an earlier manuscript reads Wilson
or MacMillan will be prime minister. Lets take a closer look at the way
Grice initially rephrases his two scenarios involving not as attached to an
auditory and a visual sense datum. I do not hear that the bell is ringing is
rationally justified by the absence or absentia of the experience of hearing
it. I do not see that the pillar box is blue is rationally justified by Us
sensing that the pillar box is red. The latter depends on Kants concept of the
synthetic a priori with which Grice tests with his childrens playmates. Can a
sweater be red and green all over? No stripes allowed! Can a pillar box be blue
and red all over? Cf. Ryles symposium on negation with Mabbott, for the
Aristotelian Society, a source for Grices reflexion. Ryle later discussing
Bradleys internal relations, reflects that that the proposition, This pillar box
is only red is incompatible with This pillar box is only blue. As bearing this
or that conversational implicata, Grices two scenarios can be re-phrased,
unhelpfully, as I am unhearing a noise and That is unred. The
apparently unhelpful point bears however some importance. It shows that
negation and not are not co-extensive. The variants also demonstrate that the
implicatum, qua conversational, rather than conventional, is non-detachable.
Not is hardly primtive pure Anglo-Saxon. It is the rather convoluted
abbreviation of ne-aught. Its ne that counts as the proper, pure, amorphous
Anglo-Saxon negation, as in a member of parliament (if not a horse) uttering
nay. Grices view of conversation as rational co-operation, as
displayed in this or that conversational implicatum necessitates that the
implicatum is never attached to this or that expression. Here the favoured, but
not exclusive expression, is not, since Strawson uses it. But the vernacular
provides a wealth of expressive ways to be negative! Grice possibly chose
negation not because, as with this or that nihilistic philosopher, such as
Schopenhauer, or indeed Parmenides, he finds the concept a key one. But one may
well say that this is the Schopenhauerian or the Parmenidesian in Griceian.
Grice is approaching not in linguistic, empiricist, or conceptual key. He is
applying the new Oxonian methodology: the reductive analysis in terms of
Russells logical construction. Grices implied priority is with by uttering x,
by which U explicitly conveys that ~p, U implicitly conveys that q. The essay
thus elaborates on this implicated q. For the record, nihilism was coined
by philosopher Jacobi, while the more primitive negatio and privatio is each a
time-honoured item in the philosophical lexicon, with which mediaeval this or
that speculative grammarian is especially obsessed. Negatio translates
Aristotles apophasis, and has a pretty pedigreed history. The philosophical
lexicon has nĕgātĭo, f. negare, which L and S, unhelpfully, render as a
denying, denial, negation, Cicero, Sull. 13, 39: negatio inficiatioque
facti, id. Part. 29, 102. L and S go on to add that negatio is predicated
of to the expression that denies, a negative. Grice would say that L and S
should realise that its the utterer who denies. The source L and S give is
ADogm. Plat. 3, p. 32, 38. As for Grices other word, there is
prīvātĭo, f. privare, which again unhelpfully, L and S render as a taking
away, privation of a thing. doloris, Cic. Fin. 1, 11, 37, and
38, or pain-free, as Grice might prefer, cf. zero-tolerance. L and S also cite:
2, 9, 28: culpæ, Gell. 2, 6, 10. The negatio-privatio distinction is
perhaps not attested in Grecian The Grecians seem to have felt happy with
ἀπόφασις, (A), from ἀπόφημι, which now L and S unhepfully render as
denial, negation, adding oκατάφασις, for which they cites from Platos
Sophista (263e), to give then the definition ἀπόφασις ἐστιν
ἀπόφανσίς τινος ἀπό τινος, a predication of one thing away
from another, i.e. negation of it, for which they provide the
source that Grice is relying. on: Arist. Int.17a25, cf. APo. 72a14;
ἀπόφασις τινός, negation, exclusion of a thing, Pl. Cra. 426d; δύο ἀ.
μίαν κατάφασιν ἀποτελοῦσι Luc. Gall.11. If he was not the first to explore
philosophically negation, Grice may be regarded as a philosopher who most
explored negation as occurring in a that-clause followed by a propositional
complexus that contains ~, and as applied to a personal agent, in a lower
branch of philosophical psychology. It is also the basis for his linguistic
botany. He seems to be trying to help other philosopher not to fall in the trap
of thinking that not has a special sense. The utterer means that ~p. In what
ways is that to be interpreted? Grice confessed to never
been impressed by Ayer. The crudities and dogmatisms seemed too pervasive.
Is Grice being an empiricist and a verificationist? Let us go back to This is
not red and I am not hearing a noise. Grices suggestion is that the
incompatible fact offering a solution to this problem is the fact that the
utterer of Someone, viz. I, does not hear that the bell tolls is indicating
(and informing) that U merely entertains the positive (affirmative)
proposition, Someone, viz. I, hears that the bell tolls, without having an
attitude of certainty towards it. More generally, Grice is proposing, like
Bradley and indeed Bosanquet, who Grice otherwise regards as a minor
philosopher, a more basic Subjects-predicate utterance. The α is
not β. The utterer states I do not know that α is β if and
only if every present mental or souly process, of mine, has some characteristic
incompatible with the knowledge that α is β. One
may propose a doxastic weaker version, replacing the dogmatic Oxonian know
with believe. Grices view of compatibility is an application of the
Sheffer stroke that Grice will later use in accounts of not. ~p iff p|p or ~p ≡df p|p. But
then, as Grice points out, Sheffer is hardly Griceian. If Pirotese did not
contain a unitary negative device, there would be many things that a pirot
should be able to express that the pirot should be unable to express unless
Pirotese contained some very artificially-looking dyadic functor like one or
other of the strokes, or the pirot put himself to a good deal of trouble to
find, more or less case by case, complicated forms of expression, as Platos
Parmenides does, involving such expressions as other than, or incompatible
with. V. Wiggins on Platos Parmenides in a Griceian key. Such a complicate form
of expression would infringe the principle of conversational helpfulness,
notably in its desideratum of conversational clarity, or conversational
perspicuity [sic], where the sic is Grices seeing that unsensitive Oxonians
sometimes mistake perspicuity for the allegedly, cognate perspicacity (L.
perspicacitas, like perspicuitas, from perspicere). Grice finds the unitary
brevity of not-p attractive. Then theres the pretty Griceian idea of the
pregnant proposition. Im not hearing a nose is pregnant, as Occam has it,
with I am hearing a noise. A scholastic and mediæval philosopher loves to be
figurative. Grices main proposal may be seen as drawing on this or that
verificationist assumption by Ayer, who actually has a later essay on not
falsely connecting it with falsity. Grices proposed better analysis would
please Ayer, had Grice been brought on the right side of the tracks, since it
can be Subjectsed to a process of verification, on the understanding
that either perception through the senses (It is red) or
introspection (Every present mental or souly process of mine ) is each an
empirical phenomenon. But there are subtleties to be drawn. At Oxford, Grices
view on negation will influence philosophers like Wiggins, and in a negative
way, Cohen, who raises the Griceian topic of the occurrence of negation in
embedded clauses, found by Grice to be crucial for the rational genitorial
justification of not as a refutation of the composite p and q), and motivating
Walker with a reply (itself countered by Cohen ‒ Can the
conversationalist hypothesis be defended?). So problems are not absent, as they
should not! Grice re-read Peirces definition or reductive analysis of not and
enjoyed it! Peirce discovers the logical connective Grice calls the
Sheffer Stroke, as well as the related connective nor (also called Joint
Denial, and quite appropriately Peirces Arrow, with other Namess in use being
Quines Arrow or Quines Dagger and today usually symbolized by “/”). The
relevant manuscript, numbered MS 378 in a subsequent edition and titled A
Boolian [sic] Algebra with One Constant, MS 378, was actually destined for
discarding and was salvaged for posterity A fragmentary text by Peirce also
shows familiarity with the remarkable meta-logical characteristics that make a
single function functionally complete, and this is also the case with Peirces
unfinished Minute Logic: these texts are published posthumously. Peirce
designates the two truth functions, nand and nor, by using the
symbol “” which he called ampheck, coining this neologism from the
Grecian ἀμφήκης, of equal length in both directions. Peirces editors
disambiguate the use of symbols by assigning “” to the connective we
call Sheffers troke while preserving the symbol / for
nor. In MS 378, Peirces A Boolian Algebra with One Constant, which
swas tagged “to be discarded” at the Department of Philosophy at Harvard,
Peirce reduces the number of logical operators to one constant. Peirce states
that his notation uses the minimum number of different signs and shows for the
first time the possibility of writing both universal and particular
propositions with but one copula. Peirce’s notation is later termed Sheffers
stroke, and is also well-known as the nand operation, in Peirce’s terms the
operation by which two propositions written in a pair are considered to be both
denied. In the same manuscript, Peirce also discovers what is the expressive
completeness of ‘nor,’ indeed today rightly recognized as the Peirce
arrow. Like Sheffer, of Cornell, independently does later (only to be
dismissed by Hilbert and Ackermann), Peirce understands that these two
connectives can be used to reduce all mathematically definable connectives
(also called primitives and constants) of propositional logic. This means that
all definable connectives of propositional logic can be defined by using only
Sheffers stroke or nor as the single connective. No other connective (or
associated function) that takes one or two variables as inputs has this
property. Standard, two-valued propositional logic has no unary functions that
have the remarkable property of functional completeness. At first blush,
availability of this option ensures that economy of resources can be
obtained—at least in terms of how many functions or connectives are to be
included as undefined. Unfortunately, as Grice, following Hilbert and Ackermann
realise, there is a trade-off between this philosophical semantic gain in
economy of symbolic resources and the pragmatically unwieldy length and rather
counterintuitive, to use Grices phrase, appearance of the formulas that use
only the one connective. It is characteristic of his logical genius,
however, and emblematic of his rather under-appreciated, surely not by Grice,
contributions to the development of semiotics that Peirce grasps the
significance of functional completeness and figure out what truth functions —
up to arity 2 — are functionally complete for two-valued propositional logic,
never mind helping the philosopher to provide a reductive analysis of negation
that Grice is looking for. Strictly, this is the property of weak functional
completeness, given that we disregard whether constants or zero-ary functions
like 1 or 0 can be defined. Peirce subscribes to a semeiotic view, popular in
the Old World with Ogden and Welby, and later Grice, according to which
the fundamental nature and proper tasks of the formal study of communication
are defined by the rules set down for the construction and manipulation of
symbolic resources. A proliferation of symbols for the various connectives that
are admitted into the signature of a logical system suffers from a serious
defect on this view. The symbolic grammar fails to match or represent the
logical fact of interdefinability of the connectives, and reductive analysis of
all to one. Peirce is willing sometimes to accept constructing a formal
signature for two-valued propositional logic by using the two-members set of
connectives, which is minimally functionally complete. This means that these
two connectives — or, if we are to stick to an approach that emphasizes the
notational character of logical analysis, these two symbols —are adequate
expressively. Every mathematically definable connective of the logic can be
defined by using only these two. And the set is minimally functionally complete
in that neither of these connectives can be defined by the other (so, as we
say, they are both independent relative to each other.) The
symbol can be viewed as representing a constant truth function
(either unary or binary) that returns the truth value 0 for any input or
inputs. Or it can be regarded as a constant, which means that it is a zero=ary
(zero-input) function, a degenerate function, which refers to the truth value
0. Although not using, as Grice does, Peanos terminology, Peirce takes the
second option. This set has cardinality 2 (it has exactly 2 members) but it is
not the best we can do. Peirces discovery of what we have called the Sheffer
functions or strokes (anachronistically and unfairly to Peirce, as Grice notes,
but bowing to convention) shows that we can have a set of cardinality 1 (a
one-member set or a so-called singleton) that is minimally functionally
complete with respect to the definable connectives of two-valued propositional
logic. Thus, either one of the following sets can do. The sets are functionally
complete and, because they have only one member each, we say that the
connectives themselves have the property of functional completeness. / is the
symbol of Sheffers stroke or nand and /is the symbol of the Peirce Arrow
or nor. Grice stipulates as such, even though he does not introduce his grammar
formally. It is important to show ow these functions can define other
functions. Algebraically approached, this is a matter of functional
composition In case one wonders why the satisfaction with defining the
connectives of the set that comprises the symbols for negation, inclusive
disjunction, and conjunction, Namesly , there is an explanation. There is
an easy, although informal, way to show that this set is functionally complete.
It is not minimally functionally complete because and are
inter-definable. But it is functionally complete. Thus, showing that one can
define these functions suffices for achieving functional completeness. Definability
should be thought as logical equivalence. One connective can be defined by
means of others if and only if the formulas in the definition (what is defined
and what is doing the defining) are logically equivalent. Presuppose the
truth-tabular definitions of the connectives. and and and and and .
Grice enjoyed that. Meanwhile, at Corpus, Grice is involved in serious
philosophical studies under the tutelage of Hardie. While his philosophical
socialising is limited, having been born on the wrong side of the tracks,
first at Corpus, and then at Merton, and ending at St. Johns, Grice fails to
attend the seminal meetings at All Souls held on Thursday evenings by the play
group of the seven (Austin, Ayer, Berlin, Hampshire, MacDermott, MacNabb, and
Woozley). Three of them will join Grice in the new play group after the war:
Austin, Hampshire, and Woozley. But at St. Johns Grice tutors Strawson, and
learns all about the linguistic botany methodology on his return from the navy.
Indeed, his being appointed Strawson as his tutee starts a life-long friendship
and collaboration.
IDENTITY: Grice advocates psychological or soul criterianism.
Psychological or soul criterianism has been advocated, in one form or another,
by philosophers such as Locke, Butler, Duncan-Jones, Berkeley, Gallie, Grice,
Flew, Haugeland, Jones, Perry, Shoemaker and Parfit, and Quinton. What all
of those theories have in common is the idea that, even if it is the case that
some kind of physical states are necessary for being a person, it is the unity
of consciousness which is of decisive importance for personal identity over
time. In this sense, person is a term which picks out a psychological, or
mental, "thing". In claiming this, all Psychological Criterianists
entail the view that personal identity consists in the continuity of psychological
features. It is interesting that Flew has an earlier "Selves,"
earlier THAN his essay on Locke on personal identity. The first, for
Mind, criticising Jones, "The self in sensory cognition."; the second
for Philosophy. Surely under the tutelage of Grice. Cf. Jones, Selves: A reply
to Flew, Philosophy. The stronger thesis asserts that there is no
conceivable situation in which bodily identity would be necessary, some other
conditions being always both necessary and sufficient. Grice takes it that
Locke’s theory (II, 27) is an example of this latter type. To say
"Grice remembers that he heard a noise", without irony or
inverted commas, is to imply that Grice did hear a noise. In this respect
remember is like, know , a factive. It does not follow from this, nor is it
true, that each claim to remember, any more than each claim to know, is alethic
or veridical; or, not everything one seems to remember is something one really
remembers. So much is obvious, although Locke -- although admittedly
referring only to the memory of actions, section 13 -- is forced to
invoke the providence of God to deny the latter. These points have been
emphasised by Flew in his discussion of Locke’s views on personal identity. In
formulating Locke’ thesis, however, Flew makes a mistake; for he offers Lockes
thesis in the form if Grice can remember Hardies doing such-and-such, Grice and
Hardie are the same person. But this obviously will not do, even for Locke, for
we constantly say things like I remember my brother Derek joining the army
without implying that I and my brother are the same person. So if we are to
formulate such a criterion, it looks as though we have to say something like
the following. If Derek Grice remembers joining my, he is the person who did
that thing. But since remembers doing means remembers himself doing, this is
trivially tautologous, and moreover lends colour to Butlers famous objection
that memory, so far from constituting personal identity, presupposes
it. As Butler puts it, one should really think it self-evident that
consciousness of personal identity presupposes, and therefore cannot
constitute, personal identity; any more than knowledge, in any other case, can
constitute truth, which it presupposes. Butler then asserts that Lockes misstep
stems from his methodology. This wonderful mistake may possibly have arisen
from hence; that to be endued with consciousness is inseparable from the idea
of a person, or intelligent being. For this might be expressed inaccurately
thus, that consciousness makes personality: and from hence it might be
concluded to make personal identity. One of the points that Locke
emphasizes—that persistence conditions are determined via defining kind
terms—is what, according to Butler, leads Locke astray. Butler additionally
makes the point that memory is not required for personal persistence. But
though present consciousness of what we at present do and feel is necessary to
our being the persons we now are; yet present consciousness of past actions or
feelings is not necessary to our being the same persons who performed those
actions, or had those feelings. This is a point that others develop when they
assert that Lockes view results in contradiction. Hence the criterion
should rather run as follows. If Derek Grice claims to remember joining the
army. We must then ask how such a criterion might be used. Grices
example is: I remember I smelled a smell. He needs two experiences to use same.
I heard a noise and I smelled a smell.The singular defines the hearing of a noise
is the object of some consciousness. The pair defines, "The hearing of a
noise and the smelling of a smell are objects of the same -- cognate with self
as in I hurt me self, -- consciousness. The standard form of an identity
question is Is this x the same x as that x which ? and in the simpler
situation we are at least presented with just the materials for constructing
such a question; but in the more complicated situation we are baffled even in
asking the question, since both the transformed persons are equally good
candidates for being its Subjects, and the question Are these two xs the same
(x?) as the x which ? is not a
recognizable form of identity question. Thus, it might be argued, the fact that
we could not speak of identity in the latter situation is no kind of proof that
we could not do so in the former. Certainly it is not a proof, as Strawson
pointed out to Grice. This is not to say that they are identical at all. The
only case in which identity and exact similarity could be distinguished, as we
have just seen, is that of the body, same body and exactly similar body really
do mark a difference. Thus one may claim that the omission of the body takes
away all content from the idea of personal identity, as Pears pointed out to
Grice. Leaving aside memory, which only partially applies to the case,
character and attainments are quite clearly general things. Joness character
is, in a sense, a particular; just because Jones’s character refers to the
instantiation of certain properties by a particular (and bodily) man, as
Strawson points out to Grice (Particular and general). If in ‘Negation and
privation,’ Grice tackles Aristotle, he now tackles Locke. Indeed, seeing that
Grice went years later to the topic as motivated by, of all people, Haugeland,
rather than perhaps the more academic milieu that Perry offers, Grice became
obsessed with Hume’s sceptical doubts! Hume writes in the Appendix that when he
turns his reflection on himself, Hume never can perceive this self without
some one or more perceptions. Nor can Hume ever perceive any thing but
the perceptions. It is the composition of these, therefore, which forms
the self, Hume thinks. Hume grants that one can conceive a thinking being to
have either many or few perceptions. Suppose, says Hume, the mind to be reduced
even below the life of an oyster. Suppose the oyster to have only one
perception, as of thirst or hunger. Consider the oyster in that situation. Does
the oyster conceive any thing but merely that perception? Has the oyster any
notion of, to use Gallies pretentious Aristotelian jargon, self or substance?
If not, the addition of this or other perception can never give the oyster
that notion. The annihilation, which this or that philosopher, including Grices
first post-war tutee, Flew, supposes to follow upon death, and which
entirely destroys the oysters self, is nothing but an
extinction of all particular perceptions; love and
hatred, pain and pleasure, thought and sensation. These therefore
must be the same with self; since the one cannot survive the other.
Is self the same with substance? If it be, how can that question have place, concerning
the subsistence of self, under a change of substance? If they be distinct,
what is the difference betwixt them? For his part, Hume claims, he has a notion
of neither, when conceived distinct from this or that particular
perception. However extraordinary Hume’s conclusion may
seem, it need not surprise us. Most philosophers, such as Locke,
seems inclined to think, that personal identity arises from consciousness.
But consciousness is nothing but a reflected thought or perception, Hume
suggests. This is Grices quandary about personal identity and its implicata.
Some philosophers have taken Grice as trying to provide an exegesis of Locke.
However, their approaches surely differ. What works for Grice may not work for
Locke. For Grice it is analytically true that it is not the case that Person1 and
Person may have the same experience. Grice explicitly states that he
thinks that his logical-construction theory is a modification of Locke’s
theory. Grice does not seem terribly interested to find why it may not, even if
the York-based Locke Society might! Rather than introjecting into Lockes shoes,
Grices strategy seems to dismiss Locke, shoes and all. Specifically, it not
clear to Grice what Lockes answer in the Essay would be to Grices question
about this or that I utterance that he sets his analysis with. Admittedly,
Grice does quote, albeit briefly, directly from Lockes Essay. As far as any
intelligent being can repeat the idea of any past action with the same
consciousness it had of it at first, and with the same consciousness it has of
any present action, Locke claims, so far the being is the same personal self.
Grice tackles Lockes claim with four objections. These are important to
consider since Grice sees as improving on Locke. A first objection concerns
icircularity, with which Grice easily disposes by following Hume and appealing
to the experience of memory or introspection. A second objection is Reid’s
alleged counterexample about the long-term memory of the admiral who cannot
remember that he was flogged as a boy. Grice dismisses this as involving too
long-term of a memory. A third objection concerns Locke’s vagueness about the
aboutness of consciousness, a point made by Hume in the Appendix. A fourth
objection concerns again circularity, this time in Locke’s use of same in the
definiens ‒ cf. Wiggins, Sameness and substance. It’s extraordinary that
Wiggins is philosophising on anything Griceian. Grice is concerned with the
implicatum involved in the use of the first person singular. I will be fighting
soon. Grice means in body and soul. The utterance also indicates that this is
Grices pre-war days at Oxford. No wonder his choice of an example. What else
could he have in his soul? The topic of personal identity, which label Hume and
Austin found pretentious, and preferred to talk about the illocutionary force
of I, has a special Oxonian pedigree, perhaps as motivated by Humes challenge,
that Grice has occasion to study and explore for his M. A. Lit. Hum. with
Locke’s Essay as mandatory reading. Locke, a philosopher with whom Oxford
identifies most, infamously defends this memory-based account of I. Up in
Scotland, Reid reads it and concocts this alleged counter-example. Hume, or
Home, if you must, enjoys it. In fact, while in the Mind essay he is not too
specific about Hume, Grice will, due mainly to his joint investigations with
Haugeland, approach, introjecting into the shoes of Hume ‒ who is idolised in
The New World ‒ in ways he does not introject into Lockes. But Grices quandary
is Hume’s quandary, too. In his own approach to I, the Cartesian ego, made
transcendental and apperceptive by Kant, Grice updates the time-honoured
empiricist mnemonic analysis by Locke. The first update is in style. Grice
embraces, as he does with negation, a logical construction, alla Russell, via
Broad, of this or that I utterance, ending up with an analysis of a someone,
less informative, utterance. Grices immediate source is Gallies essay on self
and substance in the pages of Mind. Mind was still a review of psychology and
philosophy, so poor Grice had no much choice. In fact, Grice is being
heterodoxical or heretic enough to use the Broads taxonomy, straight from the
other place of I utterances. The logical-construction theory is a third
proposal, next to the Bradleyian idealist pure-ego theory and the
misleading covert-description theory. Grice deals with the Reids alleged
counterexample of the brave officer. Suppose, Reid says, and Grice quotes
verbatim, a brave officer to have been flogged when a boy at school, for
robbing an orchard, to have taken a standard from the enemy in his first
campaign, and to have been made a general in advanced life. Suppose also, which
must be admitted to be possible, that when he2 took the
standard, he2 was conscious of his having been flogged at school,
and that, when made a general, he3 was conscious of his2 taking
the standard, but had absolutely lost the consciousness of his1 flogging. These
things being supposed, it follows, from Lockes doctrine, that he1 who is
flogged at school is the same person as him2 who later takes
the standard, and that he2 who later takes the standard is the
same person as him3 who is still later made a general. When it
follows, if there be any truth in logic, that the general is the same person
with him1 who is flogged at school. But the general’s
consciousness does emphatically not reach so far back as his1 flogging.
Therefore, according to Locke’s doctrine, he3 is emphatically
not the same person as him1 who is flogged. Therefore, we can say about the
general that he3 is, and at the same time, that he3 is
not the same person as him1 who was flogged at
school. Grice, wholl later add a temporal suffix to =t yielding, by
transitivity. The flogged boy =t1 the brave officer. And the
brave officer =t2 the admiral. But the admiral ≠t3 the
flogged boy. In Mind, Grice tackles the basic analysans, and comes up with a
rather elaborate analysans for a simple I or Someone statement. Grice just
turns to a generic affirmative variant of the utterance he had used in
Negation. It is now someone, viz. I, who hears that the bell tolls. It is the
affirmative counterpart of the focus of his earlier essay on negation, I do not
hear that the bell tolls. Grice dismisses what, in the other place, was
referred to as privileged-access, and the indexicality of I, an approach that
will be made popular by Perry, who however reprints Grices essay in his
influential collection for the University of California Press. By allowing for
someone, viz. I, Grice seems to be relying on a piece of reasoning which hell
later, in his first Locke lecture, refer to as too good. I hear that the bell
tolls; therefore, someone hears that the bell tolls. Grice attempts to reduce
this or that I utterance (Someone, viz. I, hears that the bell tolls) is in
terms of a chain or sequence of mnemonic states. It poses a few quandaries
itself. While quoting from this or that recent philosopher such as Gallie and
Broad, it is a good thing that Grice has occasion to go back to, or revisit,
Locke and contest this or that infamous and alleged counterexample presented by
Reid and Hume. Grice adds a methodological note to his proposed
logical-construction theory of personal identity. There is some intricacy of
his reductive analysis, indeed logical construction, for an apparently simple and
harmless utterance (cf. his earlier essay on I do not hear that the bell
tolls). But this intricacy does not prove the analysis wrong. Only that Grice
is too subtle. If the reductive analysis of not is in terms of each state which
I am experiencing is incompatible with phi), that should not be a minus, or
drawback, but a plus, and an advantage in terms of philosophical progress. The
same holds here in terms of the concept of a temporary state. Much later,
Grice reconsiders, or revisits, indeed, Broads remark and re-titles his
approach as the (or a) logical-construction theory of personal identity. And,
with Haugeland, Grice re-considers Humes own vagaries, or quandary, with
personal identity. Unlike the more conservative Locke that Grice favours in the
pages of Mind, eliminationist Hume sees ‘I’ as a conceptual muddle, indeed a
metaphysical chimæra. Hume presses the point for an empiricist verificationist
account of I. For, as Russell would rhetorically ask, ‘What can be more direct that
the experience of myself?’ The Hume Society should take notice of Grices
simplification of Hume’s implicatum on I, if The Locke Society won’t. As a
matter of fact, Grice calls one of his metaphysical construction routines the
Humeian projection, so it is not too adventurous to think that Grice considers
I as an intuitive concept that needs to be metaphysically re-constructed
and be given a legitimate Fregeian sense. Why that label for a construction
routine? Grice calls this metaphysical construction routine Humeian projection,
since the mind (or soul) as it were, spreads over its objects. But, by mind,
Hume does not necessarily mean the I. Cf. The minds I. Grice is especially
concerned with the poverty and weaknesses of Humes criticism to Lockes account
of personal identity. Grice opts to revisit the Lockeian memory-based of this
or that someone, viz. I utterance that Hume rather regards as vague, and
confusing. Unlike Humes, neither Lockes nor Grices reductive analysis of
personal identity is reductionist and eliminationist. The
reductive-reductionist distinction Grice draws in Retrospective epilogue as he
responds to Rountree-Jack on this or that alleged wrong on meaning that. It is
only natural that Grice would be sympathetic to Locke. Grice explores these
issues with J. C. Haugeland mainly at seminars. One may wonder why Grice spends
so much time in a philosopher such as Hume, with whom he agreed almost on
nothing! The answer is Humes influence in the Third World that forced Grice to
focus on this or that philosopher. Surely Locke is less popular in the New
World than Hume is. One supposes Grice is trying to save Hume at the implicatum
level, at least. The phrase or term of art, logical construction is Russells
and Broads, but Grice loved it. Rational reconstruction is not too dissimilar.
Grice prefers Russells and Broads more conservative label. This is more than a
terminological point. If Hume is right and there is NO intuitive concept behind
I, one cannot strictly re-construct it, only construct it. Ultimately, Grice
shows that, if only at the implicatum level, we are able to provide an
analysandum for this or that someone, viz. I utterance without using I, by
implicating only this or that mnemonic concept, which belongs, naturally, as
his theory of negation does, in a theory of philosophical psychology, and again
a lower branch of it, dealing with memory. The topic of personal identity
unites various interests of Grice. The first is identity (=) simpliciter.
Instead of talking of the meaning of I, as, say, Anscombe would, Grice sticks
to the traditional category, or keyword, for this, i. e. the theory-laden,
personal identity, or even personal sameness. Personal identity is a type of
identity, but personal adds something to it. Surely Hume was stretching person
a bit when using the example of a soul with a life lower than an oyster. Since
Grice follows Aristotles De Anima, he enjoys Hume’s choice, though. It may be
argued that personal adds Locke’s consciousness, and rational agency. Grice
plays with the body-soul distinction. I, viz someone or somebody, fell from the
stairs, perhaps differs from I will be fighting soon. This or that someone,
viz. I utterance may be purely bodily. Grice would think that the idea that his
soul fell from the stairs sounds, as it would to Berkeley, harsh. But then
theres this or that one may be mixed utterance. Someone, viz. I, plays cricket,
where surely your bodily mechanisms require some sort of control by the soul.
Finally, this or that may be purely souly ‒ the one Grice ends up analysing, Someone,
viz. I, hear that the bell tolls. At the time of his Mind essay, Grice may have
been unaware of the complications that the concept of a person may bring as
attached in adjective form to identity. Ayer did, and Strawson and Wiggins
will, and Grice learns much from Strawson. Since Parfit, this has become a
common-place topic for analysis at Oxford. A person as a complexum of a
body-soul spatio-temporal continuant substance. Ultimately, Grice finds a
theoretical counterpart here. A pirot may become a human, which Grice
understands physiologically. That is not enough. A pirot must aspire, via
meteousis, to become a person. Thus, person becomes a technical term in Grices
grand metaphysical scheme of things. Someone, viz. I, hear that the bell is
tolls is analysed as ≡df, or if and only if, a hearing that the
bell tolls is a part of a total temporary tn souly state S1 which is
one in a s. such that any state Sn, given this or that
condition, contains as a part a memory Mn of the
experience of hearing that the bell tolls, which is a component in some
pre-sequent t1n item, or contains an experience of hearing
that the bell tolls a memory M of which would, given this or that
condition, occur as a component in some sub-sequent t2>tn item,
there being no sub-set of items which is independent of the rest. Grice
simplifies the reductive analysans. Someone, viz. I, hears that the bell tolls
iff a hearing that the bell tolls is a component in an item of an interlocking s.
with emphasis on lock, s. of this or that memorable and memorative total
temporary tn state S1. Is Grices Personal identity
ever referred to in the Oxonian philosophical literature? Indeeed. Parfit
mentions, which makes it especially memorable and memorative. P. Edwards
includes a reference to Grices Mind essay in the entry for Personal identity,
as a reference to Grice et al on Met. , is referenced in Edwardss encyclopædia
entry for metaphysics. Grice does not attribute privileged access or
incorrigibility to I or the first person. He always hastens to add that I can
always be substituted, salva veritate (if baffling your addressee A) by someone
or other, if not some-body or other, a colloquialism Grice especially detested.
Grices agency-based approach requires that. I am rational provided thou art,
too. If, by explicitly saying he is a Lockeian, Grice surely does not wish us
to see him as trying to be original, or the first to consider this or that
problem about I; i.e. someone. Still, Grice is the philosopher who explores
most deeply the reductive analysis of I, i.e. someone. Grice needs the
reductive analysis because human agency (philosophically, rather than
psychologically interpreted) is key for his approach to things. By uttering The
bell tolls, U means that someone, viz. himself, hears that the bell tolls, or
even, by uttering I, hear, viz. someone hears, that the bell tolls, U means
that the experience of a hearing that the bell tolls is a component in a
total temporary state which is a member of a s. such that each member
would, given certain conditions, contain as an component one
memory of an experience which is a component in a pre-sequent member, or
contains as a component some experience a memory of which would,
given certain conditions, occur as a component in a post-sequent member;
there being no sub-set of members which is independent of the rest.
Thanks, the addressee might reply. I didnt know that! The reductive bit to
Grices analysis needs to be emphasised. For Grice, a person, and consequently,
a someone, viz. I utterance, is, simpliciter, a logical construction out of
this or that Humeian experience. Whereas in Russell, as Broad notes, a
logical construction of this or that philosophical concept, in this case
personal identity, or cf. Grices earlier reductive analysis of not, is thought
of as an improved, rationally reconstructed conception. Neither Russell nor
Broad need maintain that the logical construction preserves the original
meaning of the analysandum someone, viz. I, hears that the bell tolls, or I do
not hear that the bell tolls ‒ hence their paradox of reductionist analysis.
This change of Subjects does not apply to Grice. Grice emphatically intends to
be make explicit, if rationally reconstructed (if that is not an
improvement) through reductive (if not reductionist) analysis, the concept
Grice already claims to have. One particular development to consider is within
Grices play group, that of Quinton. Grice and Quinton seem to have been the
only two philosophers in Austins play group who showed any interest on someone,
viz. I. Or not!The fact that Quinton entitled his thing The soul didnt help.
Note that Woozley was editing Reid on “Identity” in 1941. Cf. Duncan-Jones on
mans mortality. Note that Quintons immediate trigger is Shoemaker. Grice writes
that he is not “merely a s. of perceptions,” for he is “conscious of a
permanent self, an I who experiences these perceptions and who is now
identical with the I who experienced perceptions yesterday.” So, leaving aside
that he is using I with the third person verb, but surely this is no
use-mention fallacy, it is this puzzle that provoked his thoughts on
temporal-relative “=” later on. As Grice notes, Butler argued that
consciousness of experience can contribute to identity but not define it. Grice
will use Butler in his elaboration of conversational benevolence versus
conversational self-interest. Better than Quinton, it is better to consider
Flew in Philosophy, 96, on Locke and the problem of personal identity,
obviously suggested as a term paper by Grice! Wiggins cites Flew. Flew actually
notes that Berkeley saw Lockes problem earlier than Reid, which concerns the
transitiveness of =. Recall that Wigginss tutor at Oxford was a tutee by Grice,
Ackrill.
SCEPTICISM: What is Grice’s answer to the sceptic’s implicature? The
sceptic’s implicatum is a topic that always fascinated Girce. While Grice
groups two essays as dealing with one single theme, strictly, only this or that
philosopher’s paradox (not all) may count as sceptical. This or that
philosopher’s paradox may well not be sceptical at all but rather dogmatic. In
fact, Grice defines philosophers paradox as anything repugnant to common sense,
shocking, or extravagant ‒ to Malcolms ears, that is! While it is,
strictly, slightly odd to quote this as (1946) just because, by a stroke of the
pen, Grice writes that date in the Harvard volume, we will follow his
charming practice. This is vintage Grice. Grice always takes the
sceptics challenge seriously, as any serious philosopher should. Grices
takes both the sceptics explicatum and the scepticss implicatum as
self-defeating, as a very affront to our idea of rationality, conversational or
other. V: Conversations with a sceptic: Can he be slightly more conversational
helpful? Hume’ sceptical attack is partial, and targeted only towards
practical reason, though. Yet, for Grice, reason is one. You cannot
really attack practical or buletic reason without attacking theoretical or
doxastic reason. There is such thing as a general rational acceptance, to use
Grice’s term, that the sceptic is getting at. Grice likes to play with the idea
that ultimately every syllogism is buletic or practical. If, say, a syllogism
by Eddington looks doxastic, that is because Eddington cares to omit the
practical tail, as Grice puts it. And Eddington is not even a philosopher, they
say. Grice is here concerned with a Cantabrigian topic popularised by
Moore. As Grice recollects, Some like Witters, but Moore’s my man.
Unlike Cambridge analysts such as Moore, Grice sees himself as a
linguistic-turn Oxonian analyst. So it is only natural that Grice would connect
time-honoured scepticism of Pyrrhos vintage, and common sense with
ordinary language, so mis-called, the elephant in Grices room. L and S
have σκέψις, from σκέπτομαι, which they render as viewing, perception by the
senses, ἡ διὰ τῶν ὀμμάτων ςκέψις, Pl. Phd. 83a; observation of auguries,
Hdn. 8. 3. 7., also as examination, speculation, consideration, τὸ εὕρημα
πολλῆς σκέψιος Hp. VM4, cf. Pl. Alc. 1.130d; βραχείας ςκέψις Id. Tht.
201a; ϝέμειν ςκέψις take thought of a thing, v. l. in E. Hi1323; ἐνθεὶς τῇ
τέχνῃ ςκέψις Ar. Ra. 974; ςκέψις ποιεῖσθαι Pl. Phdr. 237d;
ςκέψις προβέβληκας Id. Phlb. 65d; ςκέψις λόγων Id. R. 336e;
ςκέψις περί τινος inquiry into, speculation on a thing, Id. Grg. 487e,
etc.; περί τι Id. Lg. 636d;ἐπὶ σκέψιν τινὸς ἐλθεῖν X. Oec. 6.13.2. speculation,
inquiry,ταῦτα ἐξωτερικωτέρας ἐστὶ σκέψεως Arist. Pol. 1254a34; ἔξω τῆς νῦν
ςκέψεως Id. Ph. 228a20; οὐκ οἰκεῖα τῆς παρούσης ςκέψις Id. EN 1155b9,
etc., also hesitation, doubt, esp. of the Sceptic or Pyrthonic philosophers, AP
7. 576 (Jul.); the Sceptic philosophy, S. E. P. 1.5; οἱ ἀπὸ τῆς
ςκέψεως, the Sceptics, ib. 229. in politics, resolution, decree, συνεδρίον
Hdn. 4.3.9, cf. Poll. 6.178. If scepticism attacks common sense and fails,
Grice seems to be implicating, that ordinary language philosophy is a good
antidote to scepticism. Since what language other than ordinary language does
common sense speak? Well, strictly, common sense doesnt speak. The man in the
street does. Grice addresses this topic in a Mooreian way in a later essay,
also repr. in Studies, Moore and philosophers paradoxes, repr. in Studies.
As with his earlier Common sense and scepticism, Grice tackles Moores and Malcolms
claim that ordinary language, so-called, solves a few of philosophers
paradoxes. Philosopher is Grices witty way to generalise over your
common-or-garden, any, philosopher, especially of the type he found eccentric,
the sceptic included. Grice finds this or that problem in this overarching
Cantabrigian manoeuvre, as over-simplifying a pretty convoluted
terrain. While he cherishes Austins Some like Witters, but Moores MY man!
Grice finds Moore too Cantabrigian to his taste. While an Oxonian thoroughbred,
Grice is a bit like Austin, Some like Witters, but Moores my man, with this or
that caveat. Again, as with his treatment of Descartes or Locke, Grice is
hardly interested in finding out what Moore really means. He is a philosopher,
not a historian of philosophy, and he knows it. While Grice agrees with Austins
implicature that Moore goes well above Witters, if that is the expression (even
if some like him), we should find the Oxonian equivalent to Moore. Grice would
not Names Ryle, since he sees him, and his followers, almost every day. There
is something apostolic about Moore that Grice enjoys, which is just as well,
seeing that Moore is one of the twelve. Grice found it amusing that the
members of The Conversazione Society would still be nickNamesd apostles when
their number exceeded the initial 12. Grice spends some time exploring what
Malcolm, a follower of Witters, which does not help, as it were, has to say
about Moore in connection with that particularly Oxonian turn of phrase, such
as ordinary language is. For Malcolms Moore, a paradox by philosopher
[sic], including the sceptic, arises when philosopher [sic], including the
sceptic, fails to abide by the dictates of ordinary language. It might merit
some exploration if Moore’s defence of common sense is against: the sceptic may
be one, but also the idealist. Moore the realist, armed with ordinary language
attacks the idealists claim. The idealist is sceptical of the realists claim.
But empiricist idealism (Bradley) has at Oxford as good pedigree as empiricist
realism (Cook Wilson). Malcolm’s simplifications infuriate Grice, and ordinary
language has little to offer in the defense of common sense realism against sceptical
empiricist idealism. Surely the ordinary man says ridiculous, or silly, as
Russell prefers, things, such as Smith is lucky, Departed spirits walk along
this road on their way to Paradise, I know there are infinite stars, and I wish
I were Napoleon, or I wish that I had been Napoleon, which does
not mean that the utterer wishes that he were like Napoleon, but
that he wishes that he had lived not in the his century but in
the XVIIIth century. Grice is being specific about this. It is true
that an ordinary use of language, as Malcolm suggests, cannot be self-contradictory
unless the ordinary use of language is defined by stipulation as not
self-contradictory, in which case an appeal to ordinary language becomes
useless against this or that paradox by Philosopher. I wish that I had been
Napoleon seems to involve nothing but an ordinary use of language by any
standard but that of freedom from absurdity. I wish that I had been
Napoleon is not, as far as Grice can see, philosophical, but something which
may have been said and meant by numbers of ordinary people. Yet, I wish that
I had been Napoleon is open to the suspicion of self-contradictoriness,
absurdity, or some other kind of meaninglessness. And in this context
suspicion is all Grice needs. By uttering I wish that I had been Napoleon
U hardly means the same as he would if he uttered I wish I were like Napoleon.
I wish that I had been Napoleon is suspiciously self-contradictory, absurd, or
meaningless, if, as uttered by an utterer in a century other than the XVIIIth
century, say, the utterer is understood as expressing the proposition that the
utterer wishes that he had lived in the XVIIIth century, and not in his
century, in which case he-1 wishes that he had not been him-1? But blame
it on the buletic. That Moore himself is not too happy with Malcolms
criticism can be witnessed by a cursory glimpse at hi reply to Malcolm. Grice
is totally against this view that Malcolm ascribes to Moore as a view that is
too broad to even claim to be true. Grices implicature is that Malcolm is
appealing to Oxonian turns of phrase, such as ordinary language, but not taking
proper Oxonian care in clarifying the nuances and stuff in dealing with,
admittedly, a non-Oxonian philosopher such as Moore. When dealing with Moore,
Grice is not necessarily concerned with scepticism. Time is unreal, e.g. is
hardly a sceptic utterance. Yet Grice lists it as one of Philosophers paradoxes.
So, there are various to consider here. Grice would start with common sense.
That is what he does when he reprints this essay in WOW, with his attending
note in both the preface and the Retrospective epilogue on how he organizes the
themes and strands. Common sense is one keyword there, with its attending
realism. Scepticism is another, with its attending empiricist idealism. It is
intriguing that in the first two essays opening Grices explorations in
semantics and metaphysics it seems its Malcolm, rather than the dryer Moore,
who interests Grice most. While he would provide exegeses of this or that
dictum by Moore, and indeed, Moore’s response to Malcolm, Grice seems to be
more concerned with applications of his own views. Notably in Philosophers
paradoxes. The fatal objection Grice finds for the paradox propounder (not
necessarily a sceptic, although a sceptic may be one of the paradox
propounders) significantly rests on Grices reductive analysis of meaning
that as ascribed to this or that utterer
U. Grice elaborates on circumstances that hell later take up in the
Retrospective epilogue. I find myself not understanding what I mean is
dubiously acceptable. If meaning, Grice claims, is about an utterer U intending
to get his addressee A to believe that U ψ-s that p, U must think there is a
good chance that A will recognise what he is supposed to believe, by, perhaps,
being aware of the Us practice or by a supplementary explanation which might
come from U. In which case, U should not be meaning what Malcolm claims U might
mean. No utterer should intend his addressee to believe what is conceptually
impossible, or incoherent, or blatantly false (Charles Is decapitation willed
Charles Is death.), unless you are Queen in Through the Looking Glass. I
believe five impossible things before breakfast, and I hope youll soon get the
proper training to follow suit. Cf. Tertulian, Credo, quia absurdum est.
Admittedly, Grice edits the Philosophers paradoxes essay. It is only Grices
final objection which is reprinted in Studies, even if he provides a good
detailed summary of the previous sections. Grice appeals to Moore on later
occasions. In Causal theory, Grice lists, as a third philosophical
mistake, the opinion by Malcolm that Moore did not know how to use knowin a
sentence. Grice brings up the same example again in Prolegomena. The use of
factive know of Moore may well be a misuse. While at Madison, Wisconsin, Moore
lectures at a hall eccentrically-built with indirect lighting simulating sun
rays, Moore infamously utters, I know that there is a window behind that curtain,
when there is not. But it is not the factiveness Grice is aiming at, but the
otiosity Malcolm misdescribes in the true, if baffling, I know that I have two
hands. In Retrospective epilogue, Grice uses M to abbreviate Moore’s fairy
godmother – along with G (Grice), A (Austin), R (Ryle) and Q (Quine)! One
simple way to approach Grices quandary with Malcolm’s quandary with Moore is
then to focus on know. How can Malcolm claim that Moore is guilty of misusing
know? The most extensive exploration by Grice on know is in Grices third James
lecture (but cf. his seminar on Knowledge and belief, and his remarks on some
of our beliefs NEEDING to be true, in Meaning revisited. The examinee
knows that the battle of Waterloo was fought in 1815. Nothing odd about that,
nor about Moores uttering I know that these are my hands. Grice is perhaps the
only one of the Oxonian philosophers of Austins play group who took common
sense realsim so seriously, if only to crticise Malcoms zeal with it. For
Grice, common-sense realism = ordinary language, whereas for the typical
Austinian, ordinary language = the language of the man in the street. Back at
Oxford, Grice uses Malcolm to contest the usual criticism that Oxford
ordinary-language philosophers defend common-sense realist assumptions just
because the way non-common-sense realist philosopher’s talk is not ordinary
language, and even at Oxford. Cf. Flews reference to Joness philosophical
verbal rubbish in using self as a noun. Grice is infuriated by all this unclear
chatter, and chooses Malcolms mistreatment of Moore as an example. Grice is
possibly fearful to consider Austins claims directly! In later essays, such as
The learned and the lay, Grice goes back to the topic criticising now the
scientists jargon as an affront to the ordinary language of the layman that
Grice qua philosopher defends.
COMMUNICATION: This is the Peirce in Grice’s soul. Meaning
provides an excellent springboard for Grice to centre his analysis on
psychological or soul-y verbs as involving the agent and the first person:
smoke only figuratively means fire, and the expression smoke only figuratively
(or metabolically) means that there is fire. It is this or that utterer (say,
Grice) who means, say, by uttering Where theres smoke theres fire, or ubi
fumus, ibi ignis, that where theres smoke theres fire. A meantNN something
by x, an utterance-token is (roughly) equivalent to utterer U intends the
utterance of x to produce some effect in his addressee A by means of the
recognition of this intention; and we may add that to ask what U means is to
ask for a specification of the intended effect - though, of course, it may not
always be possible to get a straight answer involving a that-clause, for
example, a belief that He does provide a
more specific example involving the that-clause at a later stage. By uttering x
the utterer U means that-ψb-dp iff (Ǝ.φ).(Ǝ.f).(Ǝ.c):
I. U utters x intending x to be such that anyone who has φ will think
that (i) x has f (ii) f is correlated in way c with ψ-ing that p (iii) (Ǝ.φ): U intends x to be
such that anyone who has φ will think, via thinking (i) and (ii),
that U ψ-s that p (iv) in view of (3), U ψ-s that p; and II (operative only for
certain substituends for ψb-d). U utters x intending that, should there actually be anyone who
has φ, he will, via thinking (iv), himself ψ that p; and III. It is not the
case that, for some inference-element E, U intends x to be such that anyone who
has φ will both (i) rely on E in coming to ψ (or think that U ψ-s) that p and (ii) think that (Ǝ.φ): U
intends x to be such that anyone who has φ will come to ψ (or think that U ψ-s) that p without relying on E. Besides St.
John The Baptist, and Salome, Grice cites few Namess in Meaning. But he makes a
point about Stevenson! For Stevenson, smoke means fire. Meaning develops out of
an interest by Grice on the philosophy of Peirce. In his essays on Peirce,
Grice quotes from many other authors, including, besides Peirce himself (!),
Ogden, Richards, and Ewing, or A. C. Virtue is not a fire-shovel Ewing, as
Grice calls him, and this or that cricketer. In the characteristic Oxonian fashion
of a Lit. Hum., Grice has no intention to submit Meaning to publication.
Publishing is vulgar. Bennett, however, guesses that Grice decides to publish
it just a year after his Defence of a dogma. Bennett’s argument is that Defence
of a dogma pre-supposes some notion of meaning. However, a different story may
be told, not necessarily contradicting Bennetts. It is Strawson who submits the
essay by Grice to The Philosophical Review. Strawson attends Grices talk on
Meaning for The Oxford Philosophical Society, and likes it. Since In defence of
a dogma was co-written with Strawson, the intention Bennett ascribes to Grice
is Strawsons. Oddly, Strawson later provides a famous alleged counter-example
to Grice on meaning in Intention and convention in speech acts, following J. O.
Urmson’s earlier attack to the sufficiency of Grices analysans -- which has
Grice dedicating a full James lecture (No. 5) to it. Urmsons case involved a
tutee offering to buy Gardiner an expensive dinner, hoping that Gardiner will
give him permission for an over-night visit to London. Gardiner knows
that his tutee wants his permission. The appropriate analysans for "By
offering to buy Gardiner an expensive dinner, the tuttee means that Gardiner
should give him permission for an overnight stay in London" are fulfilled:
(1) The tutee offers to buy Gardiner an expensive dinner with the intention of
producing a certain response on the part of Gardiner (2) The tutee intends that
Gardiner should recognize (know, think) that the tutee is offering to buy him
an expensive dinner with the intention of producing this response; (3) The
tutee intends that Gardiners recognition (thought) that the tutee has the
intention mentioned in (2) should be at least part of Gardiners reason for
producing the response mentioned. If in general to specify in (i) the nature of
an intended response is to specify what was meant, it should be correct not
only to say that by offering to buy Gardiner an expensive dinner, the tutee
means that Gardiner is to give him permission for an overnight stay in London,
but also to say that he meas that Gardiner should (is to) give him permission
for an over-night visit to London. But in fact one would not wish to say either
of these things; only that the tutee meant Gardiner to give him permission. A
restriction seems to be required, and one which might serve to eliminate this
range of counterexamples can be identified from a comparison of two scenarios.
Grice goes into a tobacconists shop, ask for a packet of my favorite cigarettes,
and when the unusually suspicious tobacconist shows that he wants to see the
color of my money before he hands over the goods, I put down the price of the
cigarettes on the counter. Here nothing has been meant. Alternatively, Grice
goes to his regular tobacconist (from whom I also purchase other goods) for a
packet of my regular brand of Players Navy Cuts, the price of which is
distinctive (say 43p). I say nothing, but put down 43p. The tobacconist
recognizes my need, and hands over the packet. Here, I think, by putting down
43p I meant something-Namesly, that I wanted a packet of Players Navy Cuts. I
have at the same time provided an inducement. The distinguishing feature of the
second example seems to be that here the tobacconist recognized, and was intended
to recognize, what he was intended to do from my "utterance" (my
putting down the money), whereas in the first example this was not the case.
Nor is it the case with respect to Urmson’s case of the tutees attempt to bribe
Gardiner. So one might propose that the analysis of meaning be amended
accordingly. U means something by uttering x is true if: (i) U intends, by
uttering x, to induce a certain response in A (2) U intends A to recognize, at
least in part from the utterance of x, that U intends to produce that response
(3) U intends the fulfillment of the intention mentioned in (2) to be at least
in part As reason for fulfilling the intention mentioned in (i). While this
might cope with Urmsons counterexample to Grices proposal in the Oxford
Philosophical Society talk involving the tutee attempting to bribe Gardiner,
there is Strawsons rat-infested house for which it is
insufficient. An interesting fact, that confused a few, is that Hart
quotes from Grices Meaning in his critical review of Holloway for The
Philosophical Quarterly. Hart quotes Grice pre-dating the publication of
Meaning. Harts point is that Holloway should have gone to Oxford! In Meaning,
Grice may be seen as a practitioner of ordinary-language philosophy: witness
his explorations of the factivity (alla know, remember, or see) or lack thereof
of various uses of to mean. The second part of the essay, for which he became
philosophically especially popular, takes up an intention-based approach to
semantic notions. The only authority Grice cites, in typical Oxonian fashion,
is, via Ogden and Barnes, Stevenson, who, from The New World (and via Yale,
too!) defends an emotivist theory of ethics, and making a few remarks on how to
mean is used, with scare quotes, in something like a causal account (Smoke
means fire.). After its publication Grices account received almost as many
alleged counterexamples as rule-utilitarianism (B. J. Harrison), but mostly
outside Oxford, and in The New World. New-World philosophers seem to have seen
Grices attempt as reductionist and as oversimplifying. At Oxford, the sort of
counterexample Grice received, before Strawson, was of the Urmson-type:
refined, and subtle. I think your account leaves bribery behind. On the other
hand, in the New World ‒ in what Grice calls the Latter-Day School of
Nominalism, Quine is having troubles with empiricism. Meaning was reprinted in
various collections, notably in Strawsons Philosophical Logic (and it should be
remembered that it was Strawson who had the thing typed and submitted for publication!).
Why Meaning should be reprinted in a collection on Philosophical Logic only
Strawson knows! But Grice does say that his account may help clarify the
meaning of entails! It may be Strawsons implicature that Parkinson should have
reprinted (and not merely credited) Grices Meaning in his s. for Oxford on The
theory of meaning! The preferred quotation for Griceians is of course Grice
1948, seeing that Grice recalled the exact year when he gave the talk for the
Philosophical Society at Oxford! It is however, the publication in The
Philosophical Review, rather than the quieter evening at the Oxford
Philosophical Society, that occasioned a tirade of alleged counter-examples by
New-World philosophers. Granted, one or two Oxonians ‒ Urmson and Strawson ‒
fell in! Urmson criticises the sufficiency of Grices account, by introducing an
alleged counter-example involving bribery. Grice will consider a way out of
Urmsons alleged counter-example in his fifth Wiliam James Lecture, rightly
crediting and thanking Urmson for this! Strawsons alleged counter-example was
perhaps slightly more serious, if regressive. It also involves the sufficiency
of Grices analysis. Strawsons rat-infested house alleged counter-example
started a chain which required Grice to avoid, ultimately, any sneaky intention
by way of a recursive clause to the effect that, for utterer U to have meant
that p, all meaning-constitutive intentions should be above board. But why this
obsession by Grice with mean? He is being funny. Spots surely dont mean, only
mean.They dont have a mind. Yet Grice opens with a specific sample. Those spots
mean, to the doctor, that you, dear, have measles. Mean? Yes, dear, mean,
doctors orders. Those spots mean measles. But how does the doctor know? Cannot he
be in the wrong? Not really, mean is factive, dear! Or so Peirce thought. Grice
is amazed that Peirce thought that some meaning is factive. The hole in this
piece of cloth means that a bullet went through is is one of Peirce’s examples.
Surely, as Grice notes, this is an unhappy example. The hole in the cloth may
well have caused by something else, or fabricated. (Or the postmark means that
the letter went through the post.) Yet, Grice was having Oxonian tutees aware
that Peirce was krypto-technical. Grice chose for one of his pre-Meaning seminars
(i.e. 1947) on Peirce’s general theory of signs, with emphasis on general, and
Peirces correspondence with Welby. Peirce, rather than the Vienna circle,
becomes, in vein with Grices dissenting irreverent rationalism, important as a
source for Grices attempt to English Peirce. Grices implicature seems to be
that Peirce, rather than Ayer, cared for the subtleties of meaning and sign,
never mind a verificationist theory about them! Peirce ultra-Latinate-cum-Greek
taxonomies have Grice very nervous, though. He knew that his students were
proficient in the classics, but still! Grice thus proposes to reduce all of
Peirceian divisions and sub-divisions (one sub-division too many) to mean. In
the proceedings, he quotes from Ogden, Richards, and Ewing. In particular,
Grice was fascinated by Peirces correspondence with Lady Viola Welby, as
reprinted by Ogden/Richards in, well, their study on the meaning of meaning!
Grice thought the science of symbolism pretentious, but then he almost thought
Lady Viola Welby slightly pretentious, too, if youve seen her; beautiful lady!
It is via Peirce that Grice explores examples such as those spots meaning
measles. Peirce’s obsession is with weathercocks almost as Ockham was with
circles on wine-barrels. Old-World Grices use of New-World Peirce is
illustrative, thus, of the Oxonian linguistic turn focused on ordinary
language. While Peirce’s background was not philosophical, Grice thought it
comical enough. He would say that Peirce is an amateur, but then he said the
same thing about Mill, whom Grice had to study by heart to get his B. A. Lit.
Hum.! Plus, as Watson commented, Whats wrong with amateur? Give me an amateur
philosopher ANY day, if I have to choose from professional Hegel! In finding
Peirce krypo-technical, Grice is ensuing that his tutees, and indeed any
Oxonian philosophy student (he was university lecturer) be aware that to mean
should be more of a priority than this or that jargon by this or that (New
World?) philosopher!? Partly! Grice wanted his students to think on their own,
and draw their own conclusions! Grice cites Ewing, Ogden/Richards, and many
others. Ewing, while Oxford-educated, had ended up at Cambridge (Scruton almost
had him as his tutor) and written some points on Meaninglessness! Those spots
mean measles. Grice finds Peirce krypto-technical and proposes to English him
into an ordinary-language philosopher. Surely it is not important whether we
consider a measles spot a sign, a symbol, or an icon. One might just as well
find a doctor in London who thinks those spots symbolic. If Grice feels like
Englishing Peirce, he does not altogether fail! 1957. Meaning, reprints,
of Meaning and other essays, a collection of reprints and offprints of Grices
essays. Meaning becomes a central topic of at least two strands in
Retrospective epilogue. The first strand concerns the idea of the centrality of
the utterer. What Grice there calls meaning BY (versus meaning TO), i.e. as he
also puts it, active or agents meaning. Surely he is right in defending an
agent-based account to meaning. Peirce need not, but Grice must, because he is
working with an English root, mean, that is only figurative applicable to
non-agentive items (Smoke means rain). On top, Grice wants to conclude that
only a rational creature (a person) can meanNN properly. Non-human animals may
have a correlate. This is a truly important point for Grice since he surely is
seen as promoting a NON-convention-based approach to meaning, and also
defending from the charge of circularity in the non-semantic account of
propositional attitudes. His final picture is a rationalist one. Pirot1 G
wants to communicate about a danger to Pirot2. This presupposes
there IS a danger (item of reality). Then Pirot1 G believes
there is a danger, and communicates to Pirot2 G2 that there is
a danger. This simple view of conversation as rational co-operation underlies
Grices account of meaning too, now seen as an offshoot of philosophical
psychology, and indeed biology, as he puts it. Meaning as yet another survival
mechanism. While he would never use a cognate like significance in his Oxford
Philosophical Society talk, Grice eventually starts to use such Latinate
cognates at a later stage of his development. In Meaning, Grice does not
explain his goal. By sticking with a root that the Oxford curriculum did not
necessarily recognised as philosophical (amateur Peirce did!), Grice is
implicating that he is starting an ordinary-language botanising on his own
repertoire! Grice was amused by Ewings reliance on very Oxonian examples contra
Freddie Ayer: Surely Virtue aint a fire-shovel is perfectly meaningful, and if
fact true, if, Ill admit, somewhat misleading and practically purposeless at
Cambridge. Again, Grices dismissal of natural meaning is due to the fact that
natural meaning prohibits its use in the first person and followed by a that-clause.
I mean-N that p sounds absurd, no communication-function seems in the offing.
Grice found, with Suppes, all types of primacy (ontological, axiological,
psychological) in utterers meaning. In Retrospective epilogue, he goes back to
the topic, as he reminisces that it is his suggestion that there are two
allegedly distinguishable meaning concepts, even if one is meta-bolical, which
may be called natural meaning and non-natural meaning. There is this or that
test (notably factivity-entailment vs. cancelation, but also scare quotes)
which may be brought to bear to distinguish one concept from the other. We may,
for example, inquire whether a particular occurrence of the predicate mean is
factive or non-factive, i. e., whether for it to be true that [so and so] means
that p, it does or does not have to be the case that it is true that p. Again,
one may ask whether the use of quotation marks to enclose the specification of
what is meant would be inappropriate or appropriate. If factivity (as in know,
remember, and see) is present and quotation marks (oratio recta) are be
inappropriate, we have a case of natural meaning. Otherwise the meaning
involved is non-natural meaning. We may now ask whether there is a single
overarching idea which lies behind both members of this dichotomy of uses to which
the predicate meaning that seems to be Subjects. If there is such a central
idea it might help to indicate to us which of the two concepts is in greater
need of further analysis and elucidation and in what direction such elucidation
should proceed. Grice confesses that he has only fairly recently come to
believe that there is such an overarching idea and that it is indeed of some
service in the proposed inquiry. The idea behind both uses of mean is that of
consequence, or consequentia, as Hobbes has it. If [x] means that p, something
which includes p or the idea of p, is a consequence of [x]. In the metabolic
natural use of meaning that p, p, this or that consequence, is this or that
state of affairs. In the literal, non-metabolic, basic, non-natural use of
meaning that p, (as in Smith means that his neighbour’s three-year child is an
adult), p, this or that consequence is this or that conception or complexus
which involves some other conception. This perhaps suggests that of the two
concepts it is, as it should, non-natural meaning which is more in need of
further elucidation. It seems to be the more specialised of the pair, and it
also seems to be the less determinate. We may, e. g., ask how this or that
conception enters the picture. Or we may ask whether what enters the picture is
the conception itself or its justifiability. On these counts Grice should look
favorably on the idea that, if further analysis should be required for one of
the pair, the notion of non-natural meaning would be first in line. There are
factors which support the suitability of further analysis for the concept of
non-natural meaning. MeaningNN that p (non-natural meaning)
does not look as if it Namess an original feature of items in the world, for
two reasons which are possibly not mutually independent. One reason is that,
given suitable background conditions, meaning, can be changed by fiat. The
second reason is that the presence of meaningNN is dependent on
a framework provided by communication, if that is not too
circular. Communication is in the philosophical lexicon,
commūnĭcātĭo, from communicare, "(several times in Cicero, elsewhere rare),
and as they did with negatio and they will with significatio, Short and Lewis
render, unhelpfully, as a making common, imparting, communicating. largitio
et communicatio civitatis (Cic. Balb. 13, 31), quaedam societas et communicatio
utilitatum, id. Fin. 5, 23, 65: consilii communicatio, id. Fam. 5, 19, 2:
communicatio sermonis, id. Att. 1, 17, 6: criminis cum pluribus, Tiro ap. Gell.
7, 3, 14: communicatio nominum, i. e. the like appellation of several objects,
Plin. 24, 14, 80, § 129: juris, Dig. 23, 2, 1: damni, ib. 27, 3, 1, § 14. In
rhetorics, communicatio, trading on the communis, a figure, translating Grecian
ἀνακοίνωσις, in accordance with which the utterer turns to his addressee, and,
as it were, allows him to take part in the inquiry, Cic. de Or. 3, 53, 204;
Quint. 9, 1, 30; 9, 2, 20 and 23. It seems to Grice, then, at least
reasonable and possibly even emphatically mandatory, to treat the claim that a
communication vehicle, such as this and that expression means that p, in this
transferred, metaphoric, or meta-bolic use of means that as being reductively
analysable in terms of this or that feature of this or that utterer,
communicator, or user of this or that expression. The use of meaning
that as applied to this or that
expression is posterior to and explicable through the utterer-oriented, or
utterer-relativised use, i.e. involving a reference to this or that
communicator or user of this or that expression. More specifically, one should
license a metaphorical use of mean, where one allows the claim that this or
that expression means that p, provided that this or that utterer, in this or
that standard fashion, means that p, i.e. in terms of this or that souly
statee toward this or that propositional complexus this or that utterer ntends,
in a standardly fashion, to produce by his uttering this or that utterance.
That this or that expression means (in this metaphorical use) that p is
thus explicable either in terms of this or that souly state which is
standardly intended to produce in this or that addressee A by this or that
utterer of this or that expression, or in this or that souly staken up by this
or that utterer toward this or that activity or action of this or that utterer
of this or that expression. Meaning was in the air in Oxfords linguistic
turn. Everybody was talking meaning. Grice manages to quote from Hares early
“Mind” essay on the difference between imperatives and indicatives, also
Duncan-Jones on the fugitive proposition, and of course his beloved
Strawson. Grice was also concerned by the fact that in the typical
ordinary-language philosophers manoeuvre, there is a constant abuse of mean.
Surely Grice wants to stick with the utterers meaning as the primary use.
Expressions mean only derivatively. To do that, he chose Peirce to see if he
could clarify it with meaning that. Grice knew that the polemic was even
stronger in London, with Ogden and Lady Viola Welby. In the more academic
Oxford milieu, Grice knew that a proper examination of meaning, would lead him,
via Kneale and his researches on the history of semantics, to the topic of
signification that obsessed the modistae (and their modus significandi). For
what does L and S say about about this? There is indeed an entry for
signĭfĭcātĭo, f. significare. L and S render it, unhelpfully, as “a
pointing out, indicating, denoting, signifying; an
expression, indication, mark, sign, token, = indicium,
signum, ἐπισημασία, etc., freq. and class. As with Stevenson’s ‘communico,’
Grice goes sraight to ‘signĭfĭco,’ also dep. signĭfĭcor (Gell. 18,
12, 10, without an example), f. ‘significare,’ from signum-facere, to make
sign, signum-facio, I make sign, which L and S render as to signify, which is
perhaps not too helpful. Grice, if not the Grecians, knew that. Strictly, L and
S render significare as to show by signs; to show, point out, express, publish,
make known, indicate; to intimate, notify, signify, etc. Note that the cognate
signify almost comes last, but not least, if not first. Enough to want to coin
a word to do duty for them all. Which is what Grice (and the Grecians) can, but
the old Romans cannot, with mean. If that above were not enough, L and S go on,
also, to betoken, prognosticate, foreshow, portend, MEAN (syn. praedico), as in
to betoken a change of weather (post-Aug.): “ventus Africus tempestatem
significat, etc.,” Col. 11, 2, 4 sq.: cf. Grice on those dark clouds mean a
storm is coming. Short and Lewis go on, to say that significare may
be rendered as to call, name; to mean, import, signify. Hence, ‘signĭfĭcans,’
in rhet. lang., of speech, full of meaning, expressive, significant;
graphic, distinct, clear: Adv.: signĭfĭcanter , clearly, distinctly, expressly,
significantly, graphically: “breviter ac significanter ordinem rei protulisse,”
Quint. 11, 1, 53: “rem indicare (with proprie),” id. 12, 10, 52: “dicere (with
ornate),” id. 1, 7, 32. Comp.: “apertius, significantius dignitatem alicujus
defendere,” Cic. Fam. 3, 12, 3: “narrare,” Quint. 10, 1, 49: “disponere,” id.
3, 6, 65: “appellare aliquid (with consignatius),” Gell. 1, 25, 8: “dicere
(with probabilius),” id. 17, 2, 11. Sup., Pseudo Quint. Decl. 247. If
perhaps Grice was unhappy about the artificial flavour to saying that a word is
a sign, Grice surely should have checked with all the Grecian-Roman cognates of
mean, as in his favourite memorative-memorable distinction, and the many
Grecian realisations, or with Old Roman mentire and mentare.
mentĭor, f. mentire, L and S note, is prob. from root men-, whence mens and
memini, q. v. The original meaning, they say, is to invent, hence, but
alla Umberto Eco with sign, mentire comes to mean in later use what Grice (if
not the Grecians) holds is the opposite of mean. Short and Lewis render mentire
as to lie, cheat, deceive, etc., to pretend, to declare falsely: mentior nisi
or si mentior, a form of asseveration, I am a liar, if, etc.: But also,
animistically (modest mentalism?) of things, as endowed with a mind. L and S go
on: to deceive, impose upon, to deceive ones self, mistake, to lie or speak
falsely about, to assert falsely, make a false promise about; to feign,
counterfeit, imitate a shape, nature, etc.: to devise a falsehood, to
assume falsely, to promise falsely, to invent, feign, of a poetical
fiction: “ita mentitur (sc. Homerus), Trop., of inanim. grammatical Subjects,
as in Semel fac illud, mentitur tua quod subinde tussis, Do what your cough
keeps falsely promising, i. e. die, Mart. 5, 39, 6. Do what your cough means!
=imp. die!; hence, mentĭens, a fallacy, sophism: quomodo mentientem, quem
ψευδόμενον vocant, dissolvas, Cic. Div. 2, 4, 11, mentītus, imitated,
counterfeit, feigned (poet.): “mentita tela,” Verg. A. 2, 422. For
“mentior,” indeed, there is a Griceian implicatum involving rational control.
The rendition of mentire as to lie stems from a figurative shift from to
be mindful, or inventive, to have second thoughts" to "to lie,
conjure up". But Grice would also have a look at cognate “memini,” since
this is also cognate with “mind,” “mens,” and covers subtler instances of mean,
as in Latinate, “mention,” as in Grices “use-mention” distinction. mĕmĭni,
cognate with "mean" and German "meinen," to think = Grecian
ὑπομένειν, await (cf. Schiffer, "remnants of meaning," if I think, I
hesitate, and therefore re-MAIN. Cf. Gr. μεν- in μένω, Μέντωρ; μαν- in
μαίνομαι, μάντις; μνᾶ- in μιμνήσκω, etc.; cf.: maneo, or manere, as in
remain. The idea, as Schiffer well knows or means, being that if you
think, you hesitate, and therefore, wait and remain], moneo, reminiscor [cf.
reminiscence], mens, Minerva, etc. which L and S render as “to remember,
recollect, to think of, be mindful of a thing; not to have forgotten a
person or thing, to bear in mind (syn.: reminiscor, recordor).”
Surely with a relative clause, and to make mention of, to mention a
thing, either in speaking or writing (rare but class.). Hence. mĕmĭnens,
mindful And then Grice would have a look at moneo, as in adMONish, also
cognate. mŏnĕo, monere, causative from the root "men;" whence memini,
q. v., mens (mind), mentio (mention); lit. to cause to think, to re-mind, put
in mind of, bring to ones recollection; to admonish, advise, warn, instruct,
teach (syn.: hortor, suadeo, doceo). L and S are Griceian if not Grecian
when they note that monere can be used "without the accessory notion
[implicatum or entanglement, that is] of reminding or admonishing, in
gen., to teach, instruct, tell, inform, point out; also, to
announce, predict, foretell, even if also to punish, chastise (only
in Tacitus): “puerili verbere moneri,” Tac. A. 5, 9. And surely, since he
loved to re-minisced, Grice would have allowed to just earlier on just
minisced. Short and Lewis indeed have rĕmĭniscor, which, as they point out,
features the root men; whence mens, memini; and which they compare to
comminiscere, v. comminiscor, to recall to mind, recollect, remember (syn.
recordor), often used by the Old Romans with with Grices beloved that-clause,
for sure. For what is the good of reminiscing or comminiscing, if you
cannot reminisce that Austin always reminded Grice that skipping the dictionary
was his big mistake! If Grice uses mention, cognate with mean, he loved
commenting Aristotle. And commentare is, again, cognate with mean. As opposed
to the development of the root in Grecian, or English, in Roman the root for
mens is quite represented in many Latinate cognates. But a Roman, if not a
Grecian, would perhaps be puzzled by a Grice claiming, by intuition, to
retrieve the necessary and sufficient conditions for the use of this or that
expression. When the Roman is told that the Griceian did it for fun, he
understands, and joins in the fun! Indeed, hardly a natural kind in the
architecture of the world, but one that fascinated Grice and the Grecian
philosophers before him!
DISPOSITION: Grice is a philosophical psychologist. Does that make
sense? So are Austin (Other Minds), Hampshire (Dispositions), Pears (Problems
in philosophical psychology) and Urmson (Parentheticals). They are ALL against
Ryle’s silly analysis in terms of single-track disposition" vs.
"many-track disposition," and "semi-disposition." If I hum
and walk, I can either hum or walk. But if I heed mindfully, while an IN-direct
sensing may guide me to YOUR soul, a DIRECT sensing guides me to MY soul. When
Ogden consider attacks to meaning, theres what he calls the psychological,
which he ascribes to Locke Grices attitude towards Ryle is difficult to assess.
His most favourable assessment comes from Retrospective epilogue, but then he
is referring to Ryle’s fairy godmother. Initially, he mentions Ryle as a
philosopher engaged in, and possibly dedicated to the practice of the
prevailing Oxonian methodology, i.e. ordinary-language
philosophy. Initially, then, Grice enlists Ryle in the regiment of
ordinary-language philosophers. After introducing Athenian dialectic and
Oxonian dialectic, Grice traces some parallelisms, which should not surprise.
It is tempting to suppose that Oxonian dialectic reproduces some ideas of
Athenian dialectic. It would actually be surprising if there were no
parallels. Ryle was, after all, a skilled and enthusiastic student of Grecian
philosophy. Interestingly, Grice then has Ryles fairy godmother as
proposing the idea that, far from being a basis for rejecting the
analytic-synthetic distinction, opposition that there are initially two
distinct bundles of statements, bearing the labels analytic and synthetic,
lying around in the world of thought waiting to be noticed, provides us with
the key to making the analytic-synthetic distinction acceptable. The
essay has a verificationist ring to it. Recall Ayer and the
verificationists trying to hold water with concepts like fragile and the
problem of counterfactual conditionals vis-a-vis observational and
theoretical concepts. Grices essay has two parts: one on disposition as
such, and the second, the application to a type of psychological
disposition, which would be phenomenalist in a way, or verificationist, in
that it derives from introspection of, shall we say, empirical phenomena. Grice
is going to analyse, I want a sandwich. One person wrote in his
manuscript, there is something with the way Grice goes to work.
Still. Grice says that I want a sandwich (or I will that I eat a sandwich)
is problematic, for analysis, in that it seems to refer to experience that is
essentially private and unverifiable. An analysis of intending that p in terms
of being disposed that p is satisfied solves this. Smith wants a sandwich, or
he wills that he eats a sandwich, much as Toby needs nuts, if Smith opens the
fridge and gets one. Smith is disposed to act such that p is satisfied.
This Grice opposes to the ‘special-episode’ analysis of intending that p. An
utterance like I want a sandwich iff by uttering the utterance, the utterer is
describing this or that private experience, this or that private
sensation. This or that sensation may take the form of a highly specific
souly sate, like what Grice calls a sandwich-wanting-feeling. But then, if
he is not happy with the privacy special-episode analysis, Grice is also
dismissive of Ryles behaviourism in The concept of mind, fresh from
the press in 1949, which would describe the utterance in terms purely of this
or that observable response, or behavioural output, provided this or that
sensory input. Grice became friendlier with functionalism after Lewis taught
him how. The problem or crunch is with the first person. Surely, Grice
claims, one does not need to wait to observe oneself heading for the fridge
before one is in a position to know that he is hungry. Grice poses a
problem for the protocol-reporter. You see or observe someone else, Smith, that
Smith wants a sandwich, or wills that he eats a sandwich. You ask for evidence.
But when it is the agent himself who wants the sandwich, or wills that he eats
a sandwich, Grice melodramatically puts it, I am not in the
audience, not even in the front row of the stalls; I am on the
stage. Genial, as you will agree. Grice then goes on to offer an
analysis of intend, his basic and target attitude, which he has just used to
analyse and rephrase Peirces mean and which does relies on this or that piece
of dispositional evidence, without divorcing itself completely from the
privileged status or access of first-person introspective knowledge. In
Intention and uncertainty, Grice weakens his reductive analysis of intending
that, from neo-Stoutian, based on certainty, or assurance, to neo-Prichardian,
based on predicting. All very Oxonian: Stout was the sometime Wilde reader in
mental philosophy (a post usually held by a psychologist, rather than a
philosopher ‒ Stouts favourite philosopher is psychologist James! ‒ and
Prichard was Cliftonian and the proper White chair of moral philosophy. And
while in Intention and uncertainty, he allows that willing that may receive a
physicalist treatment, qua state, hell later turn a functionalist in
his Method in philosophical psychology (from the banal to the bizarre).
Grice can easily relate to Hamsphires "Thought and Action," a most
influential essay in the Oxonian scene. Rather than Ryle! And Grice actually
addresses further topics on intention drawing on Hampshire, Hart, and his joint
collaboration with Pears.
SEMIOTICS: 1951 was a vintage year at Oxford. Holloway published
his “Language and Intelligence”! It is best to see this as Grices psychologism.
Grice would rarely use ‘intelligent,’ less so the more pretentious,
‘intelligence,’ as a keyword. If he is doing it, it is because what he saw as
the misuse of it by Ryle and Holloway. Holloway, a PPE, is a tutorial fellow in
philosophy at All Souls. He acknowledges Ryle as his mentor. (Holloway also
quotes from Austin). Grice was amused that J. N. Findlay, in his review of
Holloway’s essay in “Mind,” compares Holloway to C. W. Morris, and cares to
cite the two relevant essay by Morris: The Foundation in the theory of signs,
and Signs, Language, and Behaviour. Enough for Grice to feel warmly justified
in having chosen another New-World author, Peirce, for his earlier Oxford
seminar. Morris studied under G. H. Mead. But is ‘intelligence’ part of The
Griceian Lexicon?Well, Lewis and Short have ‘interlegere,’ to chose between.
The entry is ‘interlĕgo , lēgi, lectum, 3, v. a., I’. Lewis and Short render it
as “to cull or pluck off here and there (poet. and postclass.).in tmesi) uncis
Carpendae manibus frondes, interque legendae, Verg. G. 2, 366: “poma,” Pall.
Febr. 25, 16; id. Jun. 5, 1.intellĕgo (less correctly intellĭgo), exi, ectum
(intellexti for intellexisti, Ter. Eun. 4, 6, 30; Cic. Att. 13, 32, 3:
I.“intellexes for intellexisses,” Plaut. Cist. 2, 3, 81; subj. perf.:
“intellegerint,” Sall. H. Fragm. 1, 41, 23 Dietsch), 3, v. a. inter-lego, to
see into, perceive, understand. I. Lit. A. Lewis and Short render as “to perceive,
understand, comprehend.”Cf. Grice on his handwriting being legible to few. And
The child is an adult as being UNintelligible until the creature is produced.
In Aspects of reason, he mentions flat rationality, and certain other talents
that are more difficult for the philosopher to conceptualise, such as nose
(i.e. intuitiveness), acumen, tenacity, and such. Grices approach is
pirotological. If Locke had used intelligent to refer to Prince Maurices parrot,
Grice wants to find criteria for intelligent as applied to his favourite type
of pirot, rather (intelligent, indeed rational.)
PINT: Figurative. This is Harvardite Gordon’s attempt to formulate
a philosophy of the minimum fundamental ideas that all people on the earth
should come to know. Reviewed by A. M. Honoré: Short measure. Gordon, a Stanley
Plummer scholar, e: Bowdoin and Harvard (The Eastern Gazette). Grice would
exclaim: I always loved Alfred Brooks Gordon! Grice was slightly disapppointed
that Gordon had not included the fundamental idea of implicature in his pint.
Short measure, indeed!
ESCHATOLOGY: Being and good, for Aristotle and Grice cover all.
Good was a favourite of Moore and Hare, as Barnes was well aware! Like Barnes,
Grice dislikes Prichards analysis of good. He leaned towards the emotion-based
approach by Ogden. If Grice, like Humpty
Dumpty, opposes the Establishment with his meaning liberalism (what a word
means is what I mean by uttering it), he certainly should be concerned with
category shifts. Plus, Grice was a closet Platonist. As Plato once remarked,
having the ability to see horses but not horsehood is a mark of stupidity.
Grice would endure the flinty experience of giving joint seminars at Oxford
with Austin on the first two books of Aristotles Organon, Categoriae, and De
Int. . Grice finds Aristotles use of a category, κατηγορία, a bit of a
geniality. Aristotle is using legalese, from kata, against, on, and
agoreuô [ἀγορεύω], speak in public), and uses it to designate both the
prosecution in a trial and the attribution in a logical proposition, i.
e., the questions that must be asked with regard to a Subjects, and the answers
that can be given. As a representative of the linguistic turn in
philosophy, Grice is attracted to the idea that a category can thus be
understood variously, as applying to the realm of reality (ontology), but also
to the philosophy of language (category of expression) and to philosophical
psychology (category of representation). Grice kept his explorations on
categories under two very separate, shall we say, categories: his explorations
with Austin (very serious), and those with Strawson (more congenial). Where is
Smiths altruism? Nowhere to be seen. Should we say it is idle (otiose) to speak
of altruism? No, it is just an attribute, which, via category shift, can be
made the Subjects of your sentence, Strawson. Its not spatio-temporal, though,
right? Not really. ‒ I dont particularly like your trouser words.
The essay is easy to date since Grice notes that Strawson reproduced some of
the details in his Individuals, dated 1959. Grice thought Aristotle was the
best! Or at any rate almost as good as Kantotle! Aristotle saw Categoriæ, along
with De Int. as part of his
Organon. However, philosophers of language tend to explore these topics without
a consideration of the later parts of the Organon dealing with the syllogism,
the tropes, and the topics ‒ the boring bits! The reason Grice is attracted to
the Aristotelian category (as Austin and Strawson equally were) is that
category allows for a linguistic-turn reading. Plus, its a nice, pretentious
(in the Oxonian way) piece of philosophical jargon! Aristotle couldnt find
category in the koine, so he had to coin it. While meant by Aristotle in a
primarily ontological way, Oxonian philosophers hasten to add that a category
of expression, as Grice puts it, is just as valid a topic for philosophical
exploration. His tutee Strawson will actually publish a book on Subjects and
predicate in grammar! (Trivial, Strawson!). Grice will later add an
intermediary category, which is the Subjects of his philosophical psychology.
As such, a category can be construed ontologically, or representationally: the
latter involving philosophical psychological concepts, and expressions
themselves. For Aristotle, as Grice and Austin, and Grice and Strawson, were
well aware as they educated some of the poor at Oxford (Only the poor learn at
Oxford ‒ Arnold), there are (at least ‒ at most?) ten categories.
Grice doesnt (really) care about the number. But the first are important. Actually
the very first: theres substantia prima, such as Grice. And then theres
substantia secunda, such as Grices rationality. The essentia. Then there are
various types of attributes. But, as Grice sharply notes, even substantia
secunda may be regarded as an attribute. Grices favourite game with Strawson
was indeed Category Shift, or Subjects-ification, as Strawson preferred.
Essence may be introduced as a sub-type of an attribute. We would have
substantia prima AND attribute, which in turn gets divided into essential, the
izzing, and non-essential, the hazzing. While Austin is not so fun to play
with, Strawson is. Smith is a very altruist person. Where is his altruism?
Nowhere to be seen, really. Yet we may sensically speak of Smiths altruism. Its
just a matter of a category shift. Grice scores. Grice is slightly
disappointed, but he perfectly understands, that Strawson, who footnotes
Grice as the tutor from whom I never ceased to learn about logic in
Introduction to logical lheory, fails to acknowledge that most of the research
in Strawsons Individuals: an essay in descriptive (not revisionary) metaphysics
derives from the conclusions reached at his joint philosophical investigations
at joint seminars with Grice. Grice later elaborates on this with Code, who is
keen on Grices other game, The hazz and the hazz not, the izz. But then tutor
from whom I never ceased to learn about metaphysics sounds slightlier clumsier,
as far as the implicature goes. Categories, 1973, 1974, 1977, 1980, the
Grice-Myro theory of identity, Relative identity, Grice on =, identity, notes,
with Myro, metaphysics, philosophy, with Code, Grice izz Grice – or izz he? The
idea that = is unqualified requires qualification. Whitehead and Russell
ignored this. Grice and Myro didnt. Grice wants to allow for It is the case
that a = b /t1 and It is not the case
that a = b /t2. The idea is intuitive, but philosophers of a Leibnizian bent
are too accustomed to deal with = as an absolute. Grice applies this to human vs.
person. A human may be identical to a person, but cease to be so. Indeed,
Grices earlier attempt to produce a reductive analsysis of I may be seen as
remedying a circularity he detected in Locke about same. Cf. Wiggins, Sameness
and substance. Grice makes Peano feel deeply Griceian, as Grice lists his =
postulates, here for consideration. And if you wondered why Grice prefers
Latinate individuum to the Grecian, heres the Grecian, ἄτομον, in
logic, rendered by L and S as individual, of terms, Pl. Sph. 229d; of the εἶδος
or forma, Arist. Metaph.1034a8, de An. 414b27.2. individual, Id. APo. 96b11,
al.: as a subst., τό ἄτομον, Id. Cat. 1b6, 3a38, Metaph.1058a18 (pl.),
Plot. 6.2.2, al. subst.; latinised from Grecian as indīvĭdŭum, an atom,
indivisible particle: ex illis individuis, unde omnia Democritus gigni
affirmat, Cic. Ac. 2, 17 fin.: ne individuum quidem, nec quod dirimi distrahive
non possit, id. N. D. 3, 12, 29. Note the use of individuum in alethic
modalities for necessity and possibility, starting with (11). 1. ⊢ (α izzes α). This would be the principle
of non-contradiction or identity. Grice applies it to war: War is war, as
yielding a most peculiar implicature. 2. ⊢ (α izzes β ∧ β izzes γ) ⊃ α izzes γ. This above is transitivity,
which is crucial for Grices tackling of Reids counterexample to Locke (and
which according to Flew in Locke on personal identity was predated by Berkeley.
3. ⊢ α hazzes β ⊃ ~(α izzes β). Or, what is accidental is
not essential. Grice allows that what is essential is accidental is, while
misleading, true. 4. ⊢ α hazzes β ⊃⊂ (∃x)(α hazzes x ∧ x izzes β) 5. ⊢ (∀β)(β izzes a universalium ⊃ β izzes a forma). This above defines a
universalium as a forma, or eidos. 6. ⊢ (α hazzes β ∧ α izzes a particular) ⊃ (∃γ).(γ≠α ∧ α izzes β) 7. ⊢ α izzes predicable of β ⊃⊂ ((β izzes α) ∨ (∃x)(β hazzes x ∧ x izzes α) 8. ⊢ α izzes essentially predicable of β ⊃⊂ β izzes α 9. ⊢ α izzes non-essentially/accidentally
predicable of β ⊃⊂ (∃x)(β hazzes x ∧ x izzes α) 10. ⊢ α = β ⊃⊂ α izzes β ∧ β izzes α 11. ⊢ α izzes an individuum ⊃⊂ □(∀β)(β izzes α ⊃ α izzes β) 12. ⊢ α izzes a particular ⊃⊂ □(∀β)(α izzes predicable of β ⊃ (α izzes β ∧ β izzes α)) 13. ⊢ α izzes a universalium ⊃⊂ ◊(∃β)(α izzes predicable of α ∧ ~(α izzes β ∧ β izzes α) 14. ⊢ α izzes some-thing ⊃ α izzes an individuum. 15. ⊢ α izzes a forma ⊃ (α izzes some-thing ∧ α izzes a universalium) 16. ⊢ α izzes predicable of β ⊃⊂ (β izzes α) ∨ (∃x)(β hazzes x ∧ x izzes α) 17. ⊢ α izzes essentially predicable of α
18. ⊢ α izzes
accidentally predicable of β ⊃ α ≠ β 19. ⊢ ~(α izzes accidentally predicable of
β) ⊃ α ≠ β 20. ⊢ α izzes a particular ⊃ α izzes an individuum 21. ⊢ α izzes a particular ⊃ ~(∃x)(x ≠ α ∧ x izzes α) 22. ⊢~ (∃x).(x izzes a particular ∧ x izzes a forma) 23. ⊢ α izzes a forma ⊃ ~(∃x)(x ≠ α ∧ x izzes α) 24. ⊢ x izzes a particular ⊃ ~(∃β)(α izz β) 25. ⊢ α izzes a forma ⊃ ((α izzes predicable of β ∧ α ≠ β) ⊃ β hazz α) 26. ⊢ α izzes a forma ∧ β izzes a particular ⊃ (α izzes predicable of β ⊃⊂ β hazz A) 27. ⊢ (α izzes a particular ∧ β izzes a universalium ∧ β izzes predicable of α) ⊃ (∃γ)(α ≠ γ ∧ γ izzes essentially predicable of α)
28. ⊢ (∃x) (∃y)(x izzes a particular ∧ y izzes a universalium ∧ y izzes predicable of x ⊃ ~(∀x)(x izzes a universalium ∧ x izzes some-thing) 29. ⊢ (∀β)(β izzes a universalium ⊃ β izzes some-thing) 30. ⊢ α izzes a particular) ⊃ ~∃β.(α ≠ β ∧ β izzes essentially predicable of α)
31. ⊢ (α izzes
predicable of β ∧ α ≠ β)⊃ α izzes non-essentially or accidentally
predicable of β. The use of this or that doxastic modality, necessity and
possibility, starting with (11) above, make this a good place to consider one
philosophical mistake Grice mentions in Causal theory: What is actual is not
also possible. Cf. What is essential is also accidental. He is criticising a
contemporary, if possible considered dated in the New World, form of
ordinary-language philosophy, where the philosopher detects a nuance, and
embarks risking colliding with the facts, rushing ahead to exploit it before he
can clarify it! Grice liked to see his explorations on = as belonging to
metaphysics, as the s. on his Doctrines
at the Grice Collection testifies. While Grice presupposes the use of = in his
treatment of the king of France, he also explores a relativisation of =. His
motivation was an essay by Wiggins, almost Aristotelian in spirit, against
Strawsons criterion of space-time continuancy for the identification of the
substantia prima. Grice wants to apply = to cases were the time continuancy is
made explicit. This yields that a=b in scenario S, but that it may not be the
case that a = b in a second scenario S. Myro had an occasion to expand on
Grices views in his contribution on the topic for PGRICE, or P. G. R. I. C. E.
for short. Myro mentions his System Ghp, a highly powerful/hopefully plausible
version of Grices System Q, in gratitude to to Grice. Grice explored also the
logic of izzing and hazzing with Code. Grice and Myro developed a Geach-type of
qualified identity. The formal aspects were developed by Myro, and also by
Code. Grice discussed Wigginss Sameness and substance, rather than Geach. Cf.
Wiggins and Strawson on Grice for the British Academy. At Oxford, Grice was
more or less given free rein to teach what he wanted. He found the New World
slightly disconcerting at first. At Oxford, he expected his tutees to be
willing to read the classics in the vernacular Greek. His approach to teaching
was diagogic, as Socratess! Even in his details of izzing and hazzing. Greek
enough to me!, as a student recalled! 1980, correspondence with Code, Grice
sees in Code an excellent Aristotelian. They collaborated on an exploration of
Aristotles underlying logic of essential and non-essential predication, for
which they would freely use such verbal forms as izzing and hazzing. 1980,
izzing and hazzing, Code on the significance of the middle book in Aristotles Met.
, Aristotle, metaphysics, the middle book. Very middle. Grice never knew
what was middle for Aristotle, but admired Code too much to air this! The
organisation of Aristotles metaphysics was a topic of much concern for
Grice. With Code, Grice coined izzing and hazzing to refer to essential
and non-essential attribution. Izzing and hazzing, Aristotle on the
multiplicity of being, Aristotle on multiplicity, The Pacific
Philosophical Quarterly, 1988, posthumously ed. by Loar, Aristotle, multiplicity,
izzing, hazzing, being, good, Code. Grice offers a thorough discussion of Owens
treatment of Aristotle as leading us to the snares of ontology. Grice
distinguishes between izzing and hazzing, which he thinks help in clarifying,
more axiomatico, what Aristotle is getting at with his remarks on essential
versus non-essential predication. Surely, for Grice, being, nor indeed good,
should not be multiplied beyond necessity, but izzing and hazzing are
already multiplied. The Grice Papers contains drafts of the essay
eventually submitted for publication by Loar in memoriam Grice. Note that the
Grice Papers contains a typically Griceian un-publication, entitled Aristotle
and multiplicity simpliciter. Rather than Aristotle on, as the title for
The Pacific Philosophical Quarterly piece goes. Note also that, since its
multiplicity simpliciter, it refers to Aristotle on two key ideas: being and
the good. As Code notes in his contribution to PGRICE, Grice first
presents his thoughts on izzing and hazzing publicly at Vancouver. R. B.
Jones has developed the axiomatic treatment favoured by Grice. For Grice
there is multiplicity in both being and good (ton agathon), both accountable in
terms of conversational implicata, of course. If in Prolegomena, Grice was
interested in criticising himself, in essays of historical nature like these,
Grice is seeing Aristotles Athenian dialectic as a foreshadow of the Oxonian
dialectic, and treating him as an equal. Grice is yielding his razor: senses
are not to be multiplied beyond necessity. But then Aristotle is
talking about the multiplicity of
is and is good. Surely, there are ways to turn
Aristotle into the monoguist he has to be! There is a further item in
the Grice collection that combines Aristotle on being with Aristotle on good,
which is relevant in connection with this. Aristotle on being and good
(ἀγαθόν). Aristotle, being, good (agathon), ἀγαθός. As from this f.,
the essays are ordered alphabetically, starting with Aristotle, Grice will
explore Aristotle on being or is and good (ἀγαθός) in explorations with Code.
Grice comes up with izzing and hazzing as the two counterparts to Aristotles
views on, respectively, essential and non-essential predication. Grices views
on Aristotle on the good (strictly, there is no need to restrict Arisstotles
use to the neuter form, since he employs ἀγαθός) connect with Grices
Aristotelian idea of eudaemonia, that he explores elsewhere. Strictly:
Aristotle on being and the good. If that had been Grices case, he would have
used the definite article. Otherwise, good may well translate as masculine,
ἀγαθός ‒the agathetic implicatum. He plays with Dodgson, cabbages and
kings. For what is a good cabbage as opposed to a cabbage? It does not
require very sharp eyes, but only our willingness to use the eyes one has, to
see that speech is permeated with the notion of purpose. To say what a
certain kind of thing is is only too frequently partly to say that it is
for. This feature applies to talk of, e. g., ships, shoes, sailing wax,
and kings; and, possibly and perhaps most excitingly, it extends even to
cabbages! Although Grice suspects Urmson might disagree. v. Grice on
Urmsons apples. Grice at his jocular best. If he is going to be a Kantian,
he will. He uses Kantian jargon to present his theory of conversation. This he
does only at Harvard. The implicature being that talking of vaguer assumptions
of helpfulness would not sound too convincing. So he has the maxim, the
super-maxim, and the sub-maxim. A principle and a maxim is Kantian enough. But
when he actually echoes Kant, is when he introduces what he later calls the
conversational categories – the keyword here is conversational category, as
categoria is used by Aristotle and Kant ‒ or Kantotle. Grice surely
knew that, say, his Category of Conversational Modality had nothing to do with
the Kantian Category of Modality. Still, he stuck with the idea of four
categories (versus Aristotles ten, eight or seven, as the text you consult may
tell you): category of conversational quantity (which at Oxford he had
formulated in much vaguer terms like strength and informativeness and
entailment), the category of conversational quality (keyword: principle of
conversational trust), and the category of conversational relation, where again
Kants relation has nothing to do with the maxim Grice associates with this
category. In any case, his Kantian joke may be helpful when considering the
centrality of the concept category simpliciter that Grice had to fight with
with his pupils at Oxford – he was lucky to have Austin and Strawson as
co-lecturers! Grice was irritated by L and S defining kategoria as category. I
guess I knew that. He agreed with their second shot, predicable. Ultimately,
Grices concern with category is his concern with person, or prote ousia, as
used by Aristotle, and as giving a rationale to Grices agency-based approach to
the philosophical enterprise. Aristotle used kategorein in the sense
of to predicate, assert something of something, and kategoria. The prote
ousia is exemplified by o tis anthropos. It is obvious that Grice wants to
approach Aristotles semantics and Aristotles metaphysics at one fell swoop.
Grice reads Aristotles Met. , and finds it understandable. Consider the
adjective French (which Aristotle does NOT consider) ‒ as it occurs in phrases
such as Michel Foucault is a French citizen. Grice is not a French
citizen. Michel Foucault once wrote a nice French poem. Urmson once wrote
a nice French essay on pragmatics. Michel Foucault was a French
professor. Michel Foucault is a French professor. Michel Foucault
is a French professor of philosophy. The following features are perhaps
significant. The appearance of the adjective French, or Byzantine, as the
case might be ‒ cf. Im feeling French tonight) in these phrases is
what Grice has as adjunctive rather than conjunctive, or attributive. A French
poem is not necessarily something which combines the separate features of being
a poem and being French, as a tall philosopher would simply combine the
features of being tall and of being a philosopher. French in French poem,
occurs adverbially. French citizen standardly means citizen of
France. French poem standardly means poem in French. But it is a mistake to
suppose that this fact implies that there is this or that meaning, or, worse,
this or that Fregeian sense, of the expression French. In any case, only
metaphorically or metabolically can we say that French means this or that or
has sense. An utterer means. An utterer makes sense. Cf. R. Pauls doubts about
capitalizing major. French means, and figuratively at that, only one thing,
viz. of or pertaining to France. And English only means of or
pertaining to England. French may be what Grice (unfollowing his remarks
on The general theory of context) call context-sensitive. One might indeed
say, if you like, that while French means ‒ or means only this or that, or that
its only sense is this or that, French still means, again figuratively, a
variety of things. French means-in-context of or pertaining to
France. Symbolise that as expression E means-in-context that p. Expression
E means-in-context C2 that p2. Relative to Context C1 French
means of France; as in the phrase French citizen. Relative to context C2,
French means in the French language, as
in the phrase, French poem ‒ whereas history does not behave, like this. Whether
the focal item is a universal or a particular is, contra Aristotle, quite
irrelevant to the question of what this or that related adjective means, or
what its sense is. The medical art is no more what an utterer means when he
utters the adjective medical, as is France what an utterer means by the
adjective French. While the attachment of this or that context may suggest an
interpretation in context of this or that expression as uttered by the utterer
U, it need not be the case that such a suggestion is indefeasible. It
might be e.g. that French poem would have to mean, poem composed in French,
unless there were counter indications, that brings the utterer and the
addressee to a different context C3. In which case, perhaps
what the utterer means by French poem is poem composed by a French competitor
in this or that competition. For French professor there would be two
obvious things an utterer might mean. Disambiguation will depend on the
wider expression-context or in the situational context attaching to
the this or that circumstance of utterance.
HEDONISM: Grice well knows that for Aristotle pleasure is just one
out of the three sources for phulia," -- the others being profit, and
virtue. Griceian pleasures. Democritus seems to be the earliest
philosopher on record to have categorically embraced a hedonistic philosophy.
He calls the supreme goal of life "contentment" or
"cheerfulness", claiming that "joy and sorrow are the
distinguishing mark of things beneficial and harmful" (DK 68 B 188). The
Cyrenaics were an ultra-hedonist Greek school of philosophy founded in the 4th
century BC, supposedly by Aristippus of Cyrene, although many of the principles
of the school are believed to have been formalized by his grandson of the same Names,
Aristippus the Younger. The school was so called after Cyrene, the birthplace
of Aristippus. It was one of the earliest Socratic schools. The Cyrenaics
taught that the only intrinsic good (agathon) is pleasure (hedone), which meant
not just the absence of pain, but positively enjoyable momentary sensations. Of
these, physical ones are stronger than those of anticipation or memory. They
do, however, recognize the value of social obligation, and that pleasure could
be gained from altruism. Theodorus the Atheist is a latter exponent of hedonism
who was a disciple of younger Aristippus, while becoming well known for
expounding atheism. The school dies out within a century, and is replaced by
Epicureanism. The Cyrenaics are known for their skeptical theory of
knowledge. They reduce logic to a basic doctrine concerning the criterion of
truth. They think that we can know with certainty our immediate
sense-experiences (e. g., that one is having a sweet sensation) but can know
nothing about the nature of the objects that cause these sensations (e.g., that
the honey is sweet). They also deny that we can have knowledge of what the
experiences of other people are like. All knowledge is immediate sensation.
These sensations are motions which are purely Subjectsive, and are painful,
indifferent or pleasant, according as they are violent, tranquil or gentle.
Further, they are entirely individual and can in no way be described as
constituting absolute objective knowledge. Feeling, therefore, is the only
possible criterion of knowledge and of conduct. Our ways of being affected are
alone knowable. Thus the sole aim for everyone should be pleasure.
Cyrenaicism deduces a single, universal aim for all people which is pleasure.
Furthermore, all feeling is momentary and homogeneous. It follows that past and
future pleasure have no real existence for us, and that among present pleasures
there is no distinction of kind. Socrates had spoken of the higher pleasures of
the intellect; the Cyrenaics denied the validity of this distinction and said
that bodily pleasures, being more simple and more intense, were preferable.
Momentary pleasure, preferably of a physical kind, is the only good for humans.
However some actions which give immediate pleasure can create more than their
equivalent of pain. The wise person should be in control of pleasures rather
than be enslaved to them, otherwise pain will result, and this requires
judgement to evaluate the different pleasures of life. Regard should be paid to
law and custom, because even though these things have no intrinsic value on
their own, violating them will lead to unpleasant penalties being imposed by
others. Likewise, friendship and justice are useful because of the pleasure
they provide. Thus the Cyrenaics believed in the hedonistic value of social
obligation and altruistic behaviour. Epicureanism is a system of
philosophy based upon the teachings of Epicurus, an atomic materialist,
following in the steps of Democritus and Leucippus. His materialism leads him
to a general stance against superstition or the idea of divine intervention.
Following Aristippus —about whom very little is known — Epicurus believes that
the greatest good is to seek modest, sustainable "pleasure" in the
form of a state of tranquility and freedom from fear (ataraxia) and absence of
bodily pain (aponia) through knowledge of the workings of the world and the
limits of our desires. The combination of these two states is supposed to
constitute happiness in its highest form. Although Epicureanism is a form of
hedonism, insofar as it declares pleasure as the sole intrinsic good, its
conception of absence of pain as the greatest pleasure and its advocacy of a
simple life make it different from "hedonism" as it is commonly
understood. In the Epicurean view, the highest pleasure (tranquility and
freedom from fear) was obtained by knowledge, friendship and living a virtuous
and temperate life. Epicurus lauds the enjoyment of simple pleasures, by which
he meant abstaining from bodily desires, such as sex and appetites, verging on
asceticism. Epicurus argues that when eating, one should not eat too richly,
for it could lead to dissatisfaction later, such as the grim realization that
one could not afford such delicacies in the future. Likewise, sex could lead to
increased lust and dissatisfaction with the sexual partner. Epicurus does not
articulate a broad system of social ethics that has survived but had a unique
version of the Golden Rule. It is impossible to live a pleasant life
without living wisely and well and justly (agreeing "neither to harm nor
be harmed"), and it is impossible to live wisely and well and justly
without living a pleasant life. Epicureanism was originally a challenge to
Platonism, though later it became the main opponent of Stoicism. Epicurus and
his followers shun politics. After the death of Epicurus, his school is headed
by Hermarchus; later many Epicurean societies flourished in the Late
Hellenistic era and during the Roman era (such as those in Antiochia, Alexandria,
Rhodes and Ercolano). The poet Lucretius is its most known Roman proponent. By
the end of the Roman Empire, having undergone Christian attack and repression,
Epicureanism has all but died out, and would be resurrected in the 17th century
by the atomist Pierre Gassendi, who adapts it to the Christian doctrine.
Some writings by Epicurus have survived. Some scholars consider the epic poem
On the Nature of Things by Lucretius to present in one unified work the core
arguments and theories of Epicureanism. Many of the papyrus scrolls unearthed
at the Villa of the Papyri at Herculaneum are Epicurean texts. At least some
are thought to have belonged to the Epicurean Philodemus. Cf. Barnes on
epicures and connoiseurs. Many controversies arising out of value judgements
are settled by saying I like it and you dont, and that s the end of the matter.
We are content to adopt this solution of the difficult y on matters such as
food and drink, though even here we admit the existence of epicures and
connoisseurs.Why are we not content to accept the same solution on all matters
where value is concerned? The reason we are not so content seems to lie in the
fact that the action of one man dictated by his approval of something is
frequently incompatible with the action of another man dictated by his approval
of something. This is obviously philosophical, especially for the Grecian
hedonistic Epicureians made popular by Marius and Walter Pater at Oxford. L and
S have "ἡδονή," Dor. ἁδονά (or in Trag. chorus ἡδονά S. OT1339), from
"ἥδομαι," and which they render as enjoyment, pleasure, first in
Simon.71, S.l.c., Hdt. 1.24, al.; prop. of sensual pleasures, αἱ τοῦ σώματος or
περὶ τὸ σῶμα ἡ., X. HG 4.8.22,6.1.4; αἱ κατὰ τὸ σῶμα ἡ. Pl. R. 328d; σωματικαὶ
ἡ. Arist. Eth. Nich. 1151a13; αἱ περὶ πότους καὶ περὶ ἐδωδὰς ἡ. Pl R. 389e; but
also ἀκοῆς ἡ. Th. 3.38; ἡ ἀπὸ τοῦ εἰδέναι ἡ. Pl. R. 582b; of malicious
pleasure, ἡ ἐπὶ τοῖς τῶν φίλων κακοῖς, ἐπὶ ταῖς λοιδορίαις ἡ., Id. Phlb. 50a,
D. 18. 138; ἡδονῇ ἡσσᾶσθαι, ἡδοναῖς χαρίζεσθαι, to give way to pleasure, Th.
l.c., Pl. Lg. 727c; κότερα ἀληθείη χρήσομαι ἢ ἡδονῆ; shall I speak truly or so
as to humour you? Hdt. 7.101; εἰ ὑμῖν ἡδονὴ τοῦ ἡγεμονεύειν ib. 160; ἡ.
εἰσέρχεταί τιϝι εἰ one feels pleasure at
the thought that.., Id. 1. 24; ἡδονὴν ἔχειν τινός to be satisfied with, S. OC
1604; ἡδονὴν ἔχει, φέρει, Pherecr. 145. 2, Alex. 263.6; ἡδονὴ ἰδέσθαι (θαῦμα
ἰδέσθαι), of a temple, Hdt. 2. 137, δαίμοσιν πρὸς ἡδονήν A. Pr. 494; ὃ μέν ἐστι
πρὸς ἡ. D. 18.4; πρὸς ἡ. λέγειν to speak so as to please another, S. El. 921,
Th. 2. 65; δημηγορεῖν D. 4.38; οὐ πρὸς ἡ. οἱ ἦν τὰ ἀγγελλόμενα Hdt. 3. 126;
πάντα πρὸς ἡ. ἀκούοντας D. 8.34; later πρὸς ἡδονῆς εἶναί τινι Parth. 8.8, Lib.
Or. 12.1; καθ᾽ ἡδονὴν κλύειν S. Tr. 197; καθ᾽ ἡδονήν ἐστί μοι c.inf., A. Pr.
263; καθ᾽ ἡ. τι δρᾶν, ποιεῖν, Th. 2. 37,53; καθ᾽ ἡδονὰς τῷ δήμῳ τὰ
πράγματα ἐνδιδόναι ib.65; ἐν ἡδονῇ ἐστί τινι, it is a pleasure or delight to
another, Hdt. 4.139; E. IT494; Hdt. 7.15; ἐν ἡδονῇ ἔχειν τινάς, to take
pleasure in them, Th. 3.9; ἐν ἡδονῇ ἄρχοντες, oοἱ λυπηροί, Id. 1.99; μεθ᾽
ἡδονῆς Id. 4.19; ὑφ᾽ ἡδονῆς S. Ant. 648, etc.; ὑπὸ τῆς ἡ. Alex.24, 110.23: as
dat. modi, ἡδονᾷ with pleasure, S. OT 1339 (lyr.), cf. Hdt. 2. 137 (f.l.), a
pleasure, S. El. 873, Ar. Nu.1072 (pl.); ἡδοναὶ τραγημάτων sweetmeats, Sopat.
17. 3. Pl., desires after pleasure, pleasant lusts, X. Mem.1. 2.23, Ep.
Tit.3.3, al. II. in Ion. Philosophers, taste, flavour, usu. joined with χροιή,
Diog. Apoll. 5, Anaxag. 4, cf. Arist. PA 660b9, Thphr. HP4. 4.7, LXX Nu.11.8,
Eudem. ap. Ath. 9. 369f, Mnesith. ap. eund. 8.357f. Note that Aristotle
uses somatike hedone. As a Lit. Hum. Oxon., and especially as a tutee of
Hardie at Corpus, Grice is almost too well aware of the centrality of hedone in
Aristotles system! Pleasure is rendered placitum (as in ad placitum) in
scholastic philosophy, but thats because scholastic philosophy is not as
Hellenic as it should be! Actually, Grice prefers agreeable. One of Grices
requisites for an ascription of eudaemonia (to have a fairy godmother)
precisely has the system of ends an agent chooses to realise to be an agreeable
one. One form, or mode, of agreeableness, as Grice notes, is, unless
counteracted, automatically attached to the attainment of an object of desire,
such attainment being routinely a source of satisfaction. The generation of
such a satisfaction thus provides an independent ground for preferring one
system of ends to another. However, some other mode of agreeableness, such as
being a source of delight, for example, which are _not routinely associated
with the fulfilment of this or that desire, could discriminate, independently
of other features relevant to such a preference, between one system of ends and
another. Further, a system of ends the operation of which is especially
agreeable is stable not only vis-à-vis a rival system, but also against the
somewhat weakening effect of incontinence, or akrasia, if you mustnt! A
disturbing influence, as Aristotle knew from experience, is more surely met by
a principle in consort with a supporting attraction than by the principle
alone! Grices favourite hedonistic implicatum was Please!, as in Please, please
me!
AVOWAL: A discussion of a category mistake. Cf. Grice: I may
be categorically mistaken but Im not categorically confused. It is only natural
that if Grice was interested on Aristotle on pleasure he would be
interested on Aristotle on pain. This is very philosophical, as Urmson will
agree. Is pleasure just the absence of pain? Liddell and Soctt have it: λύπη,
which they render as pain of body, oἡδον Id. Phlb. 31c, etc.; also, sad plight
or condition, Hdt. 7. 152. 2. pain of mind, grief, ib.16. ά; δῆγμα δὲ λύπης
οὐδὲν ἐφ᾽ ἧπαρ προσικνεῖται A. Ag.791, τί γὰρ καλὸν ζῆν βίοτον, ὃς λύπας φέρει;
Id. Fr. 177, cf. S. OC 1217, etc.; ἐρωτικὴ λ. Th. 6.59; λύπας προσβάλλειν
Antipho 2. 2. 2; λ. φέρειν τινί And. 2. 8; oχαρά, X. HG7. 1.32. Oddly,
Grice goes back to pain in Princeton 1972, since it is Smarts example in his
identtiy thesis. “Take pain. Surely, Grice tells the Princetonians, “it
sounds harsh,” to echo Berkeley, to say that it is Smiths brains being in this
or that a state which is justified by insufficient evidence! Oddly, Im in pain
vs. Ouch! is the example given by Barnes, of Corpus, for The Jowett, to apply
Ogdens thesis on communication as emotional. Grice criticises this in
Prolegomena, "Surely we have to qualify the idea that to say x is good is
to approve of it." Pain is an excellent example for Grice ofr a privileged
access incorrigible avowal, and stage 0 in his creature progression. By
uttering Ouch!, under voluntary control, U means, iconically, that he is in
pain. Pain should fall under keyword: emotion, as anger. Cf. Aristotle on
emotions in De anima, Rhetorica, and Eth. Nich. At Oxford, if you are a
classicist, you are not a philosopher, so Grice never explores the Stoic, say,
approach to pain, or lack thereof! Walter Pater did!
ESCHATOLOGY: Some like Hegel, but Collingwoods *my*
man! ‒ Grice. Grice participated in two consecutive evenings of the s.
of programmes on metaphysics organised by Pears. Actually, charming Pears felt
pretentious enough to label the meetings to be about the nature of metaphysics!
Grice ends up discussing, as he should, Collingwood on presupposition. Met. remained a favourite topic for Grices
philosophical explorations, as it is evident from his essay on Met. ,
Philosophical Eschatology, and Platos Republic, reprinted in his WOW . Possibly
Hardie is to blame, since he hardly tutored Grice on metaphysics! Grices two
BBC lectures are typically dated in tone. It was the (good ole) days when
philosophers thought they could educate the non-elite by dropping Namess like
Collingwood and stuff! The Third Programme was extremely popular, especially
among the uneducated ones at London, as Pears almost put it, as it was a way
for Londoners to get to know what is going on down at Oxford, the only place an
uneducated (or educated, for that matter) Londoner at the time was interested
in displaying some interest about! I mean, Johnson is right: if a man is tired
of the nature of metaphysics, he is tired of life! Since the authorship is
Grice, Strawson, and Pears, Met. , in Pears, The Nature of Met., The BBC Third
Programme, it is somewhat difficult to identify what paragraphs were actually
read by Grice (and which ones by Pears and which ones by Strawson). But trust
the sharp Griceian to detect the correct implicature! There are many (too many)
other items covered by these two lectures: Kant, Aristotle, in no particular
order. And in The Grice Collection, for that matter, that cover the field of
metaphysics. In the New World, as a sort of tutor in the graduate programme,
Grice was expected to cover the discipline at various seminars. Only I dislike
discipline! Perhaps his clearest exposition is in the opening section of his Met.
, philosophical eschatology, and Platos Republic, reprinted in his WOW , where
he states, bluntly that all you need is
metaphysics! 1980, metaphysics, Miscellaneous, metaphysics notes, Grice
would possible see metaphysics as a class – category figuring large. He was
concerned with the methodological aspects of the metaphysical enterprise, since
he was enough of a relativist to allow for one metaphysical scheme to apply to
one area of discourse (one of Eddingtons tables) and another metaphysical
scheme to apply to another (Eddingtons other table). In the third programme for
the BBC Grice especially enjoyed criticising John Wisdoms innovative look at
metaphysics as a bunch of self-evident falsehoods (Were all alone). Grice
focuses on Wisdom on the knowledge of other minds. He also discusses
Collingwoods presuppositions, and Bradley on the reality-appearance distinction.
Grices reference to Wisdom was due to Ewings treatment of Wisdom on
metaphysics. Grices main motivation here is defending metaphysics against Ayer.
Ayer thought to win more Oxonian philosophers than he did at Oxford, but he was
soon back in London. Post-war Oxford had become conservative and would not stand
to the nonsense of Ayers claiming that metaphysics is nonsense, especially, as
Ayers implicature also was, that philosophy is nonsense! Perhaps the best
summary of Griceian metaphysics is his From Genesis to Revelations: a new
discourse on metaphysics. It’s an ontological answer that one must give to
Grices metabolic operation from utterers meaning to expression meaning.
PARADIGM-CASE ARGUMENT: The issue of analyticity is, as Locke puts
it, the issue of whats trifle. That a triangle is trilateral Locke considers a
trifling proposition, like Saffron is yellow. Lewes (who calls mathematical
propositions analytic) describes the Kantian problem. Grices reductive ANALYSIS
of meaning DEPENDS on the analytic. Few Oxonian philosophers would follow Loar
(D. Phil Oxon, under Warnock) in thinking of Grices conversational maxims as
empirical inductive generalisations over functional states! Synthesis may do in
the New World,but hardly in the Old! The locus classicus for the
ordinary-language philosophical response to Quine in Two dogmas of empiricism.
Grice and Strawson claim that is analytic
does have an ordinary-language use, as attached two a type of behavioural
conversational response. To an analytically false move (such as My neighbours
three-year-old son is an adult) the addressee A is bound to utter, I dont
understand you! You are not being figurative, are you? To a synthetically false
move, on the other hand (such as My neighbours three-year-old understands
Russells Theory of Types), the addressee A will jump with, Cant believe
it! The topdogma of analyticity is for Grice very important to
defend. Philosophy depends on it! He knows that to many his claim to
fame is his In defence of a dogma, the topdogma of analyticity, no
less. He eventually turns to a pragmatist justification of the
distinction. This pragmatist justification is still in accordance with
what he sees as the use of analytic in ordinary language. His infamous examples
are as follows. My neighbours three-year old understands Russells Theory of
Types. A: Hard to believe, but I will. My neighbours three-year old is an
adult. Metaphorically? No. Then I dont understand you, and what youve
just said is, in my scheme of things, analytically false. Ultimately, there are
conversational criteria, based on this or that principle of conversational
helfpulness. Grice is also circumstantially concerned with the synthetic a
priori, and he would ask his childrens playmates: Can a sweater be red and
green all over? No stripes allowed! The distinction is ultimately Kantian,
but it had brought to the fore by the linguistic turn, Oxonian and other! In
defence of a dogma, Two dogmas of empiricism, : the
analytic-synthetic distinction. For Quine, there are two. Grice is mainly
interested in the first one: that there is a distinction between the analytic
and the synthetic. Grice considers Empiricism as a monster on his way to the
Rationalist City of Eternal Truth. Grice came back time and again to
explore the analytic-synthetic distinction. But his philosophy remained
constant. His sympathy is for the practicality of it, its rationale. He sees it
as involving formal calculi, rather than his own theory of conversation as
rational co-operation which does not presuppose the analytic-synthetic
distinction, even if it explains it! Grice would press the issue here: if one
wants to prove that such a theory of conversation as rational co-operation has
to be seen as philosophical, rather than some other way, some idea of
analyticity may be needed to justify the philosophical enterprise. Cf. the
synthetic a priori, that fascinated Grice most than anything Kantian else! Can
a sweater be green and red all over? No stripes allowed. With In defence of a
dogma, Grice and Strawson attack a New-World philosopher. Grice had previously
collaborated with Strawson in an essay on Met. (actually a three-part piece, with Pears as
the third author). The example Grice chooses to refute Quines attack of the
top-dogma is the Aristotelian idea of the peritrope, as Aristotle refutes
Antiphasis in Met. (v. Ackrill, Burnyeat
and Dancy). Grice explores chapter Γ 8 of Aristotles Met. . In Γ
8, Aristotle presents two self-refutation arguments against two theses,
and calls the asserter, Antiphasis, T1 = Everything is true, and T2 =
Everything is false, Metaph. Γ 8, 1012b13–18. Each thesis is exposed to
the stock objection that it eliminates itself. An utterer who explicitly
conveys that everything is true also makes the thesis opposite to his own true,
so that his own is not true (for the opposite thesis denies that his is true),
and any utterer U who explicitly conveys that everything is false also belies
himself. Aristotle does not seem to be claiming that, if everything
is true, it would also be true that it is false that everything is true and,
that, therefore, Everything is true must be false: the final, crucial
inference, from the premise if, p, ~p to the conclusion ~p is
missing. But it is this extra inference that seems required to have a
formal refutation of Antiphasiss T1 or T2 by consequentia mirabilis. The
nature of the argument as a purely dialectical silencer of Antiphasis is
confirmed by the case of T2, Everything is false. An utterer who explicitly
conveys that everything is false unwittingly concedes, by self-application,
that what he is saying must be false too. Again, the further and different
conclusion Therefore; it is false that everything is false is
missing. That proposal is thus self-defeating, self-contradictory (and
comparable to Grices addressee using adult to apply to three-year old, without
producing the creature), oxymoronic, and suicidal. This seems all that
Aristotle is interested in establishing through the self-refutation stock
objection. This is not to suggest that Aristotle did not believe that
Everything is true or Everything is false is false, or that he excludes that he
can prove its falsehood. Grice notes that this is not what Aristotle seems
to be purporting to establish in 1012b13–18. This holds for a περιτροπή
(peritrope) argument, but not for a περιγραφή (perigraphe) argument (συμβαίνει
δὴ καὶ τὸ θρυλούμενον πᾶσι τοῖς τοιούτοις λόγοις, αὐτοὺς ἑαυτοὺς ἀναιρεῖν. ὁ
μὲν γὰρ πάντα ἀληθῆ λέγων καὶ τὸν ἐναντίον αὑτοῦ λόγον ἀληθῆ ποιεῖ, ὥστε τὸν
ἑαυτοῦ οὐκ ἀληθῆ (ὁ γὰρ ἐναντίος οὔ φησιν αὐτὸν ἀληθῆ), ὁ δὲ πάντα ψευδῆ καὶ
αὐτὸς αὑτόν.) It may be emphasized that Aristotles argument does not
contain an explicit application of consequentia mirabilis. Indeed, no
extant self-refutation argument before Augustine, Grice is told by Mates,
contains an explicit application of consequentia mirabilis. This observation is
a good and important one, but Grice has doubts about the consequences one may
draw from it. One may take the absence of an explicit application of
consequentia mirabilis to be a sign of the purely dialectical nature of the
self-refutation argument. This is questionable. The formulation of a
self-refutation argument (as in Grices addressee, Sorry, I misused adult.) is
often compressed and elliptical and involves this or that implicatum. One
usually assumes that this or that piece in a dialectical context has been
omitted and should be supplied (or worked out, as Grice prefers) by the
addressee. But in this or that case, it is equally possible to supply some
other, non-dialectical piece of reasoning. In Aristotles arguments from Γ
8, e.g., the addressee may supply an inference to the effect that the thesis which
has been shown to be self-refuting is not true. For if Aristotle takes the
argument to establish that the thesis has its own contradictory version as a
consequence, it must be obvious to Aristotle that the thesis is not true (since
every consequence of a true thesis is true, and two contradictory theses cannot
be simultaneously true). On the further assumption (that Grice makes
explicit) that the principle of bivalence is applicable, Aristotle may even
infer that the thesis is false. It is perfectly plausible to attribute
such an inference to Aristotle and to supply it in his argument from Γ
8. On this account, there is no reason to think that the argument is of an
intrinsically dialectical nature and cannot be adequately represented as a
non-dialectical proof of the non-truth, or even falsity, of the thesis in
question. It is indeed difficult to see signs of a dialectical exchange
between two parties (of the type of which Grice and Strawson are champions) in
Γ8, 1012b13–18. One piece of evidence is Aristotles reference to the
person, the utterer, as Grice prefers who explicitly conveys or asserts (ὁ
λέγων) that T1 or that T2. This reference by the Grecian philosopher to
the Griceian utterer or asserter of the thesis that everything is true would be
irrelevant if Aristotles aim is to prove something about T1s or T2s
propositional content, independently of the act by the utterer of uttering
its expression and thereby explicitly conveying it. However, it is not
clear that this reference is essential to Aristotles argument. One may
even doubt whether the Grecian philosopher is being that Griceian, and actually
referring to the asserter of T1 or T2. The *implicit* (or implicated)
grammatical Subjects of Aristotles ὁ λέγων (1012b15) might be λόγος, instead of
the utterer qua asserter. λόγος is surely the implicit grammatical Subjects of
ὁ λέγων shortly after ( 1012b21–22. 8). The passage may be taken to be
concerned with λόγοι ‒ this or that statement, this or that
thesis ‒ but not with its asserter. In the Prior Analytics,
Aristotle states that no thesis (A three-year old is an adult) can necessarily
imply its own contradictory (A three-year old is not an adult) (2.4,
57b13–14). One may appeal to this statement in order to argue for
Aristotles claim that a self-refutation argument should NOT be analyzed as
involving an implicit application of consequentia mirabilis. Thus, one should
deny that Aristotles self-refutation argument establishes a necessary
implication from the self-refuting thesis to its contradictory. However,
this does not explain what other kind of consequence relation Aristotle takes
the self-refutation argument to establish between the self-refuting thesis and
its contradictory, although dialectical necessity has been suggested.
Aristotles argument suffices to establish that Everything is false is either
false or liar-paradoxical. If a thesis is liar-paradoxical (and Grice
loved, and overused the expression), the assumption of its falsity leads to
contradiction as well as the assumption of its truth. But Everything is
false is only liar-paradoxical in the unlikely, for Aristotle perhaps
impossible, event that everything distinct from this thesis is false. So,
given the additional premise that there is at least one true item distinct from
the thesis Everything is false, Aristotle can safely infer that the thesis is
false. As for Aristotles ὁ γὰρ λέγων τὸν ἀληθῆ λόγον ἀληθῆ ἀληθής,, or eliding
the γὰρ, ὁ λέγων τὸν ἀληθῆ λόγον ἀληθῆ ἀληθής, (ho
legon ton alethe logon alethe alethes) may be rendered as either: The statement
which states that the true statement is true is true, or, more alla Grice,
as He who says (or explicitly conveys, or indicates) that the true thesis
is true says something true. It may be argued that it is quite baffling
(and figurative or analogical or metaphoric) in this context, to take ἀληθής to
be predicated of the Griceian utterer, a person (true standing for truth
teller, trustworthy), to take it to mean that he says something true,
rather than his statement stating something true, or his statement being true.
But cf. L and S: ἀληθής [α^], Dor. ἀλαθής, [α^], Dor. ἀλαθής, ές, f. λήθω, of
persons, truthful, honest (not in Hom., v. infr.), ἀ. νόος Pi. O.2.92;
κατήγορος A. Th. 439; κριτής Th. 3.56; οἶνος ἀ. `in vino veritas, Pl. Smp.
217e; ὁ μέσος ἀ. τις Arist. EN 1108a20. Admittedly, this or that non-Griceian
passage in which it is λόγος, and not the utterer, which is the implied
grammatical Subjects of ὁ λέγων can be found in Metaph. Γ7, 1012a24–25; Δ6,
1016a33; Int. 14, 23a28–29; De motu an. 10, 703a4; Eth. Nic. 2.6, 1107a6–7.
9. So the topic is controversial. Indeed such a non-Griceian exegesis of
the passage is given by Alexander of Aphrodisias (in Metaph. 340. 26–29):9,
when Alexander observes that the statement, i.e. not the utterer, that says
that everything is false (ὁ δὲ πάντα ψευδῆ εἶναι λέγων λόγος) negates itself,
not himself, because if everything is false, this very statement, which, rather
than, by which the utterer, says that everything is false, would be false, and
how can an utterer be FALSE? So that the statement which, rather than the
utterer who, negates it, saying that not everything is false, would be true,
and surely an utterer cannot be true. Does Alexander misrepresent Aristotles
argument by omitting every Griceian reference to the asserter or utterer qua
rational personal agent, of the thesis? If the answer is negative, even if the
occurrence of ὁ λέγων at 1012b15 refers to the asserter, or utterer, qua
rational personal agent, this is merely an accidental feature of Aristotles
argument that cannot be regarded as an indication of its dialectical nature.
None of this is to deny that some self-refutation argument may be of an
intrinsically dialectical nature; it is only to deny that every one is This is
in line with Burnyeats view that a dialectical self-refutation, even if
qualified, as Aristotle does, as ancient, is a subspecies of self-refutation,
but does not exhaust it. Granted, a dialectical approach may provide a useful
interpretive framework for many an ancient self-refutation argument. A
statement like If proof does not exist, proof exists ‒ that occurs in an
anti-sceptical self-refutation argument reported by Sextus
Empiricus ‒ may receive an attractive dialectical re-interpretation.
It may be argued that such a statement should not be understood at the
level of what is explicated, but should be regarded as an elliptical reminder
of a complex dialectical argument which can be described as follows. Cf. If
thou claimest that proof doth not exist, thou must present a proof of what thou
assertest, in order to be credible, but thus thou thyself admitest that proof
existeth. A similar point can be made for Aristotles famous argument in the
Protrepticus that one must philosophise. A number of sources state that this
argument relies on the implicature, If one must not philosophize, one must
philosophize. It may be argued that this implicature is an elliptical reminder
of a dialectical argument such as the following. If thy position is that thou
must not philosophise, thou must reflect on this choice and argue in its
support, but by doing so thou art already choosing to do philosophy, thereby
admitting that thou must philosophise. The claim that every instance of an
ancient self-refutation arguments is of an intrinsically dialectical nature is
thus questionable, to put it mildly. V also 340.19–26, and A. Madigan, tcomm.,
Alexander of Aphrodisias: On Aristotles Met. 4, Ithaca, N.Y., Burnyeat, Protagoras and
Self-Refutation in Later Greek Philosophy,. Grices implicature is that Quine
should have learned Greek before refuting Aristotle. But then *I* dont speak
Greek! Strawson refuted.
OXONIANISM: Grice cannot possibly claim to talk about post-war
Oxford philosophy, but his own! Cf. Oxfords post-war
philosophy. What were Grices first impressions when arriving at
Oxford. He was going to learn. Only the poor learn at Oxford was an adage he
treasured, since he wasnt one! Lets start with an alphabetical listing of
Grices Play Group companions: Austin, Butler, Flew, Gardiner, Grice,
Hare, Hampshire, Hart, Nowell-Smith, Parkinson, Paul, Pears, Quinton, Sibley,
Strawson, Thomson, Urmson, and Warnock. Grices main Oxonian
association is St. Johns, Oxford. By Oxford Philosophy, Grice notably
refers to Austins Play Group, of which he was a member. But Grice had
Oxford associations pre-war, and after the demise of Austin. But back to the
Play Group, this, to some, infamous, playgroup, met on Saturday mornings at
different venues at Oxford, including Grices own St. Johns ‒
apparently, Austins favourite venue. Austin regarded himself and his
kindergarten as linguistic or language botanists. The idea was to list various
ordinary uses of this or that philosophical notion. Austin: They say
philosophy is about language; well, then, lets botanise! Grices involvement
with Oxford philosophy of course predated his associations with Austins play
group. He always said he was fortunate of having been a tutee to Hardie at
Corpus. Corpus, Oxford. Grice would occasionally refer to the emblematic
pelican, so prominently displayed at Corpus. Grice had an interim
association with the venue one associates most directly with philosophy, Merton
‒: Grice, Merton, Oxford. While Grice loved to drop Oxonian Namess,
notably his rivals, such as Dummett or Anscombe, he knew when not to. His
Post-war Oxford philosophy, as opposed to more specific items in The Grice
Collection, remains general in tone, and intended as a defense of the
ordinary-language approach to philosophy. Surprisingly, or perhaps not (for
those who knew Grice), he takes a pretty idiosyncratic characterisation of
conceptual analysis. Grices philosophical problems emerge with Grices
idiosyncratic use of this or that expression. Conceptual analysis is meant to
solve HIS problems, not others! Repr. in Grice, WOW . Grice
finds it important to reprint this since he had updated thoughts on the matter,
which he displays in his Conceptual analysis and the province of
philosophy. The topic represents one of the strands he identifies behind
the unity of his philosophy. By post-war Oxford philosophy, Grice meant
the period he was interested in. While he had been at Corpus, Merton, and
St. Johns in the pre-war days, for some reason, he felt that he had made
history in the post-war period. The historical reason Grice gives is
understandable enough. In the pre-war days, Grice was the good student and
the new fellow of St. Johns ‒ the other one was Mabbott. But he had not
been able to engage in philosophical discussion much, other than with other
tutees of Hardie. After the war, Grice indeed joins Austins more popular, less
secretive Saturday mornings. Indeed, for Grice, post-war means all philosophy
after the war (and not just say, the forties!) since he never abandoned the
methods he developed under Austin, which were pretty congenial to the ones he had
himself displayed in the pre-war days, in essays like Negation and Personal
identity. Grice is a a bit of an expert on Oxonian philosophy. He
sees himself as a member of the school of analytic philosophy, rather than the
abused term ordinary-language philosophy. This is evident by the fact that
he contributed to such polemic ‒ but typically Oxonian ‒
volumes such as Butler, Analytic Philosophy, published by Blackwell (of all
publishers). Grice led a very social life at Oxford, and held frequent
philosophical discussions with the Play group philosophers (alphabetically
listed above), and many others, such as Wood. Post-war Oxford philosophy,
1958, miscellaneous, Oxford philosophy, in WOW , Part II, Semantics and Met. ,
Essay. By Oxford philosophy, Grice means his own! Grice went back to the topic
of philosophy and ordinary language, as one of his essays is precisely
entitled, Philosophy and ordinary language, 1970, philosophy and ordinary
language, : ordinary-language philosophy, linguistic botanising. Grice is not
really interested in ordinary language as a philologist might. He spoke
ordinary language, he thought. The point had been brought to the fore by
Austin. If they think philosophy is a play on words, well then, lets play
the game. Grices interest is methodological. Malcolm had been claiming
that ordinary language is incorrigible. While Grice agreed that language can be
clever, he knew that Aristotle was possibly right when he explored ta
legomena in terms of the many and the selected wise, 1960, philosophy and
ordinary language, philosophy and ordinary language, : philosophy, ordinary
language. At the time of writing, ordinary-language philosophy had become,
even within Oxford, a bit of a term of abuse. Grice tries to defend
Austins approach to it, while suggesting ideas that Austin somewhat ignored,
like what an utterer implies by the use of an ordinary-language expression,
rather than what the expression itself does. Grice is concerned, contra
Austin, in explanation (or explanatory adequacy), not taxonomy (or descriptive
adequacy). Grice disregards Austins piecemeal approach to ordinary
language, as Grice searches for the big picture of it all. Grice never used
ordinary language seriously. The phrase was used, as he explains, by those who
HATED ordinary-language philosophy. Theres no such thing as ordinary language.
Surely you cannot fairly describe the idiosyncratic linguistic habits of an Old
Cliftonian as even remotely ordinary. Extra-ordinary more likely! As far as the
philosophy bit goes, this is what Bergmann jocularly described as the
linguistic turn. But as Grice notes, the linguistic turn involves both the
ideal language and the ordinary language. Grice defends Austins choice of the
ordinary seeing that it was what he had to hand! While Grice seems to be in
agreement with the tone of his Wellesley talk, his idioms there in. Youre
crying for the moon! Philosophy need not be grand! These seem to contrast with
his more grandiose approach to philosophy. His struggle was to defend the
minutiæ of linguistic botanising, that had occupied most of his professional
life, with a grander view of the discipline. He blamed Oxford for that. Never
in the history of philosophy had philosophers shown such an attachment to
ordinary language as they did in post-war Oxford, Grice liked to say.
Having learned Grecian and Latin at Clifton, Grice saw in Oxford a way to go
back to English! He never felt the need to explore Continental modern languages
like German or French. Aristotle was of course cited in Greek, but Descartes is
almost not cited, and Kant is cited in the translation available to Oxonians
then. Grice is totally right that never has philosophy experienced such a
fascination with ordinary use except at Oxford. The ruthless and unswerving
association of philosophy with ordinary language has been peculiar to the
Oxford scene. While many found this attachment to ordinary usage insidious, as
Warnock put it, it fit me and Grice to a T, implicating you need a sort of
innate disposition towards it! Strawson perhaps never had it! And thats why
Grices arguments contra Strawson rest on further minutiæ whose detection by
Grice never ceased to amaze his tutee! In this way, Grice felt he WAS Austins
heir! While Grice is associated with, in chronological order, Corpus, Merton,
and St. Johns, it is only St. Johns that counts for the Griceian! For it is at
St. Johns he was a Tutorial Fellow in Philosophy! And we love him as a
philosopher.
SENSE-DATUM: This is Grice on sense-datum. Note that Price is also cited by Grice in Personal identity. Grice: That pillar box seems red to me. The locus classicus in the philosophical literature for Grices implicatum. Grice introduces a dout-or-denial condition for an utterance of a phenomenalist report (That pillar-box seems red to me). Grice attacks neo-Wittgensteinian approaches that regard the report as _false_. In a long excursus on implication, he compares the phenomenalist report with utterances like He has beautiful handwriting (He is hopeless at philosophy), a particularised conversational implicatum; My wife is in the kitchen or the garden (I have non-truth-functional grounds to utter this), a generalised conversational implicatum; She was poor but she was honest (a Great-War witty (her poverty and her honesty contrast), a conventional implicatum; and Have you stopped beating your wife? an old Oxonian conundrum. You have been beating your wife, cf. Smith has not ceased from eating iron, a presupposition. More importantly, he considers different tests for each concoction! Those for the conversational implicatum will become crucial: cancellability, calculability, non-detachability, and indeterminacy. In the proceedings he plays with something like the principle of conversational helpfulness, as having a basis on a view of conversation as rational co-operation, and as giving the rationale to the implicatum. Past the excursus, and back to the issue of perception, he holds a conservative view as presented by Price at Oxford. One interesting reprint of Grices essay is in Daviss volume on Causal theories, since this is where it belongs! Whites response is usually ignored, but shouldnt. White is an interesting Australian philosopher at Oxford who is usually regarded as a practitioner of ordinary-language philosophy. However, in his response, White hardly touches the issue of the implicature with which Grice is primarily concerned. Grice found that a full reprint from the Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society in a compilation also containing the James Harvard would be too repetitive. Therefore, he omits the excursus on implication. However, the way Grice re-formulates, in 1987, what that excursus covers is very interesting. There is the conversational implicatum, particularised (Smith has beautiful handwriting) and generalised (My wife is in the kitchen or in the garden). Then there is the præsuppositum, or presupposition (You havent stopped beating your wife). Finally, there is the conventional implicatum ( She was poor, but she was honest). Even at Oxford, Grices implicature goes, philosophers ‒ even Oxonian philosophers ‒ use imply for all those different animals! Warnock had attended Austins Sense and Sensibilia (not to be confused with Austens Sense and Sensibility), which Grice found boring, but Warnock didnt because Austin reviews his "Berkeley." But Warnock, for obvious reasons, preferred philosophical investigations with Grice. Warnock reminisces that Grice once tells him, and not on a Saturday morning, either, How clever language is For they had found that ordinary language does NOT need the concept of a visum. Grice and Warnock spent lovely occasions exploring what Oxford has as the philosophy of perception. While Grice later came to see philosophy of perception as a bit or an offshoot of philosophical psychology, the philosophy of perception is concerned with that treasured bit of the Oxonian philosophers lexicon, the sense-datum, always in the singular! The cause involved is crucial. Grice plays with an evolutionary justification of the material thing as the denotatum of a perceptual judgement. If a material thing causes the sense-datum of a nut, that is because the squarrel (or squirrel) will not be nourished by the sense datum of the nut; only by the nut! There are many other items in the Grice Collection that address the topic of perception – notably with Warnock, and criticizing members of the Ryle group like Roxbee-Cox (on vision, cf. visa ‒ taste, and perception, in general – And we should not forget that Grice contributed a splendid essay on the distinction of the senses to Butlers Analytic philosophy, which in a way, redeemed a rather old-fashioned discipline by shifting it to the idiom of the day. 1959. The philosophy of perception: a retrospective, with Warnock, the philosophy of perception, : perception, the philosophy of perception, visum. Warnock was possibly the only philosopher at Oxford Grice felt congenial enough to engage in different explorations in the so-called philosophy of perception. Their joint adventures involved the disimplicature of a visum. Grice later approached sense data in more evolutionary terms: a material thing is to be vindicated transcendentally, in the sense that it is a material thing (and not a sense datum or collection thereof) that nourishes a creature like a human. Grice was particularly grateful to Warnock. By reprinting the full symposium on The causal theory of perception in his influential s. of Oxford Readings in Philosophy, Warnock had spread Grices lore of implicature all over! In some parts of the draft he uses more on visa, 1959, vision, 1969, vision, with Warnock, vision. Of the five senses, Grice and Warnock are particularly interested in seeing. As Grice will put it later, see is a factive. It presupposes the existence of the event reported after the that-clause. A visum, however, as an intermediary between the material thing and the perceiver does not seem necessary in ordinary discourse. Warnock will reconsider Grices views too (On what is seen, in Sibley). While Grice uses vision, he knows he is interested in Philosophers paradox concerning seeing, notably Witters on seeing as. 1959, vision, taste and the philosophy of perception, : vision, seeing. As an Oxonian philosopher, Grice was of course more interested in seeing than in vision. He said that Austin would criticise even the use of things like sensation and volition! 1959, taste, The Grice Papers, keyword: taste, the objects of the five senses, the philosophy of perception, perception, the philosophy of perception, : philosophy of perception, vision, taste, perception. Mainly with Warnock. Warnock reprinted Grices Causal theory of perception in his influential Reading in Philosophy, The philosophy of perception, 1959, perception, with Warnock, with Warner, : perception. Warnock learns about perception much more from Grice than from Austin! 1959, taste, 1960, The philosophy of perception, the philosophy of perception, notes with Warnock on visum, : visum, Warnock, Grice, the philosophy of perception. Grice kept the lecture notes to a view of publishing a retrospective. Warnock recalled Grice saying, How clever language is! Grice took the offer by Harvard University Press, and it was a good thing he reprinted part of Causal theory. However, the relevant bits for his theory of conversation as rational co-operation lie in the excursus which he omitted. What is Grices implicature: that one should consider the topic rather than the method here. being sense datum, and causation, rather than conversational helpfulness. After all, That pillar box seems red to me, does not sound very helpful. But the topic of Causal theory is central for his view of conversation as rational co-operation. Why? Pirot1 gets an impression of danger as caused by the danger out there. He communicates the danger to Pirot1, causing in Pirot2 some behaviour. Without causation, or causal links, the very point of offering a theory of conversation as rational co-operation seems minimized. On top, as a metaphysician, he was also concerned with cause simpliciter. He was especially proud that Prices Casual Theory of Perception had been reprinted along with his essay in the influential volume by Davis on Causal theories. In Actions and events, he further explores cause now in connection with Greek aitia. As Grice notes, the original usage of this very Grecian item is the one we find in rebel without a cause, cause-to, rather than cause-because. The two-movement nature of causing is reproduced in the conversational exchange: a material thing causes a sense datum which causes an expression which gets communicated, thus causing a psychological state which will cause a behaviour. This causation is almost representational. A material thing or a situation cannot govern our actions and behaviours, but a re-præsentatum of it might. Govern our actions and behaviour is Grices correlate of what a team of North-Oxfordshire cricketers can do for North-Oxfordshire: what North Oxfordshire cannot do for herself, Namesly, engage in a game of cricket! In Retrospective epilogue he casts doubts on the point of his causal approach. It is a short paragraph that merits much exploration. Basically, Grice is saying his causalist approach is hardly an established thesis. He also proposes a similar serious objection to his view in Some remarks about the senses, the other essay in the philosophy of perception in Studies. As he notes, both engage with some fundamental questions in the philosophy of perception, which is hardly the same thing as saying that they provide an answer to each question! Grice: The issue with which I have been mainly concerned may be thought rather a fine point, but it is certainly not an isolated one. There are several philosophical theses or dicta which would I think need to be examined in order to see whether or not they are sufficiently parallel to the thesis which I have been discussing to be amenable to treatment of the same general kind. Examples which occur to me are the following. You cannot see a knife as a knife, though you may see what is not a knife as a knife. When Moore said he knew that the objects before him were human hands, he was guilty of misusing the word know. For an occurrence to be properly said to have a cause, it must be something abnormal or unusual. For an action to be properly described as one for which the agent is responsible, it must be the sort of action for which people are condemned. What is actual is not also possible. What is known by me to be the case is not also believed by me to be the case. I have no doubt that there will be other candidates besides the six which I have mentioned. I must emphasize that I am not saying that all these examples are importantly similar to the thesis which I have been criticizing, only that, for all I know, they may be. To put the matter more generally, the position adopted by my objector seems to me to involve a type of manoeuvre which is characteristic of more than one contemporary mode of philosophizing. I am not condemning this kind of manoeuvre. I am merely suggesting that to embark on it without due caution is to risk collision with the facts. Before we rush ahead to exploit the linguistic nuances which we have detectcd, we should make sure that we are reasonably clear what sort of nuances they are. The causal theory of perception, knowledge and belief, 1977, knowledge, belief, philosophical psychology. Grice: the doxastic implicatum. I know only implicates I do not believe. The following is philosophers mistake. What is known by me to be the case is not also believed by me to be the case. The topic had attracted the attention of some Oxonian philosophers such as Urmson in Parenthetical verbs. Urmson speaks of a scale: I know can be used parenthetically, as I believe can. For Grice, to utter I believe is obviously to make a weaker conversational move than you would if you utter I know. And in this case, an approach to informativeness in terms of entailment is in order, seeing that I know entails I believe. A A is thus allowed to infer that the utterer is not in a position to make the stronger claim. The mechanism is explained via his principle of conversational helpfulness. Philosophers tend two over-use these two basic psychological states, attitudes, or stances. Grice is concerned with Gettier-type cases, and also the factivity of know versus the non-factivity of believe. Grice follows Hintikkas lexicological innovations: the logic of belief is doxastic; the logic of knowledge is epistemic. The last thesis that Grice lists in Causal theory that he thinks rests on a big mistake he formulates as: What is known by me to be the case is NOT also believed by me to be the case. What are his attending remarks? Grice writes: The issue with which I have been mainly concerned may be thought rather a fine point, but it is certainly not an isolated one. There are several philosophical theses or dicta which would I think need to be examined in order to see whether or not they are sufficiently parallel to the thesis which I have been discussing to be amenable to treatment of the same general kind. An example which occurs to me is the following: What is known by me to be the case is not also believed by me to be the case. I must emphasise that I am not saying that this example is importantly similar to the thesis which I have been criticising, only that, for all I know, it may be. To put the matter more generally, the position adopted by my objector seems to me to involve a type of manoeuvre which is characteristic of more than one contemporary mode of philosophizing. I am not condemning this kind of manoeuvre. I am merely suggesting that to embark on it without due caution is to risk collision with the facts. Before we rush ahead to exploit the linguistic nuances which we have detected, we should make sure that we are reasonably clear what SORT of nuances they are! The ætiological implicatum. Grice. For an occurrence to be properly said to have a cause, it must be something abnormal or unusual. This is an example Grice lists in Causal theory but not in Prolegomena. For an occurrence to be properly said to have a cause, it must be something abnormal or unusual. Similar commentary to his example on responsible/condemnable apply. The objector may stick with the fact that he is only concerned with proper utterances. Surely Grice wants to go to a pre-Humeian account of causation, possible Aristotelian, aetiologia. Where everything has a cause, except, for Aristotle, God! What are his attending remarks? Grice writes: The issue with which I have been mainly concerned may be thought rather a fine point, but it is certainly not an isolated one. There are several philosophical theses or dicta which would I think need to be examined in order to see whether or not they are sufficiently parallel to the thesis which I have been discussing to be amenable to treatment of the same general kind. An example which occurs to me is the following: What is known by me to be the case is not also believed by me to be the case. I must emphasise that I am not saying that this example is importantly similar to the thesis which I have been criticizing, only that, for all I know, it may be. To put the matter more generally, the position adopted by my objector seems to me to involve a type of manoeuvre which is characteristic of more than one contemporary mode of philosophising. I am not condemning this kind of manoeuvre. I am merely suggesting that to embark on it without due caution is to risk collision with the facts. Before we rush ahead to exploit the linguistic nuances which we have detected, we should make sure that we are reasonably clear what sort of nuances they are! Causal theory, cause, causality, causation, conference, colloquium, Stanford, 1980, : cause, metaphysics, the abnormal/unusual implicatum, ætiology, ætiological implicatum. Grice: the ætiological implicatum. Grices explorations on cause are very rich. He is concerned with some alleged misuse of cause in ordinary language. If as Hume suggests, to cause is to will, one would say that The decapitation of Charles I willed his death, which sounds harsh, if not ungrammatical, too! Grice later relates cause to the Greek aitia, as he should. He notes collocations like rebel without a cause. For the Greeks, or Grecians, as he called them, and the Griceians, its a cause to which one should be involved in elucidating. A cause to connects with the idea of freedom. Grice was constantly aware of the threat of mechanism, and his idea was to provide philosophical room for the idea of finality, which is not mechanistically derivable. This leads him to discussion of overlap and priority of, say, a physical-cum-physiological versus a psychological theory explaining this or that piece of rational behaviour. Grice can be Wittgensteinian when citing Anscombes translation: No psychological concept without the behaviour the concept is brought to explain. It is best to place his later treatment of cause with his earlier one in Causal theory. Its surprising Grice does not apply his example of a philosophers mistake to the causal bit of his causal theory. Grice states the philosophical mistake as follows: For an occurrence to be properly said to have a cause, it must be something abnormal or unusual. This is an example Grice lists in Causal theory but not in Prolegomena. For an occurrence to be properly said to have a cause, it must be something abnormal or unusual. A similar commentary to his example on responsible/condemnable applies: The objector may stick with the fact that he is only concerned with PROPER utterances. Surely Grice wants to embrace a pre-Humeian account of causation, possible Aristotelian. Keyword: Aitiologia, where everything has a cause, except, for Aristotle, God! What are his attending remarks? Grice writes: The issue with which I have been mainly concerned may be thought rather a fine point, but it is certainly not an isolated one. There are several philosophical theses or dicta which would Grice thinks need to be examined in order to see whether or not they are sufficiently parallel to the thesis which Grice has been discussing to be amenable to treatment of the same general kind. One example which occurs to Grice is the following: For an occurrence to be properly said to have a cause, it must be something abnormal or unusual. Grice feels he must emphasise that he is not saying that this example is importantly similar to the thesis which I have been criticizing, only that, for all I know, it may be. To put the matter more generally, the position adopted by my objector seems to me to involve a type of manoeuvre which is characteristic of more than one contemporary mode of philosophizing. I am not condemning this kind of manoeuvre. I am merely suggesting that to embark on it without due caution is to risk collision with the facts. Before we rush ahead to exploit the linguistic nuances which we have detected, we should make sure that we are reasonably clear what sort of nuances they are! Re: responsibility/condemnation. Cf. Mabbott, Flew on punishment, Philosophy, 30. And also Hart. At Corpus, Grice enjoys his tutor Hardies resourcefulness in the defence of what may be a difficult position, a characteristic illustrated by an incident which Hardie himself once told Grice about himself. Hardie had parked his car and gone to a cinema. Unfortunately, Hardie had parked his car on top of one of the strips on the street by means of which traffic-lights were, at the time, controlled by the passing traffic. As a result, the lights are jammed, and it requires four policemen to lift Hardies car off the strip. The police decides to prosecute. Grice indicated to Hardie that this hardly surprised him and asked him how he fared. Oh, Hardie says, I got off. Then Grice asks Hardie how on earth he managed that! Quite simply, Hardie answers. I just invoked Mills method of difference. The police charged me with causing an obstruction at 4 p.m. I told the police that, since my car was parked at 2 p.m., it could not have been my car which caused the obstruction at *4* p.m. This relates to an example in Causal theory that he Grice does not discuss in Prolegomena, but which may relate to Hart, and closer to Grice, to Mabbotts essay on Flew on punishment, in Philosophy, 30. Grice states the philosophical mistake as follows: For an action to be properly described as one for which the agent is responsible, it must be thc sort of action for which people are condemned. As applied to Hardie. Hardie was IRRESPONSIBLE? In any case, while condemnable, he was not! Grice writes: The issue with which I have been mainly concerned may be thought rather a fine point, but it is certainly not an isolated one. There are several philosophical theses or dicta which would I think need to be examined in order to see whether or not they are sufficiently parallel to the thesis which I have been discussing to be amenable to treatment of the same general kind. An example which occurs to me is the following: For an action to be properly described as one for which the agent is responsible, it must be the sort of action for which people are condemned. I must emphasise that I am not saying that this example is importantly similar to the thesis which I have been criticizing, only that, for all I know, it may be. To put the matter more generally, the position adopted by my objector seems to me to involve a type of manoeuvre which is characteristic of more than one contemporary mode of philosophizing. I am not condemning this kind of manoeuvre. I am merely suggesting that to embark on it without due caution is to risk collision with the facts. Before we rush ahead to exploit the linguistic NUANCES which we have detected, we should make sure that we are reasonably clear what SORT of nuances they are! The modal example (What is actual is not also possible) discussed under Indicative conditonals, 1967. Grice on Macbeths implicature: seeing a dagger as a dagger. Grice elaborates on this in Prolegomena, but the austerity of Causal theory is charming, since he does not give a quote or source. OBVIOUSLY: Witters! Grice writes: Witters might say You cannot see a knife as a knife, though you may see what is not a knife as a knife. The issue, Grice notes, with which I have been mainly concerned may be thought rather a fine point, but it is certainly not an isolated one. There are several philosophical theses or dicta which would I think need to be examined in order to see whether or not they are sufficiently parallel to the thesis which I have been discussing to be amenable to treatment of the same general kind. An example which occurs to Grice is the following: You cannot see a knife as a knife, though you may see what is not a knife as a knife. Grice feels that he must emphasise that he is not saying that this example is importantly similar to the thesis which I have been criticizing, only that, for all I know, it may be. To put the matter more generally, the position adopted by my objector seems to me to involve a type of manoeuvre which is characteristic of more than one contemporary mode of philosophizing. I am not condemning this kind of manoeuvre. I am merely suggesting that to embark on it without due caution is to risk collision with the facts. Before we rush ahead to exploit the linguistic nuances which we have detected, we should make sure that we are reasonably clear what sort of nuances they are! Is this a dagger which I see before me, the handle toward my hand? Come, let me clutch thee. I have thee not, and yet I see thee still. Art thou not, fatal vision, sensible To feeling as to sight? or art thou but A dagger of the mind, a false creation, Proceeding from the heat-oppressed brain? I see thee yet, in form as palpable As this which now I draw. Thou marshallst me the way that I was going; And such an instrument I was to use. Mine eyes are made the fools o the other senses, Or else worth all the rest; I see thee still, And on thy blade and dudgeon gouts of blood, Which was not so before. Theres no such thing: It is the bloody business which informs Thus to mine eyes. Now oer the one halfworld Nature seems dead, and wicked dreams abuse The curtaind sleep; witchcraft celebrates Pale Hecates offerings, and witherd murder, Alarumd by his sentinel, the wolf, Whose howls his watch, thus with his stealthy pace. With Tarquins ravishing strides, towards his design Moves like a ghost. Thou sure and firm-set earth, Hear not my steps, which way they walk, for fear Thy very stones prate of my whereabout, And take the present horror from the time, Which now suits with it. Whiles I threat, he lives: Words to the heat of deeds too cold breath gives. [a bell rings] I go, and it is done; the bell invites me. Hear it not, Duncan; for it is a knell That summons thee to heaven or to hell. The Moore example is used both in Causal theory and Prolegomena. But the use in Causal Theory is more austere: Philosophers mistake: Malcolm: When Moore said he knew that the objects before him were human hands, he was guilty of misusing the word know. Grice writes: The issue with which I have been mainly concerned may be thought rather a fine point, but it is certainly not an isolated one. There are several philosophical theses or dicta which would I think need to be examined in order to see whether or not they are sufficiently parallel to the thesis which I have been discussing to be amenable to treatment of the same general kind. An example which occurs to me is the following: When Moore said he knew that the objects before him were human hands, he was guilty of misusing the word know. I must emphasise that I am not saying that this example is importantly similar to the thesis which I have been criticizing, only that, for all I know, it may be. To put the matter more generally, the position adopted by my objector seems to me to involve a type of manoeuvre which is characteristic of more than one contemporary mode of philosophizing. I am not condemning this kind of manoeuvre. Grice is merely suggesting that to embark on it without due caution is to risk collision with the facts. Before we rush ahead to exploit the linguistic nuances which we have detected, we should make sure that we are reasonably clear what sort of nuances they are! So surely Grice is meaning: I know that the objects before me are human hands as uttered by Moore is possibly true. Grice was amused by the fact that while at Madison, Wisc., Moore gave the example: I know that behind those curtains there is a window. Actually he was wrong, as he soon realised when the educated Madisonians corrected him with a roar of unanimous laughter. You see, the lecture hall of the University of Wisconsin at Madison is a rather, shall we say, striking space. The architect designed the lecture hall with a parapet running around the wall just below the ceiling, cleverly rigged with indirect lighting to create the illusion that sun light is pouring in through windows from outside. So, Moore comes to give a lecture one sunny day. Attracted as he was to this eccentric architectural detail, Moore gives an illustration of certainty as attached to common sense. Pointing to the space below the ceiling, Moore utters. We know more things than we think we know. I know, for example, that the sunlight shining in from outside proves At which point he was somewhat startled (in his reserved Irish-English sort of way) when his audience burst out laughing! Is that a proof of anything? Grice is especially concerned with I seem He needs a paradeigmatic sense-datum utterance, and intentionalist as he was, he finds it in I seem to see a red pillar box before me. He is relying on Paul. Grice would generalise a sense datum by φ I seem to perceive that the alpha is phi. He agrees that while cause may be too much, any sentence using because will do: At a circus: You seem to be seeing that an elephant is coming down the street because an elephant is coming down the street. Grice found the causalist theory of perception particularly attractive since its objection commits one same mistake twice: he mischaracterises the cancellable implicatum of both seem and cause! While Grice is approaching the philosophical item in the philosophical lexicon, perceptio, he is at this stage more interested in vernacular that- clauses such as sensing that, or even more vernacular ones like seeming that, if not seeing that! This is of course philosophical (cf. aesthetikos vs. noetikos), and L and S have perceptĭo, f. perceptio, as used by Cicero (Ac. 2, 7, 22) translating catalepsis,and which they render as a taking, receiving; a gathering in, collecting. Ambros. in Luc. 4, 15: frugum fruetuumque reliquorum, Cic. Off. 2, 3, 12: fructuum, Col. 1, 3, 2., also as perception, comprehension, cf.: notio, cognitio ): animi perceptiones, notions, ideas, Cic. Ac. 2, 7, 22: cognitio aut perceptio, aut si verbum e verbo volumus comprehensio, quam κατάληψιν illi vocant, id. ib. 2, 6, 17, in philosophy, direct apprehension of an object by the mind, Zeno Stoic.1.20, Luc. Par. 4, al.; τῶν μετεώρων Philostr. Her. 10.9; ἀκριβὴς κ. certainty, Herod. Med. ap. Aët. 9.37: pl., perceptions, Stoic.2.30, Luc. Herm.81, etc.; introduced into Latin by Cicero, Plu. Cic. 40. As for causa, he was even more sure he was exploring a time-honoured philosophical topic. The entry in L and S is causa (by Cicero, and also a little after him, caussa , Quint. 1, 7, 20; so Fast. Prænest. 321, 322; Inscr. Orell. 3681; 4077; 4698 al.; in Mon. Ancyr. 3, 1 dub.), which they judge to be perh. root cav- of caveo, prop. that which is defended or protected; cf. cura, and that they render as, unhelpfully, as cause, that by, on account of, or through which any thing takes place or is done; a cause, reason, motive, inducement; also, in gen., an occasion, opportunity (oeffectis, Quint. 6, 3, 66; 7, 3, 29: factis, id. 4, 2, 52; 12, 1, 36 al.; very freq. in all periods, and in all kinds of discourse. In its different usages syn. with ratio, principium, fons, origo, caput; excusatio, defensio; judicium, controversia, lis; partes, actio; condicio, negotium, commodum, al.). Correlated to aition, or aitia, cause, δι᾽ ἣν αἰτίην ἐπολέμησαν Hdt. Prooem., cf. Democr. 83, Pl. Ti. 68e, Phd. 97a sq., etc.; on the four causes of Arist. v. Ph. 194b16, Metaph. 983a26: αἰ. τοῦ γενέσθαι or γεγονέναι Pl. Phd. 97a; τοῦ μεγίστου ἀγαθοῦ τῇ πόλει αἰτία ἡ κοινωνία Id. R. 464b: αἰτίᾳ for the sake of, κοινοῦ τινος ἀγαθοῦ Th. 4.87, cf. D. H. 8.29: αἴτιον (cf. αἴτιος 11.2) is used like αἰτία in the sense of cause, not in that of accusation. Grice will go back to perception at a later stage, reminiscing on his joint endeavours with akin Warnock. 1972. Pirots karulise elatically, potching and cotching obbles, Pirotese, Pirotese, creature construction, philosophical psychology. Grice was fascinated by Carnaps pirots which karulise elatically. Grice adds potching for something like perceiving and cotching for something like cognising.
SENSE-DATUM: With his essay Some remarks about the senses, Grice
introduces the question by which criterion we distinguish our five senses into
the contemporary philosophy of perception. The literature concerning this
question is not very numerous but the discussion is still alive and was lately
inspired by the volume The Senses2. There are four acknowledged possible
answers to the question how we distinguish the senses, all of them already
stated by Grice: (1) The senses are distinguished by the properties we perceive
by them. (2) The senses are distinguished by the phenomenal qualities of the
perception itself or as Grice puts it “by the special introspectible character
of the experiences” 3. (3) The senses are distinguished by the physical stimuli
that are responsible for the relevant perceptions. (4) The senses are
distinguished by the sense-organs that are (causally) involved in the
production of the relevant perceptions. Most contributions discussing this
issue reject answers (3) and (4) in a very short argumentation. Nearly all
philosophers writing on the topic vote either for answer (1) or for answer (2).
Accordingly, most part of the debate regarding the initial question takes the
form of a dispute between these two positions. Or” was a big thing in
Oxford philosophy. The only known published work of Wood, our philosophy tutor
at Christ Church, was an essay in Mind, the philosophers journal, entitled
“Alternative Uses of “Or” ”, a work which was every bit as indeterminate as its
title. Several years later he published another paper, this time for the Aristotelian
Society, entitled On being forced to a conclusion. Cf. Grice and Wood on the
demands of conversational reason. Wood, The force of linguistic rules. Wood, on
the implicatum of or in review in Mind of Connor, Logic. The five senses, as
Urmson notes, are to see that the sun is shining, to hear that the car
collided, to feel that her pulse is beating, to smell that something has been
smoking and to taste that. An interesting piece in that it was commissioned by
Butler, who knew Grice from his Oxford days. Grice cites Wood and R. Albritton.
Grice is concerned with a special topic in the philosophy of perception,
notably the identification of the traditional five senses:
vision, audition, taste, smell, and tact. He introduces what is regarded
in the philosophical literature as the first thought-experiment, in terms of
the senses that Martians may have. They have two pairs of eyes: are we going to
allow that they see with both pairs? Grice introduces a sub-division of seeing:
a Martian x-s an object with his upper pair of eyes, but he y-s an object with
the lower pair of eyes. In his exploration, he takes a realist stance, which
respects the ordinary discursive ways to approach issues of perception. A
second interesting point is that in allowing this to be reprinted in Butlers
Analytic philosophy, Grice is demonstrating that analytic philosophers should
NOT be obsessed with ordinary language. Butlers compilation, a rather dry one,
is meant as a response to the more linguistic oriented ones by Flew (Grices first
tutee at St. Johns, as it happens), also published by Blackwell, and containing
pieces by Austin, and company. One philosopher who took Grice very seriously on
this was Coady, in his The senses of the Martians. Grice provides a serious
objection to his own essay in Retrospective epilogue We see with our eyes. I.e.
eye is teleologically defined. He notes that his way of distinguishing the
senses is hardly an established thesis. Grice actually advances this topic in
his earlier Causal theory. Grice sees nothing absurd in the idea that a
non-specialist concept should contain, so to speak, a blank space to be filled
in by the specialist; that this is so, e.g., in the case of the concept of
seeing is perhaps indicated by the consideration that if we were in doubt about
the correctness of speaking of a certain creature with peculiar sense-organs as
seeing objects, we might well wish to hear from a specialist a comparative
account of the human eye and the relevant sense-organs of the creature in
question. He returns to the point in Retrospective epilogue with a bit of
doxastic humility, We see with our eyes is analytic ‒ but
philosophers should take that more seriously. Grice tested the
playmates of his children, aged 7 and 9, with Nothing can be green
and red all over. Instead, Morley Bunker preferred
philosophy undergrads. Aint that boring? To give examples:
Summer follows Spring was judged analytic by Morley-Bunkers informants, as
cited by Sampson, in Making sense (Clarendon) by highly significant majorities
in each group of Subjectss, while We see with our eyes was given near-even
split votes by each group. Over all, the philosophers were somewhat more
consistent with each other than the non-philosophers. But that global finding
conceals results for individual sentences that sometimes manifested the
opposed tendency. Thus, Thunderstorms are electrical disturbances in the
atmosphere is judged analytic by a highly significant majority of the
non-philosophers, while a non-significant majority of the philosophers deemed
it non-analytic or synthetic. In this case, it seems, philosophical training,
surely not brain-washing, induces the realisation that well-established results
of contemporary science are not necessary truths. In other cases, conversely,
cliches of current philosophical education impose their own mental blinkers on
those who undergo it: Nothing can be completely red and green all over is
judged analytic by a significant majority of philosophers but only by a
non-significant majority of non-philosophers. All in all, the results argue
strongly against the notion that our inability to decide consistently whether
or not some statement is a necessary truth derives from lack of skill in
articulating our underlying knowledge of the rules of our language. Rather, the
inability comes from the fact that the question as posed is unreal. We choose
to treat a given statement as open to question or as unchallengeable in the
light of the overall structure of beliefs which we have individually
evolved in order to make sense of our individual experience. Even the cases
which seem clearly analytic or synthetic are cases which individuals judge
alike because the relevant experiences are shared by the whole community, but
even for such cases one can invent hypothetical or suppositional future
experiences which, if they should be realised, would cause us to revise our
judgements. This is not intended to call into question the special status of
the truths of logic, such as either Either it is raining or it is not. He
is of course inclined to accept the traditional view according to which logical
particles such as not and or are distinct from the bulk of the vocabulary in
that the former really are governed by clear-cut inference rules. Grice
does expand on the point.
Grice at Cornell, the
Cornell Seminar, Grices Seminar at Cornell, 1966, The Grice Papers, s. III , c. 5-f. 1, . : philosophy of
action, Thomson Historically important in that they predate his Harvard James
lectures which made of him a household Names in New-World philosophy. Harman
cites a seminar by Grice on trying at Brandeis, 1962.
Grices three lectures on
trying at Brandeis. Cf. his later remarks on trying (to cash a cheque) in
Prolegomena at Harvard.
IMPLICATURE: Those
without a philosophical background tend to ignore a joke by Grice! His echoing
Kant in the James is a joke, in the sense that he is using Katns well-known to
be pretty artificial quartet of ontological caegories to apply to a totally
different phenomenon: the taxonomy of the maxims! In his earlier non-jocular
attempts, he applied more philosophical concepts with a more serious rationale.
His key concept, conversation as rational co-operation, underlies all his
attempts. A pretty worked-out model is in terms then of this central, or
overarching principle of conversational helpfulness (where conversation as cooperation
need not be qualified as conversation as RATIONAL co-operation) and being
structured by two contrasting sub-principles: the principle of conversational
benevolence (which almost overlaps with the principle of conversational
helpfulness) and the slightly more jocular principle of conversational
self-love. There is something oxymoronic about self-love being conversational,
and this is what leads to replace the two subprinciples by a principle of
conversational helfpulness (as used in WoW:IV) simpliciter. His desideratum of
conversational candour is key. The clash between the desideratum of
conversational candour and the desideratum of conversational clarity (call them
supermaxims) explains why I believe that p (less clear than p) shows the
primacy of candour over clarity. The idea remains of an overarching principle
and a set of more specific guidelines. Non-Oxonian philosophers would see
Grices appeal to this or that guideline as ad hoc, but not his tutees! Grice
finds inspiration in Joseph Butler’s sermon on benevolence and self-love. Sermon
9, Upon the love of our neighbour, preached on advent Sunday. And if there be
any other commandment, it is briefly comprehended in this saying, Namesly, Thou
shalt love thy neighbour as thyself.—Romans xiii. 9. It is commonly
observed, that there is a disposition in men to complain of the viciousness and
corruption of the age in which they live, as greater than that of former ones:
which is usually followed with this further observation, that mankind has been
in that respect much the same in all times. Now, to determine whether this last
be not contradicted by the accounts of history: thus much can scarce be
doubted, that vice and folly takes different turns, and some particular kinds
of it are more open and avowed in some ages than in others; and, I suppose, it
may be spoken of as very much the distinction of the present, to profess a
contracted spirit, and greater regards to self-interest, than appears to have
been done formerly. Upon this account it seems worth while to inquire, whether
private interest is likely to be promoted in proportion to the degree in which
self-love engrosses us, and prevails over all other principles; "or
whether the contracted affection may not possibly be so prevalent as to disappoint
itself, and even contradict its own end, private good?" Reprinted in
revised form as Part I of WOW . Grice felt the need to go back to his
explantion (cf. Fisher, Never contradict. Never explain) of the nuances about
seem and cause (Causal theory of perception.). He had used Smiths My wife is in
the kitchen or the bedroom as relying on a requirement of discourse. But there
must be more to it. Variations on a theme by Grice. Make your contribution such
as is required, at the stage at which it occurs, by the accepted purpose or
direction of the talk exchange in which you are engaged. Variations on a
theme by Grice. I wish to represent a certain subclass of non-conventional
implicaturcs, which I shall call conversational implicaturcs, as being
essentially connected with certain general features of discourse; so my next
step is to try to say what these features are. The following may provide a
first approximation to a general principle. Our talk exchanges do not normally
consist of a succession of disconnected remarks, and would not be rational if
they did. They are characteristically, to some degree at least, cooperative
efforts; and each participant recognizes in them, to some extent, a common
purpose or set of purposes, or at least a mutually accepted direction. This
purpose or direction may be fixed from the start (e.g., by an initial proposal
of a question for discussion), or it may evolve during the exchange; it may be
fairly definite, or it may be so indefinite as to leave very considerable
latitude to the participants, as in a casual conversation. But at each stage,
some possible conversational moves would be excluded as conversationally
unsuitable. We might then formulate a rough general principle which
participants will be expected ceteris paribus to observe, viz.: Make your
conversational contribution such as is required, at the stage at which it
occurs, by the accepted purpose or direction of the talk exchange in which you
are engaged. One might label this the co-operative principle. We might then
formulate a rough general principle which participants will be expected ceteris paribus to observe, viz.: Make your
contribution such as is required, at the stage at which it occurs, by the
accepted purpose or direction of the talk exchange in which you are engaged. One
might label this the Cooperative Principle. Strictly, the principle itself is
not co-operative: conversants are. Less literary variant: Make your
move such as is required by the accepted goal of the conversation in which you
are engaged. But why logic and conversation? Logica had been part of the
trivium for ages ‒ Although they called it dialectica, then. Grice on the
seven liberal arts. Moved by Strawsons treatment of the formal devices in
Introduction to Logical Theory, Grice targets these, in their
ordinary-discourse counterparts. Strawson indeed characterizes Grice as his
logic tutor – Strawson was following a P. P. E., and his approach to logic was
practical. His philosophy tutor was Mabbott. For Grice, with a M. A. Lit.
Hum.the situation was different. He knew that the Categoriae and De Int. of his beloved Aristotle were part of the
Logical Organon which had been so influential in the history of
philosophy. Grice attempts to reconcile Strawsons observations with the
idea that the formal devices reproduce some sort of explicatum, or explicitum,
as identified by Whitehead and Russell in Principia Mathematica. In the
proceedings, Grice has to rely on some general features of discourse, or
conversation as a rational co-operation. The alleged divergence between
the ordinary-language operators and their formal counterparts is explained in
terms of the conversational implicata, then. I.e. the content of the
psychological attitude that the addressee A has to ascribe to the utterer U to
account for any divergence between the formal device and its alleged
ordinary-language counterpart, while still assuming that U is engaged in a
co-operative transaction. The utterer and his addressee are seen as
caring for the mutual goals of conversation ‒ the exchange of
information and the institution of decisions ‒ and judging that
conversation will only be profitable (and thus reasonable and rational) if
conducted under some form of principle of conversational helpfulness. The
observation of a principle of conversational helpfulness is
reasonable (rational) along the following lines: anyone who cares
about the goals that are central to conversation/communication (such as giving
and receiving information, influencing and being influenced by others) must be expected
to have an interest, given suitable circumstances, in participating in a
conversation that will be profitable ONLY on the assumption that it is
conducted in general accordance with a principle of conversational
helpfulness. In titling his seminar Logic and conversation, Grice is
thinking Strawson. After all, in the seminal Introduction to logical theory,
that every Oxonian student was reading, Strawson had the cheek to admit that he
never ceased to learn logic from his tutor, Grice. Yet he elaborates a totally
anti Griceian view of things. To be fair to Strawson, the only segment where he
acknwoledges Grices difference of opinion is a brief footnote, concerning the
strength or lack thereof, of this or that quantified utterance. Strawson uses
an adjective that Grice will seldom do, pragmatic. On top, Strawson attributes
the adjective to rule. For Grice, in Strawsons wording, there is this or that
pragmatic rule to the effect that one should make a stronger rather than a
weaker conversational move. Strawsons Introduction was published before Grice
aired his views for the Aristotelian Society. In this seminar then Grice takes
the opportunity to correct a few misunderstandings. Important in that it
is Grices occasion to introduce the principle of conversational helpfulness as
generating implicata under the assumption of rationality. The lecture makes it
obvious that Grices interest is methodological, and not philological. He is not
interest in conversation per se, but only as the source for his principle of
conversational helpfulness and the notion of the conversational implicatum,
which springs from the distinction between what an utterer implies and what his
expression does, a distinction apparently denied by Witters and all too
frequently ignored by Austin. Logic and conversation, an Oxford seminar,
1964, implicatum, principle of conversational helpfulness, eywords:
conversational implicature, conversational implicatum. Conversational
Implicature Grices main invention, one which trades on the distinction
between what an utterer implies and what his expression does. A
distinction apparently denied by Witters, and all too frequently ignored by, of
all people, Austin. Grice is implicating that Austins sympathies were for
the Subjectsification of Linguistic Nature. Grice remains an obdurate
individualist, and never loses sight of the distinction that gives rise to the
conversational implicatum, which can very well be hyper-contextualised,
idiosyncratic, and perfectly particularized. His gives an Oxonian example. I
can very well mean that my tutee is to bring me a philosophical essay next week
by uttering It is raining.Grice notes that since the object of the present
exercise, is to provide a bit of theory which will explain, for a
certain family of cases, why is it that a particular
implicature is present, I would suggest that the final test of
the adequacy and utility of this model should be: can it be used to construct
an explanation of the presence of such an implicature, and is it more
comprehensive and more economical than any rival? is the no
doubt pre-theoretical explanation which one would be prompted to give
of such an implicature consistent with, or better still a favourable pointer
towards the requirements involved in the model? cf. Sidonius: Far otherwise:
whoever disputes with you will find those protagonists of heresy, the Stoics,
Cynics, and Peripatetics, shattered with their own arms and their
own engines; for their heathen followers, if they resist the doctrine and
spirit of Christianity, will, under your teaching, be caught in their own
familiar entanglements, and fall headlong into their own toils; the barbed
syllogism of your arguments will hook the glib tongues of the
casuists, and it is you who will tie up their slippery
questions in categorical clews, after the manner of a clever
physician, who, when compelled by reasoned thought, prepares antidotes for
poison even from a serpent.qvin potivs experietvr qvisqve conflixerit stoicos
cynicos peripateticos hæresiarchas propriis armis propriis qvoqve concvti machiNamesntis
nam sectatores eorum Christiano dogmati ac sensvi si repvgnaverint mox te
magistro ligati vernaculis implicaturis in retia sua præcipites
implagabvntur syllogismis tuæ propositionis vncatis volvbilem tergiversantvm
lingvam inhamantibvs dum spiris categoricis lubricas qvæstiones tv potivs
innodas acrivm more medicorvm qui remedivm contra venena cum ratio compellit et
de serpente conficivnt. If he lectured on Logic and Conversation on
implicature, Grice must have thought that Strawsons area was central. Yet, as
he had done in Causal theory and as he will at Harvard, Grice kept collecting
philosophers mistakes. So its best to see Grice as a methodologist, and as
using logic and conversation as an illustration of his favourite manoeuvre,
indeed, central philosophical manoeuver that gave him a place in the history of
philosophy. Restricting this manoeuvre to just an area minimises it. On the
other hand, there has to be a balance: surely logic and conversation is a topic
of intrinsic interest, and we cannot expect all philosophers – unless they are
Griceians! – to keep a broad unitarian view of philosophy
as avirtuous whole! Philosophy, like virtue, is entire. Destructive
implicature to it: Mr. Puddle is our man in æsthetics implicates he is not good
at it. What is important to Grice is that the mistakes of these philosophers
(notably Strawson!) arise from some linguistic phenomena,or, since we must use
singular expressions this or that linguistic phenomenon. Or as Grice puts it,
it is this or that linguistic phenomenon which provides the material for the
philosopher to make his mistake! So, to solve it, his theory of conversation as
rational co-operation is posited – technically, as a way to explain (never
merely describe, which Grice found boring ‒ if English, cf. never explain,
never apologise ‒ Jacky Fisher: Never contradict. Never explain.) these phenomena
– his principle of conversational helpfulness and the idea of a conversational
implicatum. The latter is based not so much on rationality per se, but on the
implicit-explicit distinction that he constantly plays with, since his earlier
semiotic-oriented explorations of Peirce. But back to this or that linguistic
phenomenon, while he would make fun of Searle for providing this or that
linguistic phenomenon that no philosopher would ever feel excited about, Grice
himself was a bit of a master in illustrating this a philosophical point with
this or that linguistic phenomenon that would not be necessarily connected with
philosophy. He rarely quotes authors, but surely the section in Causal theory
where he lists seven philosophical theses (which are ripe for an
implicatum treatment) would be familiar enough for anybody to be able to drop a
Names to attach to each! At Harvard, almost every example Grice gives of this
or that linguistic phenomenon is UN-authored (and sometimes he expands on his
own view of them, just to amuse his audience – and show how committed to this
or that thesis he was), but some are not unauthored. And they all belong to the
linguistic turn: He quotes from Ryle (who thought he knew about ordinary
language), Wittgenstein, Austin (he quotes him in great detail, from
Pretending, Plea of excuses, and No modification without aberration,), Strawson
(in Introduction to Logical theory and on Truth for Analysis), Hart (as I have
heard him expand on this), Searle, and Benjamin . He implicates Hare (on good).
Etc. When we mention the explicit/implicit distinction as source for the
implicatum, we are referring to Grices own wording in Retrospective epilogue
where he mentions an utterer as conveying in some explicit fashion this or
that, as opposed to a gentler, more (midland or southern) English, way, via
implicature, or implIciture, if you mustnt. Cf. Fowler: As a southern
Englishman, Ive stopped trying teaching a northern Englishman the distinction
between ought and shall. He seems to get it always wrong. It may be worth
exploring how this connects with rationality. His point would be that that an
assumption that the rational principle of conversational helpfulness is in
order allows Pirot-1 not just to convey in a direct explicit fashion that p, but
in an implicit fashion that q, where q is the implicatum. The principle of
conversational helpfulness as generator of this or that implicata, to use
Grices word (generate). Surely, He took off his boots and went to bed; I wont
say in which order sounds hardly in the vein of conversational helpfulness –
but provided Grice does not see it as logically incoherent, it is still a
rational (if not reasonable) thing to say. The point may be difficult to
discern, but you never know. The utterer may be conveying, Viva Boole! Grices
point about rationality is mentioned in his later Prolegomena, on at least two
occasions. Rational behaviour is the phrase he uses (as applied first to
communication and then to discourse) and in stark opposition with a
convention-based approach he rightly associates with Austin. Grice is here less
interested here as he will be on rationality, but coooperation as such.
Helpfulness as a reasonable expecation (normative?), a mutual one between
decent chaps, as he puts it. His charming decent chap is so Oxonian. His tutee
would expect no less ‒ and indeed no more!
UNCERTAINTY: In the end,
its all about the converational implciata and conversation as rational
co-operation. Why does Pirot 2 should judge that Pirot 1 is being more or less
certain about what he is talking? Theres a rationale for that! Our conversation
does not consist of idle remarks. Grices example: "The Chairman of the
British Academy has a corkscrew in his pocket. Urmsons example: "The king
is visiting Oxford tomorrow. Why? Oh, for no reason at all As a
philosophical psychologist, and an empiricist with realist tendencies, Grice
was obsessed with what he called (in a nod to the Kiparskys) the factivity of
know. Surely, Grices preferred collocation, unlike surely Ryles, is "Grice
knows that p." Grice has no problem in seeing this as involving three
clauses: First, p. Second, Grice believes that p, and third, p causes Grices
belief. No mention of certainty. This is the neo-Prichardian in Grice, from
having been a neo-Stoutian (Stout was obsessed, as a few Oxonians like
Hampshire and Hart were, with certainty). If the three-prong analysis of know
applies to the doxastic, Grices two-prong analysis of intending in Intention
and UNcertainty, again purposively avoiding certainty, covers the buletic
realm. This does not mean that Grice, however proud he was of his ignorance of
the history of philosophy (He held it as a badge of honour, his tuteee Strawson
recalls), had read some of the philosophical classics to realise that certainty
had been an obsession of what Ryle abusively (as he himself puts it) called
Descartes and the Establishments "official doctrine"! While ps true
in Grices analysis of know is harmless enough, there obviously is no correlate
for ps truth in the buletic case. Grices example is Grice intending to scratch
his head, via his willing that Grice scratches his head in t2. In this case, as
he notes, the doxastic eleent involves the uniformity of nature, and ones more
or less relying that if Grice had a head to be scratched in t1, he will have a
head to be sratched in t2, when his intention actually GETS satisfied, or
fulfilled. Grice was never worried about buletic satisfaction. As the
intentionalist that Suppes showed us Grice was, Grice is very much happy to say
that if Smith intends to give Joness a job, the facct as to whether Jones
actually gets the job is totally irrelevant for most philosophical purposes. He
gets more serious when he is happier with privileged access than
incorrigibility in "Method in philosophical psychology." But he is
less strict than Austin. For Austin, "Thats a finch implies that the
utterer KNOWS its a finch. While Grice has a maxim, do not say that for which
you lack adequate evidence (Gettiers analysandum) and a super-maxim, try
to make your contribution one that is true, the very phrasing highlights
Grices cavalier to this! Imagine Kant turning on his grave. "Try!?".
Grice is very clever in having try in the super-maxim, and a prohibition as the
maxim, involving falsehood avoidance, "Do not say what you believe to be
false." Even here he is cavalier. "Cf. "Do not say what you KNOW
to be false." If Gettier were wrong, the combo of maxims yields, "Say
what you KNOW," say what you are certain about! Enough for Sextus Empiricus
having one single maxim: "Either utter a phenomenalist utterance, a
question or an order, or keep your mouth shut!." (cf. Grice, "My lips
are sealed," as cooperative or helfpul in ways -- "At least he is not
lying."). Hampshire, in the course of some recent remarks,l advances
the view that self-prediction is (logically) impossible. When I say I know that
I shall do X (as against, e.g., X will happen to me, or You will do X), I am
not contemplating myself, as I might someone else, and giving tongue to a
conjecture about myself and my future acts, as I might be doing about someone
else or about the behaviour ofan animal -for that would be tantamount (if I
understand him rightly) to looking upon myself from outside, as it were, and
treating my own acts as mere caused events. In saying that I know that I shall
do X, I am, on this view, saying that I have decided to do X: for to predict
that I shall in certain circumstances in fact do X or decide to do X, with no
reference to whether or not I have already decided to do it - to say I can tell
you now that I shall in fact act in manner X, although I am, as a matter of
fact, determined to do the very opposite - does not make sense. Any man who
says I know myself too well to believe that, whatever I now decide, I shall do
anything other than X when the circumstances actually arise is in fact, if I
interpret Hampshires views correctly, saying that he does not really, i.e.
seriously, propose to set himself against doing X, that he does not propose
even to try to act otherwise, that he has in fact decided to let events take
their course. For no man who has truly decided to try to avoid X can, in good
faith, predict his own failure to act as he has decided. He may fail to avoid
X, and he may predict this; but he cannot both decide to try to avoid X and
predict that he will not even try to do this; for he can always try; and he
knows this: he knows that this is what distinguishes him from non-human
creatures in nature. To say that he will fail even to try is tantamount to
saying that he has decided not to try. In this sense I know means I have
decided and (Murdoch, Hampshire, Gardiner and Pears, Freedom and Knowledge, in Pears
(ed.), Freedom and tAe Will (London,), 80-104) cannot in principle be
predictive. That, if I have understood it, is Hampshires position, and I have a
good deal of sympathy with it, for I can see that self-prediction is often an
evasive way of disclaiming responsibility for difficult decisions, while
deciding in fact to let events take their course, disguising this by attributing
responsibility for what occurs to my own allegedly unalterable nature. But I
agree with Hampshires critics in the debate, whom I take to be maintaining
that, although the situation he describes may often occur, yet circumstances
may exist in which it is possible for me both to say that I am, at this moment,
resolved not to do X, and at the same time to predict that I shall do X,
because I am not hopeful that, when the time comes, I shall in fact even so
much as try to resist doing X. I can, in effect, say I know myself well. When
the crisis comes, do not rely on me to help you. I may well run away; although
I am at this moment genuinely resolved not to be cowardly and to do all I can
to stay at your side. My prediction that my resolution will not in fact hold up
is based on knowledge of my own character, and not on my present state of mind;
my prophecy is not a symptom of bad faith (for I am not, at this moment,
vacillating) but, on the contrary, of good faith, of a wish to face the facts.
I assure you in all sincerity that my present intention is to be brave and
resist. Yet you would run a great risk if you relied too much on my present
decision; it would not be fair to conceal my past failures of nerve from you. I
can say this about others, despite the most sincere resolutions on their part,
for I can foretell how in fact they will behave; they can equally predict this
about me. Despite Hampshires plausible and tempting argument, I believe that
such objective self-knowledge is possible and occur. From Descartes to
Stout and back. Stout indeed uses both intention and certainty, and in the
same paragraph. Stout notes that, at the outset, performance falls far short of
intention. Only a certain s. of contractions of certain muscles, in proper
proportions and in a proper order, is capable of realising the end aimed at,
with the maximum of rapidity and certainty, and the minimum of obstruction and
failure, and corresponding effort. At the outset of the process of acquisition,
muscles are contracted which are superfluous, and which therefore operate as
disturbing conditions. Grices immediate trigger, however, is Ayer on sure
that, and having the right to be sure, as his immediate trigger later will be
Hampshire and Hart. Grice had high regard for Hampshires brilliant Thought and
action. He was also concerned with Stouts rather hasty UNphilosophical,
but more scientifically psychologically-oriented remarks about assurance in
practical concerns. He knew too that he was exploring an item of the
philosophers lexicon (certus) that had been brought to the forum when Anscombe
and von Wright translate Witters German expression Gewißheit in Über
Gewißheit as Certainty. The Grecians were never sure about being sure. But
the modernist turn brought by Descartes meant that Grice now had to deal with
incorrigibility and privileged access to this or that pirot, notably himself
(When I intend to go, I dont have to observe myself, Im on the stage, not in
the audience, or Only I can say I will to London, expressing my intention to do
so. If you say, You will go you are expressing yours! Grice found
Descartes very funny ‒ in a French way. Grice is interested in contesting Ayer
and other Oxford philosophers, on the topic of a criterion for
certainty. In so doing, Grice choses Descartess time-honoured criterion of
clarity and distinction, as applied to perception. Grice does NOT
quote Descartes in French! In the proceedings, Grice distinguishes between
two kinds of certainty apparently ignored by Descartes: (a) objective
certainty: Ordinary-language variant: It is certain that p, whatever
it refers to. cf. Grice, its an illusion. What is it? (b) Subjectsive
certainty: Ordinary-language variant: I am certain that p. I
being, of course, Grice, in my bestest days, of course! There are further
items on Descartes in the Grice Collection, notably in the last s. of topics
arranged alphabetically. Grice never cared to publish his views on
Descartes until he found an opportunity to do so when compiling his WOW . Grice
is not interested in an exegesis of Descartess thought. He doesnt care to give
a reference to any edition of Descartess oeuvre. But he plays with certain. It
is certain that p is objective certainty, apparently. I am certain that p is Subjectsive
certainty, rather. Oddly, Grice will turn to UNcertainty as it connects with
intention in his British Academy lecture. Grices interest in Descartes
connects with Descartess search for a criterion of certainty in terms of
clarity and distinction of this or that perception. Having explored the
philosophy of perception with Warnock, its only natural he wanted to give
Descartess rambles a second and third look! 1966, Descartes on clear and
distinct perception, in WOW , part 2, eemantics and metaphysics, essay,
Descartes on clear and distinct perception and Malcom on dreaming, perception,
Descartes, clear and distinct perception, Malcolm, dreaming. Descartes
meets Malcolm, and vice versa. Descartes on clear and distinct
perception, in WOW , Descartes on clear and distinct perception,
1966, Descartes on clear and distinct perception, in WOW , part II, semantics
and metaphysics, essay. Grice gives a short overview of Cartesian metaphysics
for the BBC third programme. The best example, Grice thinks, of
a metaphysical snob is provided by Descartes, about whose idea of
certainty Grice had philosophised quite a bit, since its in total contrast with
Moores! Descartes is a very scientifically
minded philosopher, with very clear ideas about the proper direction for science. Descartes,
whose middle Names seems to have been Euclid, thinks that mathematics, and in
particular geometry, provides the model for a scientific procedure, or
method. And this determines all of Descartess thinking in two ways.
First, Descartes thinks that the fundamental method in science is the axiomatic
deductive method of geometry, and this Descartes conceives (as Spinoza morality
more geometrico) of as rigorous reasoning from a self-evident axiom (Cogito,
ergo sum.). Second, Descartes thinks that the Subjects matter of physical
science, from mechanics to medicine, must be fundamentally the same as the Subjects
matter of geometry! The only characteristics that the objects studied by
geometry poses are spatial characteristics. So from the point of view of
science in general, the only important features of things in the physical world
were also their spatial characteristics, what he called extensio, res extensa.
Physical science in general is a kind of dynamic, or kinetic, geometry.
Here we have an exclusive preference for a certain type of scientific
method, and a certain type of scientific explanation: the method is deductive,
the type of explanation mechanical. These beliefs about the right way to do
science are exactly reflected in Descartess ontology, one of the two branches
of metaphysics; the other is philosophical eschatology, or the study of
categories), and it is reflected in his doctrine, that is, about what really
exists. Apart from God, the divine substance, Descartes recognises just
two kinds of substance, two types of real entity. First, there is material
substance, or matter; and the belief that the only scientifically important
characteristics of things in the physical world are their spatial
characteristics goes over, in the language of metaphysics,into the doctrine
that these are their only characteristics. Second, and to Ryles horror,
Descartes recognizes the mind or soul, or the mental substance, of which the
essential characteristic is thinking; and thinking itself, in its pure form at
least, is conceived of as simply the intuitive grasping of this or
that self-evident axiom and this or that of its deductive consequence. These
restrictive doctrines about reality and knowledge naturally call for
adjustments elsewhere in our ordinary scheme of things. With the help of the
divine substance, these are duly provided. It is not always obvious that
the metaphysicians scheme involves this kind of ontological preference, or
favoritism, or prejudice, or snobbery this tendency, that is, to promote one or
two categories of entity to the rank of the real, or of the ultimately real, to
the exclusion of others, Descartess entia realissima. One is taught at Oxford
that epistemology begins with the Moderns such as Descartes, which is not true.
Grice was concerned with certain, which was applied in Old Roman times to this
or that utterer: the person who is made certain in reference to a thing,
certain, sure: certi sumus periisse omnia, Cic. Att. 2, 19, 5: num quid
nunc es certior? Plaut. Am. 1, 1, 191: posteritatis, i. e. of posthumous fame,
Plin. Ep. 9, 3, 1: sententiæ, Quint. 4, 3, 8: judicii, Sen. Ep. 45, 9: certus
de suā geniturā, Suet. Vesp. 25: damnationis, id. Tib. 61: exitii, Tac. A. 1,
27: spei, id. H. 4, 3: matrimonii, id. A. 12, 3: certi sumus, etc., Gell. 18,
10, 5. In class. prose mostly in the phrase certiorem facere aliquem (de aliquā
re, alicujus rei, with a foll, acc. and inf., with a rel.-clause or absol.), to
inform, apprise one of a thing: me certiorem face, Ter. Phorm. 4, 3, 69: ut nos
facias certiores, Plaut. Curc. 5, 2, 32: uti se (sc. Cæsarem) de his rebus
certiorem faciant, Cæs. B. G. 2, 2: qui certiorem me sui consilii fecit, Cic.
Att. 9, 2, a, 2: Cæsarem certiorem faciunt, sese non facile ab oppidis vim
hostium prohibere, Cæs. B. G. 1, 11: faciam te certiorem quid egerim, Cic. Att.
3, 11, 1. With subj. only: milites certiores facit, paulisper intermitterent
proelium, Cæs. B. G. 3, 5 fin. Pass.: quod crebro certior per me fias de
omnibus rebus, Cic. Fam. 1, 7, 1; so Cæs. B. G. 1, 7; Sall. J. 104, 1: Cæsar
certior factus est, tres jam copiarum partes Helvetios id flumen transduxisse,
Cæs. B. G. 1, 12; so id. ib. 1, 21; 1, 41; 2, 1; Sall. J. 82, 2; Nep. Att. 12,
3: factus certior, quæ res gererentur, Cæs. B. C. 1, 15: non consulibus
certioribus factis, Liv. 45, 21, 4. Also in posit., though rarely: fac me
certum quid tibi est, Plaut. Ps. 1, 1, 16; 4, 6, 35; Verg. A. 3, 179: lacrimæ
suorum Tam subitæ matrem certam fecere ruinæ, Ov. M. 6, 268.
EUDAIMONISM:
While Grice claims to love Kantotle, he cannot hide his greater reverence,
instilled early on at Corpus, for Aristotle. An Oxonian need not recite Kant in
what during the Second World War was referred to as the Hun, and while
Aristotle was a no-no at Clifton (koine!), Hardie made Grice loved him. With
eudaemonia, found a perfect synthetic concept to balance his innate analytic
tendencies. Grecian eudaemonism and Griceian eudaemonism. L and S are not too
helpful. Theres εὐδαιμονία , Ion. -ιη, which they render not as happiness, but
as prosperity, good fortune, opulence, h.Hom. 11.5, Pi. N.7.56, Hdt.1.5,32,
Hp.Ep.11 (v.l.), etc.; χρημάτων προσόδῳ καὶ τῇ ἄλλῃ εὐ. Th.2.97; of countries,
Hdt.5.28, 7.220, etc.; “μοῖρ᾽ εὐδαιμονίας” Pi.P.3.84: pl., E.IA591 (anap.),
Pl.Phd.115d. In a second use it is indeed rendered as true, full
happiness, “εὐ. οὐκ ἐν βοσκήμασιν οἰκεῖ οὐδ᾽ ἐν χρυσῷ” Democr.171; εὐ. ψυχῆς,
oκακοδαιμονίη, Id.170, cf. Pl. Def. 412d, Arist. EN1095a18, Zeno Stoic.1.46,
etc. b. personified as a divinity, SIG985.8 (Philadelphia). Theres eudaemonia
and theres kakodaemonia. Of course, Grices locus classicus is
EN1095a18. Grice H. P. Grices fairy godmother. Cf. Austin on agathon and
eudaimonia in Aristotles ethics. Agathon and Eudaimonia in the Ethics of
Aristotle is Austins response to an article on the meaning of Agathon in the
Ethics of Aristotle, published by H. A. Pritchard in 1935. Pritchard argues
that Aristotle regarded agathon to mean conducive to eudaimonia and,
consequently, that Aristotle maintains that every deliberate action stems,
ultimately, from the desire for eudaemonia. Austin finds fault with this view:
first, agathon in Aristotle does not have a single sense, and a fortiori not
the one Pritchard suggests. Secondly, if one had to summarise the SENSE of
agathon in one phrase, being desired cannot fulfil this function, for there are
other objects of desire besides τό άγαθόν, even if Davidson would disagree.
Revisiting Prichards essay of "Philosophy" may help. Prichard
endeavours to specify what Aristotle means by αγαθον. In some contexts, it
seems to mean simply that being desired or a persons ultimate or non‐ultimate
end or aim. In other contexts, αγαθον takes on a normative quality. For his
statements to have content, argues Prichard, Aristotle must hold that when we
pursue something of a certain kind, such as an honour, we pursue it as a good.
Prichard argues that by "αγαθον" Aristotle actually means (except in
the Nicomachean Ethics) conducive to happiness, and holds that when a man acts
deliberately, he does it from a desire to be happy. Prichard attributes this
position to Plato as well, despite the fact that both thinkers make statements
inconsistent with this view of our ultimate aim. Grice took life seriously:
philosophical biology! Philosophy of life is dated 1966 in P. G. R. I. C. E.
Grice bases his thought on Ackrills Dawes Hicks essay for the B. A. who quotes
extensively from Hardie. Grice also considers that serious student of Greek
philosophy, JAustin, in his essay on
eudaimonia in Aristotle. Grices fairy godmother. Much the most plausible
conjecture regarding what Greek eudaimonia means, is Namesly that eudaimonia is
to be understood as the Names for that state or condition which ones good dæmon
would, if he could, ensure for one. And my good dæmon is a being motivated,
with respect to me, solely by concern for my well-being or happiness. To change
the idiom, eudæmonia is the general characterization of what a full-time and
unhampered fairy godmother would secure for you. Grice is concerned with the
specific system of ends that eudaimonia consists for for both Kant and
Aristotle (or Kantotle for short). Grice borrows, but never returns, some
reflections by his fomer tuttee at St. Johns, Ackrill. Ackrills point is about
the etymological basis for eudaimonia, from eudaimon, or good dæmon, as Grice
prefers. Grice thinks the metaphor should be disimplicated, and taken quite
literally. Grice concludes with a set of ends that justify our ascription of
eudaemonia to the agent. For Grice, as for Aristotle, and indeed Kant
(Kantotle, in short), a telos and eudaemonia are related in subtle ways. For
eudaemonia we cannot deal with just ONE end, but a system of ends (Although
such a system may be a singleton). Grice specifies a subtle way of
characterising end so that a particular ascription of an end may entail an
ascription of eudaemonia. Grice follows the textual criticism of his former
tutee, Ackrill, in connection with the Socratic point that eudaemonia IS
literally related to the eudaemon. Warner has explored Grices concept of
happiness, notably in P. G. R. I. C. E. Warner was especially helpful with
Grices third difficult Carus lecture, a metaphysical defence of absolute value.
Warner also connected with Grice in such topics as the philosophy of perception
(seen in an evolutionary light) and the Kantotelian idea of happiness. In
response to Warners overview of Grices oeuvre for the festschrift (that Warner
co-authored with Grandy), Grice refers to the editors by the collective Names
of Richards. While Grice felt he had to use happiness, he is always having
Aristotles eudaimonia in mind! The implicata of Smith is happy are more complex
than Kantotle thought! Austen knew! (You decide if youre happy! — Emma).
Ultimately, for Grice, the rational life is the happy life! Grice took life
seriously: philosophical biology! Grice is clear when reprinting the Descartes
paper in Studies (where he does quote from Descartes sources quite a bit, even
if he implicates he is no Cartesian scholar – what Oxonian would? ‒:
it concerns certainty. And certainty was originally Cantabrigian (Moore), but
also Oxonian, in parts. Ayer was saying that to know is to assure that one is
certain or sure. So he could connect. Grice will at various stages of his development
play and explore this authoritative voice of introspection: incorrigibility and
privileged access. He surely wants to say that a declaration of an intention is
authoritative. And he plays with meaning, too when provoking Malcolm in a don
recollection: Grice: I want you to bring me a paper tomorrow. Strawson: You
mean a newspaper? Grice: No, a philosophical essay. Strawson: How do you know?
Are you certain you mean that? Grice finds not being certain about what one
means Strawsonian and otiose! (Tutees!). Grice loved to place himself in the
role of the philosophical hack, dealing with his tutees inabilities, a whole
week long – until he could find refreshment in para-philosophy on the Saturday
morning! Now, the logical form of certain is a trick. Grice would symbolize it
as numbering of operators. If Pirot G ψs p, Pirot G ψs ψs p, and Pirot G ψs ψs ψs p, and so ad infinitum. This
is a bit like certainty. But not quite! When he explores trust, Grice considers
something like a backing for it. But does conclusive evidence yield certainty?
He doesnt think so. Certainty, for Grice should apply to any psychological
attitude, state or stance. And it is just clever of him that when he had to
deliver that lecture at London he chose intention and uncertainty as its topic,
just to provoke. Not surprisingly, the Intention and uncertainty piece opens
with the sceptics challenge. And he wont conclude that the intender is certain.
Only that theres some good chance (p greater than 0.5) that what he intends
will get through! When there is a will, there is a way, When there is a neo-Prichardian
will-ing, there is a palæo-Griceian way-ing! Perhaps by know Moore means
certain. Grice was amused by the fact that Moore thought that he knew that
behind the curtains at the lecture hall at the University of Wisconsin at
Madison, there was a window, when there wasnt. He uses Moores misuse of know –
according to Malcolm – both in Causal theory and Prolegomena. And of course
this relates to the topic of the sceptics implicature, 1946 above, with the two
essays Scepticism and Common sense and Moore and Philosophers Paradoxes
reprinted (one partially) in Studies. With regard to certainty, it is
interesting to compare it, as Grice does, not so much with privileged access,
but with incorrigibility. Do we not have privileged access to our own
beliefs and desires? And, worse still, may it not be true that at least some of
our avowals of our beliefs and desires are incorrigible? One of
Grices problems is, as he puts it, how to accommodate privileged access and,
maybe, incorrigibility. This or that a second-order state may be, in
some fashion, incorrigible. On the contrary, for Grice, this or that
lower-order, first-order judging is only a matter for privileged
access. Note that while he is happy to allow privileged access to lower-order
souly states, only those who are replicated at a higher-order or second-order
may, in some fashion, be said to count as an incorrigible avowal. It rains.
Pirot judges it rains (privileged access). Pirot judges that Pirot judges that
it rains (incorrigibile). The justification is conversational. It rains says
the pirot, or expresses the pirot. Grice wants to be able to say that if a
pirot expresses that p, the pirot judges2 that p. If the pirot
expresses that it rains, the pirot judges that he judges that it rains. In this
fashion, his second-order, higher-order judging is incorrigible, only. Although
Grice may allow for it to be corrected by a third-order judging. It is not
required that we should stick with judging here. Let Smith return the money
that he owes to Jones. If pirot expresses !p, pirot ψ-s2 that
!p. His second-order, higher-order buletic state is incorrigibile (if ceteris
paribus is not corrected by a third-order buletic or doxastic state). His
first-order buletic state is a matter only of privileged access.
ILLUSION:
Hallucination is Grice’s topic.Malcolm argues in Dreaming and Skepticism and in
his Dreaming that the notion of a dream qua conscious experience that occurs at
a definite time and has definite duration during sleep, is unintelligible. This
contradicts the views of philosophers like Descartes (and indeed Moore!), who, Malcolm
holds, assume that a human being may have a conscious thought and a conscious
experience during sleep. Descartes claims that he had been deceived during
sleep. Malcolms point is that ordinary language contrasts consciousness and
sleep. The claim that one is conscious while one is sleep-walking is stretching
the use of the term. Malcolm rejects the alleged counter-examples based on
sleepwalking or sleep-talking, e.g. dreaming that one is climbing stairs while
one is actually doing so is not a counter-example because, in such a case, the
individual is not sound asleep after all. If a person is in any state of
consciousness, it logically follows that he is not sound asleep. The concept of
dreaming is based on our descriptions of dreams after we have awakened in
telling a dream. Thus, to have dreamt that one has a thought during sleep is
not to have a thought any more than to have dreamt that one has climbed Everest
is to have climbed Everest. Since one cannot have an experience during sleep,
one cannot have a mistaken experience during sleep, thereby undermining the
sort of scepticism based on the idea that our experience might be wrong because
we might be dreaming. Malcolm further argues that a report of a conscious state
during sleep is unverifiable. If Grice claims that he and Strawson saw a
big-foot in charge of the reserve desk at the Bodleian library, one can verify
that this took place by talking to Strawson and gathering forensic evidence
from the library. However, there is no way to verify Grices claim that he
dreamed that he and Strawson saw a big-foot working at the Bodleian. Grices
only basis for his claim that he dreamt this is that Grice says so after he
wakes up. How does one distinguish the case where Grice dreamed that he saw a
big-foot working at The Bodleian and the case in which he dreamed that he saw a
person in a big-foot suit working at the library but, after awakening,
mis-remembered that person in a big-foot suit as a big-foot proper? If Grice
should admit that he had earlier mis-reported his dream and that he had
actually dreamed he saw a person in a big-foot suit at The Bodleian, there is
no more independent verification for this new claim than there was for the
original one. Thus, there is, for Malcolm, no sense to the idea of mis-remembering
ones dreams. Malcolm here applies one of Witters ideas from his private
language argument. One would like to say: whatever is going to seem right to me
is right. And that only means that here we cant talk about right. For a similar
reason, Malcolm challenges the idea that one can assign a definite duration or
time of occurrence to a dream. If Grice claims that he ran the mile in 3.4
minutes, one could verify this in the usual ways. If, however, Grice says he
dreamt that he ran the mile in 3.4 minutes, how is one to measure the duration
of his dreamt run? If Grice says he was wearing a stopwatch in the dream and
clocked his run at 3.4 minutes, how can one know that the dreamt stopwatch is
not running at half speed (so that he really dreamt that he ran the mile in 6.8
minutes)? Grice might argue that a dream report does not carry such a
conversational implicata. But Malcolm would say that just admits the point. The
ordinary criteria one uses for determining temporal duration do not apply to
dreamt events. The problem in both these cases (Grice dreaming one saw a
bigfoot working at The Bodleian and dreaming that he ran the mile in 3.4
minutes) is that there is no way to verify the truth of these dreamt events —
no direct way to access that dreamt inner experience, that mysterious glow of
consciousness inside the mind of Grice lying comatose on the couch, in order to
determine the facts of the matter. This is because, for Malcolm, there are no
facts of the matter apart from the dreamers report of the dream upon awakening.
Malcolm claims that the empirical evidence does not enable one to decide
between the view that a dream experience occurs during sleep and the view that
they are generated upon the moment of waking up. Dennett agrees with Malcolm
that nothing supports the received view that a dream involves a conscious
experience while one is asleep but holds that such issues might be settled
empirically. Malcolm also argues against the attempt to provide a physiological
mark of the duration of a dream, for example, the view that the dream lasted as
long as the rapid eye movements. Malcolm replies that there can only be as much
precision in that common concept of dreaming as is provided by the common
criterion of dreaming. These scientific researchers are misled by the
assumption that the provision for the duration of a dream is already there,
only somewhat obscured and in need of being made more precise. However, Malcolm
claims, it is not already there (in the ordinary concept of dreaming). These
scientific views are making radical conceptual changes in the concept of
dreaming, not further explaining our ordinary concept of dreaming. Malcolm
admits, however, that it might be natural to adopt such scientific views about
REM sleep as a convention. Malcolm points out, however, that if REM sleep is
adopted as a criterion for the occurrence of a dream, people would have to
be informed upon waking up that they had dreamed or not. As Pears observes,
Malcolm does not mean to deny that people have dreams in favour of the view
that they only have waking dream-behaviour. Of course it is no misuse of
language to speak of remembering a dream. His point is that since the concept
of dreaming is so closely tied to our concept of waking report of a dreams, one
cannot form a coherent concept of this alleged inner (private) something that
occurs with a definite duration during sleep. Malcolm rejects a certain
philosophical conception of dreaming, not the ordinary concept of dreaming,
which, he holds, is neither a hidden private something nor mere outward
behaviour. Malcolms account of dreaming has come in for considerable criticism.
Some argue that Malcolms claim that occurrences in dreams cannot be verified by
others does not require the strict criteria that Malcolm proposes but can be
justified by appeal to the simplicity, plausibility, and predictive adequacy of
an explanatory system as a whole. Some argue that Malcolms account of the
sentence I am awake is inconsistent. A comprehensive programme in considerable
detail has been offered for an empirical scientific investigation of dreaming
of the sort that Malcolm rejects. Others have proposed various counterexamples
and counter arguments against Malcolms account of dreaming. Grices emphasis is
in Malcolms easy way out with statements to the effect that implicata do or do
not operate in dream reports. They do in mine! Grice considers, I may be
dreaming in the two essays opening the Part II: Explorations on semantics and
metaphysics in WOW .
CONVERSATIONAL CANDOUR: It is all about confidence, you know. U U
expects his addressee A will find him confident. Thus we find in Short and
Lewis, confīdo, fĭsus sum, 3, I.v. n., wich they render as to trust confidently
in something, and also, confide in, rely firmly upon, to believe, be assured of
(as an enhancing of sperare, Cic. Att. 6, 9, 1; Nep. Milt. 1, 1; freq. and
class. in prose and poetry); constr. with abl., acc. and inf., with dat.,
rarely with de, ut, or absol. Trust and rationality are pre-requisites of
conversation. Urmson had developed this. Urmsons key phrase is "implied
claim." Whenever an utterer makes a conversational contribution in a standard
context, there is an implied claim to the utterer being trustworthy and
reasonable. What do Grice and Urmson mean by an "implied
claim"? Its obvious enough, but they both loved to expand. Whenever an
utterer U utters a sentence which can be used to convey truth or falsehood
there is an implied claim to trustworthiness by the utterer, unless the
situation shows that this is not so. The utterer is acting or reciting or
incredulously echoing the remark of another, or flouting the expectation. This,
Urmson thinks, may need an explanation. Suppose that an utterer utters
the sentence It will rain tomorrow or It rained yesterday, or Its raining
in ordinary circumstances. This act carries with it the claim that the
utterer should be trusted and that it will rain tomorrow. By this is
meant that just as it is understood that no utterer will give an order unless
he is entitled to give orders, so it is understood that no utterer will utter a
sentence of a kind which can be used to make a statement unless he is willing
to claim that that statement is true, and hence one would be acting in a
misleading manner if one uttered the sentence if he was not willing to make
that claim. The predicate implies that , Grice and Urmson hasten to add,
as Nowell-Smith, and Grant do, is being used in such a way that, if there is a
an expectation that a thing ks be done in Circumstance C, the utterer implies
that C holds if he does the thing. The point has often been made before, though
not always in these terms, and it is, Urmson and Grice believe, in substance
uncontroversial. Grice and Urmson wish to make the point that, when an utterer
U deploys a hedge with an indicative sentence, there is not merely an implied
claim that the whole statement is true but also that is true. This is
surely obvious in some cases. I believe it will rain. He is, I regret, too
fast. You intend, I gather, to refuse. But Grice and Urmson think that a little
thought shows that it is also true in the case of, say, I hear that he is ill
in bed, He is, I hear, ill in bed. An utterer would not say these things if he
did not accept the report on which the statement is based, and by saying it the
utterer implies that he can be claimed to be trustworthy. Grice is more careful
than Urmson here in that the primary buletic or doxastic claim is more
crucially (even in a NON ceteris paribus way), expressed than merely
implied, though. Vide, Way of Words, iii, on Moores paradox. The utterers
implied or expressed claim to trustworthiness need not be very strong. The
whole point of a hedge is to modify or to weaken (if not, as Grice would have
it, flout) the utterers claim to full trustworthiness which would be implied by
the assertion. But even if the utterer utters He is, I suppose, at home
or I guess that the penny will come down heads" the utterer
expresses, or for Urmson plainly implies, with however little reason, that this
is what he accept as worth his addressees trust, We our statements
In con as well as logical. E.g. the utterer often have an emotional
attitude to the fact he states, or it is likely to arouse emotion in his
addresee. To some extent, both by accident and by design our manner,
intonation and choice of words betray the utterers attitude and prepares his
addressee. But this is imprecise and uncertain, and, in writing, is
difficult to get right for all but the great stylist. Again, content and
manner give some clue to the addressee of how he is to understand the statement
in relation to its logical context, but not infallibly. Further, the
utterer makes his statement sometimes with good, sometimes with moderate,
sometimes with poor evidence. Which of these situations the utterer is in
need not be obvious to the addressee, and it would be cumbersome always to
convey explicitly. It is Grices and Urmsons contention that a hedge is
one of the sets of devices that an utterer uses in order to deal with these
matters, though not the only set. By them the utterer primes his
addressee to see the emotional significance, the logical relevance, and the
reliability of his statement. This the utterer does not by telling the
addressee how he is moved or how he should be moved by the statement, nor by
telling him how the utterers statement fits into the context, nor by describing
the evidential situation, but by the use of warning, priming or orientating
signals. The utterer shows rather than states. This is the
contention which will now be somewhat elaborated. Suppose that an utterer goes
to a mother in wartime as a messenger to inform her of the death of her
son. The utterer can, no doubt, merely say Madam, your son is dead.
But this would be abrupt and harsh, and the utterer would more probably say
Madam, I regret that your son is dead. For anyone other than a great actor it
is easier to steer a course between callousness and false sentiment as a
stranger bearing news by the use of a hedge in this way than by means of
intonation. Clearly the utterer is mainly bearing news, and the
addition of "I regret" (not necessarily at the beginning of the sentence)
shows without it being actually explicitly conveyed that it is being offered,
and will be received as, sad news. The utterer is not being a hypocrite,
even within the excusable, conventional, limits of hypocrisy, if he personally
has no feelings on the matter at all. Messengers of that sort can rarely
have much feeling in wartime about each case. If, for the moment we turn
to a less purely parenthetical use of the same verity we shall find that the
essential point remains the same. If, as a friend of the family, the
utterer goes to the mother when the death is well known and says I much regret
that your son is dead. He was a dear friend, then, no doubt, I am no
longer mainly bearing news. But I am still NOT describing my
feelings. It is rather that the signal is being made for its own sake as
an act of sympathy, the indicative clause giving the occasion of my
sympathy. Regret and rejoice are two of the most obvious examples of
verbs which give emotional orientation when used parenthetically. Another set
of these hedges is used to signal how the statement is to be taken as fitting
logically into the discussion. I admit that he is able assigns the
statement that he is able to the logical position of being support for the
opposed position, or a part of the opposed position which will not be assailed
one shows while saying that he is able that this is to be treated as an
admission. Grice refers to this as a second-order meta-conversational device in
Retrospective epilogue in Way of words, a non-central speech act (oppose,
object, add, contrast central speech acts are stating and ordering, only.
One is forestalling a possible misapprehension. But dont you see, that is
part of my point. One is not reporting the occurrence of "a bit of
admitting", whatever that may be supposed to be. The hedge
in Smith was, I conclude, the murderer assigns to the statement the
status of following from what has been said before, preventing it from being
taken as, say, an additional fact to be taken into account. Cf. Grice, Smith
is, therefore, the murderer and the conventional implicature of
"therefore". There is no specific activity of
"concluding". Other hedges which fulfil approximately similar
tasks are deduce, infer, presume, presuppose, confess, concede, maintain, and assume. Another rough group is
constituted by such hedges as know, believe, guess, suppos, suspect,
estimate, and, in a metaphorical use, feel. Never sense but metaphorical
use. Cf. Grices modified Occams razor, do not multiply senses beyond necessity,
and Urmsons having learned the lesson (his earlier, On the two senses of
probable"). This group is probably more controversial than the previous
ones, and will require more explanation. This, the belief and knowledge,
the group which is used to indicate the evidential situation in which the
statement is made (though not to describe that situation), and hence to signal
degree of reliability is claimed for, and should be accorded to, the statement
to which the hedged is conjoined. Thus I think that this is the
right road to take is a weaker way of saying that this is the right road,
indicating that one is just plumping and has no adequate evidence, so that the
statement will be received with the right amount of caution. I know, on the
other hand, shows that there is all the adequate evidence one could need. Some
of these hedges can clearly be arranged in a scalar set showing the reliability
of the conjoined statement according to the wealth of evidence,: know"
"believe" "suspect" "guess," so that "I believe,"
being on the weak side of the scale, impliese "I do not know." An
adverb can make the situation even plainer. I strongly believe, I rather
suspect and so on. The utterer is, in fact, in a position where he can either
make our statements neat, and leave it to the context and the general
probabilities to show to the addressee how much credence he should give to the
statement ; or, in addition to making the statement we can actually describe
the evidential situation in more or less detail ; or give a warning such as,
Dont rely on this too implicitly, but or
the utterer can employ the warning device of a parenthetical verb "I
believe it will rain." If this is insufficient for any reason (perhaps
it is an important matter), the addressee can ask why and get the description
of the evidential situation. More will have to be said about these verbs,
but it will be convenient first to introduce another topic, and that is the one
of adverbs corresponding to parenthetical verbs. Grice and Urmson mention
that parenthetical verbs are not the only device that an utterer has for
warning his addressee how his statement is to be taken while making it.
It will perhaps make it clearer how a parenthetical verb is used if one of
these other devices is briefly outlined. We were taught at school that an
adverb modifies a verb. But this is inaccurate, for some adverbs are
quite as loosely attached to whole sentences as are parenthetical verbs.
Examples are luckily, happily unfortunately consequently presumably admittedly
certainly undoubtedly probably possibly otiosely and Speranzas
favourite hopefully (Speranza _means_ hope). Note that the
position of these adverbs is variable in relation to the sentence as in the
case of a parenthetical verbs. We can say Unfortunately, he is ill,
or He is, unfortunately, ill. If the word modify is to be used the
adverbs can perhaps be said to modify the whole statement to which it are
attached. But how does it modify them? Surely by giving a warning
how they are to be understood, Luckily! , happily and unfortunately indicate
the appropriate attitude to the statement, for example. Admittedly,
consequently and presumably, among others, Indicate how to take the statement
in regard to the context. Certainly, probably and possibly , among others,
show how much reliability is to be ascribed to the statement. Perhaps it is
worth saying, though the matter should be sufficiently obvious, that no
importance should be attached to the grouping of verbs and adverbs into three
sets which has been adopted. It has been done purely for convenience in
an outline exposition. There are differences between the members of each of my
groups and the groups are not sharply divided. It is easy to think of verbs
which might with equal reason be placed In either of two groups. Once again it
must be said that our aim is to lay down general lines for the interpretation
of parenthetical verbs, not to do full justice to any of them. Provided
that it is not construed as a list of synonyms, we can couple these adverbs
with parenthetical verbs as follows. happily I rejoice unfortunately I
regret consequently I deduce I infer presumably I presume admittedly I
admit -"Certainly" compares to "I know, cf.. knowingly.
Probably I believe, cf. Unbelievably, believably. This is not, Grice and Urmson
repeat, a list of synonyms. Apart from questions of nuance of meaning the
adverbs are more impersonal. "Admittedly" suggests that what is
said would be regarded by anyone as an admission whereas I admit shows
only the way that the statement is to be regarded here, by the utterer.
Also it is not possible to say that every adverb has a verb corresponding to it
which has more or less the same import, or vice versa. But it does seem
that these adverbs and parenthetical play much the same role and have much the
same grammatical relation to the statements which they accompany, and that,
therefore, the comparison is illuminating in both directions. Now Grice and
Urmson meet an objection which will certainly be made by some philosophers to
this comparison. Grice and Urmson intend to meet the objection by a fairly
detailed examination of the example which they themselves would most likely
choose. In doing this Grice and Urmson further explain the use of a
parenthetical verbs. The adverb is "Probably" and the verb is I
believe. To say, that something is probable, my imaginary objector will say, is
to imply that it is reasonable to believe, that the evidence justifies a
guarded claim for the utterers trust or trustworthiness and the truth of the
statement. But to say that someone believes something does not imply that it is
reasonable for the utterer to believe it, nor that the evidence justifies the
guarded or implied claim to factivity or truth which he makes. Therefore,
the objector will continue, the difference between the use of t believe and
probably is not, as Grice and Urmson suggest, merely one of nuance and degree
of impersonality. In one case reasonableness is implied in the other it is not.
This objection is met by Grice and Urmson. They do so by making a general
point. There is the utterers implied claim to reasonableness. There
is an implied claim to trust whenever a sentence is uttered in a standard
context, and the meaning of this is explained. Now Grice and Urmson add,
to meet the sceptical objection about the contrast between probably and I
believe that, whenever an utterer makes a statement in a standard context there
is an implied claim to reasonableness. This contention must be explained alla
Kant. Cf. Strawson on the presumption of conversational relevance, and
Nowell-Smith, and Grant, and Warnock. And Austin. Grice on rational and
reasonable in "Aspects of reason". Unless we are acting
or story-telling, or preface our remarks with some such phrase as I know
Im being silly, but or, I admit it is unreasonable, but
" it is, Grice and Urmson think, a presupposition or expectation of
communication or conversation that a communicator will not make a statement,
thereby implying this trust, unless he has some ground, however tenuous,
for the statement. To utter The King is visiting Oxford tomorrow or The
President of the British Academy has a corkscrew in his pocket, and then, when
asked why the utterer is uttering that, to answer Oh, for no reason
at all would be to sin, theologically, against the basic conventions
governing the use of discourse. Grice goes on to provide a Kantian
justification for that, hence his amusing talk of maxims and stuff.
Therefore, Urmson and Grice think there is an implied or expressed claim
to reasonableness which goes with all our statements, i.e. there is
a mutual expectation that a communicator will not make a statement unless he is
prepared to claim and defend its reasonablenesss. Cf. Grice on reasonable
and rational, in "Aspects of reason" (the John Locke Lectures,
Oxford). They can return to the defence of their account of belief and
probability. We can now say, with less risk of being misunderstood, that when
an utterer utterer I believe, not know, that he is at home or Smith
is, I believe (but not know), at home the utterer both implies (or
expresses as Grice may prefer -- since implicate is too strong) a guarded
claim of his being trustworthy and reasonable re: the statement that Smith is
at home. Thus, if our sceptical objector points out that Probably he is
at home, unlike I believe he is at home, implies, in the view of the utterer,
the reasonableness and justifiability of the statement, we may answer that this
is equally true of believe in the first person present. In such a form as I
believe that Smith is at home. What our objector fails to do is to notice
the vast array of situations in which believe is used. We will now single
out some, but only some, of these uses. Jones says, Smith is, I believe,
at home. Here Jones makes an implied guarded claim (that is the effect of
adding I believe) to his being trustworthy and also an implied claim to his
being reasonable re the statement Smith Is at home. This is the case already
examined. Williams, reports Jones, says Smith is, Jones believes, at
home. This is oratio obliqua, reporting Jones parenthetical use of the
verb. Williams, by uttering the sentence, implies his and Joness being
trustworthy and reasonable re: the statement that Jones has made the statement
that Smith is at home. Jones thereby implying its truth and reasonableness with
the conventional warning signal about the evidential situation. A third
scenario is Smith, who has discovered that there has been a sudden railway
stoppage, sees Jones making his habitual morning dash to the station, and says
Jones believes that the trains are working. This is a new, and, however
important, derivative, use of believe. Note that in this context Smith could
not say, The trains, Jones believes, are working. But we can say, The trains,
if Jones is to be believed, are working. who has probably not considered the
matter at all is behaving in the way that someone who prepared to say either
The trains are running or I believe that the trains are running would behave
(no doubt he would be prepared to say one or other of these things if he
considered the matter. We thus in a perfectly intelligible way, extend our use
of believe to those situations in which a person behaves as a person who
has considered the evidence and was willing to say I believe would consistently
behave. In this case, but in this case alone, there is some point in
saying that believe is used dispositionally. But note that it is so used
with reference to another use of believe. It is also noteworthy that the
verb cannot be so used in the first person present. To say I believe in this way is no more possible
than to say I am under the delusion that
I believe is always used parenthetically, though not always purely
so. If one does recognizes that a belief that one has held is
unreasonable, one either gives it up or is driven to saying I cant help
believing. This is psychological history, and carries with it no claim to truth
or reasonableness. Thus we see that Jones believes that p does not imply
the reasonableness of "p" any more than It seems probable to Jones
that p does. On the other hand, both "Probably p" and I
believe that p do imply utterers reasonableness re: p. Thus, so far at
least as we are concerned with the well-known objection about reasonableness,
the parallel between probably (or certainly) and I believe (or I know) has
stood the test without difficulty. At the risk of digression we may pause
to comment on the history of the analysis of knowledge and belief. Of
old, since Plato, philosophers have tried to find a primary occurrent use of
believe as a psychological description. But since Austin, the impossibility of
this has been amply demonstrated, and philosophers have resorted to a
Ryle-inspired dispositional analysis, assuming that if the verb does not
describe an occurrence it must describe a tendency to an occurrence.
There is some point in the traditionalist reply to this that belief is here
analysed as being the behaviour, if any, which would consistently accompany
itself. A recognition that in the analysis of belief the non-descriptive
parenthetical use is primary seems to illuminate and resolve this
dispute. This is all that can here be said about belief. It far from
exhausts even all the relevant considerations, but Grices and Urmsons aim is
not to examine any one parenthetical verb exhaustively; rather it is to shed
new light on them all by presenting them as a group. I want to say the main
things which may be said about a set of verbs which are not normally considered
together as an aid to the thorough examination of each which Grice or Urmson
not undertake. Individually, none of these verbs can be exhaustively treated in
their capacity as parenthetical verbs and Grice and Urmson must not be taken as
suggesting that they can. Further consideration of the third
group. I guess has nowadays a colloquial use in which its
significance is, at the best, very indeterminate -- or as Speranza would
prefer, "otiose". But in a stricter use it serves to warn
that what is being said is a guess. Suppose that one is asked Do you know
who called this afternoon? One may answer No, but I guess that it was Mrs.
Jones. Even here one is making an implied claim that it was Mr. Jones who
called and that this is a reasonable thing to say. If one had said I
guess that it was Mr. Stalin one would have been making a clumsy joke and not
really guessing at all. It seems to Urmson and Grice to be quite
impossible that anyone should think that here I guess reports a psychological state or a tendency
or disposition o behave in any special way. It is put in to show that one
is making ones statement without any specific evidence, that it is, in fact, a
guess. What makes it a guess is not a psychological state nor a
disposition to behave in any way, but, if it is a genuine guess, its being said
without any specific evidence, and its being potentially silly or lucky, not
well-based or ill- supported. Grice and Urmson cannot see that there is any
essential difference between guess on the one hand and know, opine, and
suspect, for example, on the other.specially The epistemological
situation is more complicated in the latter set of cases, and some of them have
special quirks in their use, know being a notorious example, but that Is all.
Each is essentially the same sort of verb. It might be worth while to
compare this view of knowledge with what Austin said in Other Minds,
P.A.S. Su20 (reprinted in L. L., II). Much of Grices and Urmsons approach
is suggested by this paper by Austin. Among other, less immediately
relevant, things, Austin distinguishes a class of performatory verbs and
compares our use of know with our use of these verbs. In particular,
Austin compares it with guarantee. But Austin is careful not to say that
know is a performatory verb. He also points out important differences
between the guarantee and know. Grice and Urmson agree that the comparison
which Austin makes between know and performatory verbs is just and
illuminating. Parenthetical and performatory verbs have much in common as
against ordinary descriptive verbs. Grice and Urmson are not therefore
disagreeing with Austin, but trying to locate the verb to in a class which it
was not his purpose to consider. Grice and Urmson distinguish a set of
parenthetical verbs and make some points about their parenthetical use in the
first person of the present tense. Each occurs in the present perfect, not the
continuous tense, though its use is different from that of the present perfect
tense of verbs which have a present continuous tense. Though, in a wide
sense, a psychological verb, each is not psychologically descriptive.
Each functions rather like a certain class of adverbs to orient the addressee
aright towards the statements with which each is associated. The ways in which
they do this may be roughly indicated as being aids to placing the statements
aright against the emotional, social, logical, and evidential background.
There is, as when the conjoined statements are used alone, an implied claim for
the trustworthiness and reasonableness of the utterer re these associated
statements. But parenthetical verbs are not always used
parenthetically. In the first person present, to which use we have
so far confined practically all our attention. We must now say something about
their other uses. We may consider the positive analogy. In connexion with the
point above, there is a positive analogy, though not a very tidy one. The
analogy seems to hold completely in the case of some verbs. One cannot say I was believing, he is believing , I was
knowing , he was knowing, I was suspecting, or he was suspecting. In the case
of some other parenthetical verbs, we find a rare and anomalous imperfect
tense. For example, we can say that you were admitting something if you were
interrupted in the middle of a statement which you were making as an admission
; or again, we can say that someone is deducing the consequences of a set of
premisses, while he is stating a succession of things as deductions. But these
are not genuine exceptions. In the case of another set of these verbs an
imperfect is not so strange. At the end of an argument which have been put
forth someone might say, for example, All the while you were assuming
(presupposing, accepting) that so and so. But this is not like the imperfect
tense of ordinary verbs which report the continuance throughout a period of
some occurrence. I was not throughout the period continuously doing an act of
assumption which I carefully refrained from mentioning. Rather I was
arguing as a man would reasonably argue who was prepared to say, I assume that so-and-so; that is to say, I
was arguing in a way that required so and so as a premiss if the argument was
to be valid. I ought, therefore, to be willing to state so-and-so as a
premiss. Thus here, too, the other use has to be understood In the light
of the parenthetical use. We must also note that, in general, these verbs
can throughout be used in parenthesis. We can say Jones was, Smith
admitted, able. This seems to be so whenever the use is either definite
oratio obliqua or, at any rate, a fair paraphrase. Some verbs, such as
deduce and admit, seem always to be used in this way. But others,
including, as we have already seen assume, presuppse s and are used, not
of a man who has said, (I assume (believe, presuppose) , or words to that
effect, but of a man who as a man reasonably would who was prepared to say
that. In such a use, which is a genuine descriptive use, the
parenthetical Insertion (in a grammatical sense) of the verb seems to be
impossible. Continuing with the positive analogy, it seems to follow from
the above that, except in some derivative uses, parenthetical verbs are not
used as psychological descriptions in other parts of their conjugation any more
than in the first person present. And even in these derivative uses, they seem
to describe general behaviour rather than to be specifically mental. The
obvious negative analogy is, first, that the adverbs can only be used to
correspond to the first person. But this negative analogy is only so in a very
limited way. If the adverbs did correspond exactly to the whole conjugation of
the verb, then the conjugation would appear to be otiose. But the adverbs can
be systematically correlated with the whole conjugation of the parenthetical
verbs with the aid of the verb to seem. Cf. Grices desideratum of
conversational candour, subsumed under the over-arching principle of
conversational helpfulness (formerly conversational
benevolence-cum-self-interest). Grice thinks that the principle of
conversational benevolence has to be weighed against the principle of
conversational self-interest. The result is the overarching principle of
conversational helpfulness. Clarity gets in the picture. The desideratum of
conversational clarity is a reasonable requirement for conversants to abide
by. Grice follows some of Warnocks observations. The logical
grammar of trust (and indeed candour) is subtle, especially when we are
considering the two sub-goals of conversation: giving and receiving
information/influencing and being influenced by others. In both sub-goals,
trust is paramount. The explorations of trust had become an Oxonian hobby, with
authors not such like Warnock, but Williams, and others. : trust,
metaphysics, value. Trust as a corollary of the principle of conversational
helpfulness. The logical grammar of trust is an interesting one. Grice
used to speak of candour. In a given conversational setting, assuming the
principle of conversational helpfulness is operating, the utterer U is assumed
by the addressee A to be trustworthy. There are two dimensions for trust,
which relate to the TWO goals which Grice assumes the principle of
conversational helpfulness captures: ‒ giving and receiving information,
and influencing and being influenced by others. In both sub-goals, trust
is key. In the doxastic realm, trust has to do, not so much with truth
(with which the expression is cognate) but evidence. In the boulomaic realm,
evidence becomes less crucial. Grice mentions attitudes of the boulomaic type
that are not usually judged in terms of evidential support. However, in
the boulomaic realm, utterer will be assumed as trustworthy if the conative
attitudes he displays are sincere. Cf. decency. A cheater for Grice is not
irrational, just repugnant!
PRINCIPLE OF CONVERSATIONAL HELPFULNESS: A set of seven lectures,
entitled as follows. Lecture 1, Prolegomena; Lecture 2: Logic and Conversation;
Lecture 3: Further notes on logic and conversation; Lecture 4: Indicative
conditionals; Lecture 5: Us meaning and intentions; Lecture 6: Us meaning,
sentence-meaning, and word-meaning; and Lecture 7: Some models for implicature.
I hope they dont expect me to lecture on James! Grice admired James, but
not vice versa. Grice entitled the set as being Logic and Conversation.
That is the title, also, of the second lecture. Grice keeps those titles seeing
that it was way the whole set of lectures were frequently cited, and that the
second lecture had been published under that title in Davidson and
Harman, The Logic of Grammar. The content of each lecture is
indicated below. In the first, Grice manages to quote from
Witters. In the last, he didnt! The original set consisted of seven
lectures. To wit: Prolegomena, Logic and conversation, Further notes on logic
and conversation, Indicative Conditionals, Us meaning and intentions, Us
meaning, sentence-meaning, and word meaning, and Some models for implicature.
They were pretty successful at Oxford. While the notion of an implicatum had
been introduced by Grice at Oxford, even in connection with a principle of
conversational helpfulness, he takes the occasion now to explore the type of
rationality involved. Observation of the principle of conversational
helpfulness is rational (reasonable) along the following lines: anyone who
cares about the two central goals to conversation (give/receive information,
influence/be influened) is expected to have an interest in participating in a
conversation that is only going to be profitable given that it is conducted
along the lines set by the principle of conversational helpfulness. In
Prolegomena he lists Austin, Strawson, Hare, Hart, and himself, as victims of a
disregard for the implicatum. In the third lecture he introduces his razor,
Senses are not to be muliplied beyond necessity. In Indicative conditionals he
tackles Strawson on if as not representing the horse-shoe of Whitehead and
Russell. The next two lectures, Us meaning and intentions and Us meaning,
sentence-meaning, and word-meaning refine his earlier, more austere, account of
this particularly Peirceian phenomenon. He concludes the lectures with an
exploration on the relevance of the implicatum to philosophical
psychology. Grice was well aware that many philosophers had become
enamoured with the s. and would love to give it a continuous perusal. The set
is indeed grandiose. It starts with a Prolegomena to set the scene: He notably
quotes himself in it, which helps, but also Strawson, which sort of justifies
the general title. In the second lecture, Logic and Conversation, he expands on
the principle of conversational helpfulness and the explicitum/implicatum
distinction – all very rationalist! The third lecture is otiose in that he makes
fun of Ockham: Senses are not to be multiplied beyond necessity. The fourth
lecture, on Indicative conditionals, is indeed on MOST of the formal devices he
had mentioned on Lecture II, notably the functors (rather than the quantifiers
and the iota operator, with which he deals in Presupposition and conversational
implicature, since, as he notes, they refer to reference). This lecture is the
centrepiece of the set. In the fifth lecture, he plays with mean, and discovers
that it is attached to the implicatum or the implicitum. In the sixth lecture,
he becomes a nominalist, to use Bennetts phrase, as he deals with dog and
shaggy in terms of this or that resultant procedure. Dont ask me what they are!
Finally, in Some models for implicature, he attacks the charge of circularity,
and refers to nineteenth-century explorations on the idea of thought without
language alla Wundt. I dont think a set of James lectures had even been so
comprehensive!
PRINCIPLE OF
CONVERSATIONAL HELPFULNESS: This is Grice at his methodological best. He was
aware that the type of philosophying he was about to criticise wass a bit
dated, but whats wrong with being old-fashioned? While this may be seen as a
development of his views on implicature at that seminal Oxford seminar, it may
also be seen as Grice popularising the views for a New-World, non-Oxonian
audience. A discussion of Oxonian philosophers of Grices play group, notably
Austin, Strawson, Hart, and Hare. He adds himself for good measure (The causal
theory of perception). Philosophers, even at Oxford, have to be careful with
the attention that is due to general principles of discourse. Grice quotes
philosophers of an earlier generation, such as Ryle, and some interpreters or
practitioners of Oxonian analysis, such as Benjamin and Searle. He even manages
to quote from Witterss Philosophical investigations, on seeing a banana as a
banana. There are further items in the Grice collection that address Austins
manoeuvre, Austin on ifs and cans, Ifs and cans, : conditional,
power. Two of Grices favourites. He opposed Strawsons view on if.
Grice thought that if was the horseshoe of Whitehead and Russell, provided we
add an implicatum to an entailment. The can is merely dispositional, if
not alla Ryle, alla Grice! Ifs and cans, : Austin, intention,
disposition. Austin had brought the topic to the fore as an exploration of
free will. Pears had noted that conversational implicature may account for the
conditional perfection (if yields iff). Cf. Ayers on Austin on if and can.
Recall that for Grice the most idiomatic way to express a disposition is with
the Subjectsive mode, the if, and the can ‒ The ice can break. Cf. the mistake:
It is not the case that what you must do, you can do. The can-may distinction
is one Grice played with too. As with will and shall, the attachment of one
mode to one of the lexemes is pretty arbitrary and not etymologically justified
‒ pace Fowler on it being a privilege of this or that Southern Englishman as
Fowler is. If he calls it Prolegomena, he is being jocular. Philosophers
Mistakes would have been too provocative. Benjamin, or rather Broad, erred, and
so did Ryle, and Ludwig Witters, and my friends, Austin (the mater that
wobbled), and in order of seniority, Hart (I heard him defend this about
carefully – stopping at every door in case a dog comes out at breakneck speed),
Hare (To say good is to approve), and Strawson (Introduction to Logical theory:
To utter if p, q is to implicate some inferrability, To say true! is to endorse
– Analysis). If he ends with Searle, he is being jocular. He quotes Searle from
an essay in British philosophy in Lecture I, and from an essay in Philosophy in
America in Lecture V. He loved Searle, and expands on the Texas oilmens club
example! We may think of Grice as a linguistic botanizer or a meta-linguistic
botanizer: his hobby was to collect philosophers mistakes, and he catalogued
them. In Causal theory he produces his first list of seven. The pillar box
seems red to me. One cannot see a dagger as a dagger. Moore didnt know that the
objects before him were his own hands. What is actual is not also possible. For
someone to be called responsible, his action should be condemnable. A cause
must be given only of something abnormal or unusual (cf. ætiology). If you know
it, you dont believe it. In the Prolegomena, the taxonomy is more complicated.
Examples A (the use of an expression, by Ryle, Wittgenstein, Austin, Hart, and
Benjamin), Examples B (Strawson on and, or, and especially if), and Examples C
(Strawson on true and Hare on good – the performative theories). But even if
his taxonomy is more complicated, he makes it more SO by giving other examples
as he goes on to discuss how to assess the philosophical mistake. Cf. his
elaboration on trying, I saw Mrs. Smith cashing a cheque, Trying to cash a
cheque, you mean. Or cf. his remarks on remember, and There is an analogy here
with a case by Wittgenstein. In summary, he wants to say. Its the philosopher
who makes his big mistake. He has detected, as Grice has it, some
conversational nuance. Now he wants to exploit it. But before rushing ahead to
exploit the conversational nuance he has detected, or identified, or collected
in his exercise of linguistic botanising, the philosopher should let us know
with clarity what type of a nuance it is. For Grice wants to know that the
nuance depends on a general principle (of goal-directed behaviour in general,
and most likely rational) governing discourse – that participants in a
conversation should be aware of, and not on some minutiæ that has been
identified by the philosopher making the mistake, unsystematically, and merely
descriptively, and taxonomically, but without ONE drop of explanatory adequacy.
The fact that he directs this to his junior Strawson is the sad thing. The rest
are all Grices seniors! The point is of philosophical interest, rather than
other. And he keeps citing philosophers, Tarski or Ramsey, in the third James
leture, to elaborate the point about true in Prolegomena. He never seems
interested in anything but an item being of philosophical interest, even if
that means HIS and MINE! On top, he is being Oxonian: Only at Oxford my
colleagues were so obsessed, as it has never been seen anywhere else, about the
nuances of conversation. Only they were all making a big mistake in having no
clue as to what the underlying theory of conversation as rational co-operation
would simplify things for them – and how! If I introduce the explicatum as a
concession, I shall hope I will be pardoned! Is Grices intention epagogic, or
diagogic in Prolegomena? Is he trying to educate Strawson, or just delighting
in proving Strawson wrong? We think the former. The fact that he quotes himself
shows that Grice is concerned with something he still sees, and for the rest of
his life will see, as a valid philosophical problem. If philosophy generated no
problems it would be dead.
CONVERSATIONAL IMPLICATURE:Grice loved an implicatum. An
elaboration of his Oxonian seminar on Logic and conversation. Theres a
principle of conversational helpfulness, which includes a desideratum of
conversational candour and a desideratum of conversational clarity, and the
sub-principle of conversational self-interest clashing with the sub-principle
of conversational benevolence. The whole point of the manoeuvre is to provide a
rational basis for a conversational implicatum, as his term of art goes.
Observation of the principle of conversational helpfulness is rational/reasonable
along the following lines: anyone who is interested in the two goals
conversation is supposed to serve ‒ give/receive information, influence/be
influenced ‒ should only care to enter a conversation that will be only
profitable under the assumption that it is conducted in accordance with the
principle of conversational helfpulness, and attending desiderata and
sub-principles. Grice takes special care in listing tests for the proof that an
implicatum is conversational in this rather technical usage: a conversational
implicatum is rationally calculable (it is the content of a psychological
state, attitude or stance that the addressee assigns to the utterer on
condition that he is being helpful), non-detachable, indeterminate, and very
cancellable, thus never part of the sense and never an entailment of this or
that piece of philosophical vocabulary, in Davidson and Harman, the logic of
Grammar, also in Cole and Morgan, repr. in a revised form in Grice, logic and
conversation, the second James lecture, : principle of conversational
helpfulness, implicatum, cancellability. While the essay was also
reprinted by Cole and Morgan, Grice always cited it from the Davidsons and
Harmans two-column reprint in The Logic of Grammar. Most people without a
philosophical background first encounter Grice through this
essay. Philosophers usually get first acquainted with his In defence
of a dogma, or Meaning. In Logic and Conversation, Grice re-utilises the
notion of an implicatum and the principle of conversational helpfulness
that he had introduced at Oxford to a more select audience. Grices idea is that
the observation of the principle of conversational helfpulness is rational
(reasonable) along the following lines: anyone who is concerned with the
two goals which are central to conversation (to give/receive information,
to influence/be influenced) should be interested in participating in a
conversation that is only going to be profitable on the assumption that it
is conducted along the lines of the principle of conversational
helfpulness. Grices point is methodological. He is not at all interested
in conversational exchanges as such. Unfortunately, the essay starts in
media res, and skips Grices careful list of Oxonian examples of disregard
for the key idea of what a conversant implicates by the conversational
move he makes. His concession is that there is an explicatum or explicitum
(roughly, the logical form) which is beyond pragmatic constraints. This
concession is easily explained in terms of his overarching irreverent, conservative,
dissenting rationalism. This lecture alone had been read by a few
philosophers leaving them confused. I dont know what Davidson and Harman were
thinking when they reprinted just this in The logic of grammar. I mean: its
obviously in media res. Grice starts with the logical devices, and never again
takes the topic up. Then he explores metaphor, irony, and hyperbole, and surely
the philosopher who bought The logic of grammar must be left puzzled! He had to
wait sometime to see the thing in full completion. Oxonian philosophers would,
out of etiquette, hardly quote from unpublished material! Cohen had to rely on
memory, and thats why he got all his Grice wrong! And so did Strawson in If and
the horseshoe. Even Walker responding to Cohen is relying on memory. Few
philosophers quote from The logic of grammar. At Oxford, everybody knew what
Grice was up to. Hare was talking implicature in Mind, and Pears was talking
conversational implicature in Ifs and cans. And Platts was dedicating a full
chapter to Causal Theory of Perception. It seems the Oxonian etiquette was to
quote from Causal Theory. It was obvious that Grices implication excursus had
to read implicature! In a few dictionaries of philosophy, such as Hamlyns,
under implication, a reference to Grices locus classicus Causal theory is made
– Passmore quotes from Causal theory in Hundred years of philosophy. Very few
Oxonians would care to buy a volume published in Encino. Not many Oxonian
philosophers ever quoted The logic of grammar, though. At Oxford, Grices
implicata remained part of the unwritten doctrines of a few. And philosophers
would NOT cite a cajoled essay in the references.
MODIFIED OCCAM’S RAZOR: Grice loved a razor. The essay had
circulated since the Harvard days, and it was also reprinted by Peter Cole in his Pragmatics for
Academic Press. Personally, I prefer dialectica. ‒
Grice. This is the third James lecture at Harvard. It is particularly
useful for Grices introduction of his razor, M. O. R., or Modified Occams
Razor, jocularly expressed by Grice as: Senses are not to be multiplied
beyond necessity. An Englishing of the Ockhams Latinate, Entia non sunt
multiplicanda præter necessitatem. But what do we mean sense. Surely Occam
was right with his Entia non sunt multiplicanda præter necessitatem. We need to
translate that alla linguistic turn. Grice jokes: Senses are not be multiplied
beyond necessity. He also considers irony, stress (supra-segmental
fourth-articulatory phonology), and truth, which the Grice Papers have under a
special f. in the s. V . Three topics where the implicatum helps. He
is a scoundrel may well be the IMPLICATUM of He is a fine friend. But cf.
the pretense theory of irony. Grice, being a classicist, loved the etymological
connection. With Stress, he was concerned with anti-Gettier uses of
emphatic know: I KNOW. (Implicatum: I do have conclusive evidence). Truth
(or is true) sprang from Grices
attention to that infamous Bristol symposium between Austin and
Strawson. Cf. Moores paradox. Grice wants to defend Austins correspondence
theory against Strawsons performative approach. If is true implicates someone previously
affirmed this, that does not mean a ditto implicatum is part of the entailment
of a is true utterance. 1967,
1978. Further notes on logic and conversation, in Cole, repr. in a revised
form, Modified Occams Razor, irony, stress, truth. The preferred citation
should be Grice 1967:III. This is originally the third James
lecture, in a revised form. In that lecture, Grice introduced the M.
O. R., or Modified Occams Razor. Senses are not be multiplied beyond
necessity. The point is that entailment-cum-implicatum does the job that
multiplied senses should not do! The Grice Papers contains in a different f.
the concluding section for that lecture, on irony, stress, and truth. Grice
went back to the Modified Occams razor, but was never able to formalise it! It
is, as he concedes, almost a vacuous methodological thingy! It is interesting
that the way he defines the alethic value of true alrady cites satisfactory. I
shall use, to Names such a property, not true but factually
satisfactory. Grices sympathies dont lie with Strawsons Ramsey-based
redundance theory of truth, but rather with Tarskis theory of correspondence.
He goes on to claim his trust in the feasibility of such a theory. It is,
indeed, possible to construct a theory which treats truth as (primarily) a
property, not true but factually satisfactory. One may see that point above as
merely verbal and not involving any serious threat. Lets also assume that
it will be a consequence, or theorem, of such a theory that there will be a
class C of utterances (utterances of affirmative Subjects-predicate sentences
[such as snow is white or the cat is on the mat of the dog is hairy-coated such
that each member of C designates or refers to some item and indicates or
predicates some class (these verbs to be explained within the theory), and is
factually satisfactory if the item belongs to the class. Let us also
assume that there can be a method of introducing a form of expression, it is true
that /it is buletic that and linking it
with the notion of factually or alethic or doxastic satisfactory, a consequence
of which will be that to say it is true that Smith is happy will be equivalent
to saying that any utterance of class C which designates Smith and indicates
the class of happy people is factually satisfactory (that is, any utterance
which assigns Smith to the class of happy people is factually satisfactory.
Mutatis mutandis for Let Smith be happy, and buletic satisfactoriness. The
move is Tarskian. The two standard truth definitions are at first glance not
definitions of truth at all, but definitions of a more complicated relation
involving assignments of objects to variables: a satisfies the formula F,
(where the symbol F is a placeholder for a Names of a particular formula of the
object language). In fact satisfaction reduces to truth in this way: aa
satisfies the formula FF if and only if taking each free variable in FF as a Names
of the object assigned to it by aa makes the formula FF into a true sentence.
So it follows that our intuitions about when a sentence is true can guide our
intuitions about when an assignment satisfies a formula. But none of this can
enter into the formal definition of truth, because taking a variable as a Names
of an object is a semantic notion, and Tarskis truth definition has to be built
only on notions from syntax and set theory (together with those in the
object-language); In fact Tarskis reduction goes in the other direction: if the
formula FF has no free variables, to say that FF is true is to say that every
assignment satisfies it. The reason why Tarski defines satisfaction directly,
and then deduces a definition of truth, is that satisfaction obeys recursive
conditions in the following way. if FF is a compound formula, to know which
assignments satisfy FF, its enough to know which assignments satisfy the
immediate constituents of FF. Here are two typical examples: The assignment a
satisfies the formula F and GG if and
only if aa satisfies FF and aa satisfies GG. The assignment aa satisfies the
formula For all xx, GG if and only if for every individual ii, if bb is the
assignment that assigns ii to the variable xx and is otherwise exactly like aa,
then bb satisfies GG. We have to use a different approach for atomic formulas.
But for these, at least assuming for simplicity that LL has no function
symbols, we can use the metalanguage copies #(R)#(R) of the predicate symbols
RR of the object language. Thus The assignment aa SATSIFIES the formula
R(x,y)R(x,y) if and only if #(R)(a(x),a(y))#(R)(a(x),a(y)). Warning: the
expression ## is in the meta-meta-language, not in the meta-language MM. We may
or may not be able to find a formula of MM that expresses ## for predicate
symbols; it depends on exactly what the language LL is.). Subjects to this or
that mild reservation, Tarskis definition of satisfaction is compositional,
meaning that the class of assignments which satisfy a compound formula FF is
determined solely by the syntactic rule used to construct FF from its immediate
constituents and the classes of assignments that satisfy these immediate
constituents. This is sometimes phrased loosely by saying that satisfaction is
defined recursively. But this formulation misses the central point, that the
above do not contain any syntactic information about the immediate
constituents. Compositionality explains why Tarski switches from true to
satisfied. You cant define whether For all x,Gx,G is true in terms of whether
GG is true, because in general GG has a free variable xx and so it isnt either
true or false. The reservation is that Tarskis definition of satisfaction in
Tarskis essay doesnt in fact mention the class of assignments that satisfy a
formula FF. Instead, as we saw, he defines the relation aa satisfies FF, which
determines what that class is. This is probably the main reason why some people
(including Tarski himself in conversation have preferred NOT to describe the
definition as compositional. But the class format, which is compositional on
any reckoning, does appear in an early variant of the truth definition in
Tarskis essay on definable sets of real numbers. Tarski had a good reason for
preferring the format aa satisfies FF in his essay, viz. that it allowed him to
reduce the set-theoretic requirements of the truth definition. He spells out
these requirements carefully. Compositionality first appears in an essay by
Putnam. In talking about compositionality, we have moved to thinking of Tarskis
definition as a semantics, i.e. a way of assigning meanings to formulas. Here
we take the meaning of a sentence to be its truth value. Compositionality means
essentially that the meanings assigned to formulas give at least enough
information to determine the truth values of sentences containing them. One can
ask conversely whether Tarskis semantics provides only as much information as
we need about each formula, in order to reach the truth values of sentences. If
the answer is yes, we say that the semantics is fully abstract (for truth). One
can show fairly easily, for any of the standard languages of logic, that
Tarskis definition of satisfaction is in fact fully abstract. As it stands,
Tarskis definition of satisfaction is not an explicit definition, because
satisfaction for one formula is defined in terms of satisfaction for other
formulas. So to show that it is formally correct, we need a way of converting
it to an explicit definition. One way to do this is as follows, using either
higher order logic or set theory. Suppose we write SS for a binary relation
between assignments and formulas. We say that SS is a satisfaction relation if
for every formula G, SG, S meets the conditions put for satisfaction of GG by
Tarskis definition. E.g., if GG is G1G1 and G2G2, SS should satisfy the
following condition for every assignment aa: S(a, G) if and only if S(a, G1)
and S(a, G2).S (a, G) if and only if S(a, G1) and S(a, G2). We can define
satisfaction relation formally, using the recursive clauses and the conditions
for atomic formulas in Tarskis recursive definition. Now we prove, by induction
on the complexity of formulas, that there is exactly one satisfaction relation
SS. There are some technical subtleties, but it can be done. Finally we define
aa satisfies FF if and only if: there is a satisfaction relation SS such that S
(a, F) S (a, F). It is then a technical exercise to show that this definition
of satisfaction is materially adequate. Actually one must first write out the
counterpart of Convention TT for satisfaction of formulas, but I leave this to
the reader. The remaining truth definition in Tarskis essay – the third
as they appear in the essay – is really a bundle of related truth definitions,
all for the same object-language LL but in different interpretations. The
quantifiers of LL are assumed to range over a particular class, call it AA; in
fact they are second order quantifiers, so that really they range over the
collection of subclasses of AA. The class AA is not Namesd explicitly in the
object language, and thus one can give separate truth definitions for different
values of AA, as Tarski proceeds to do. So for this section of the paper,
Tarski allows one and the same sentence to be given different interpretations;
this is the exception to the general claim that his object language sentences
are fully interpreted. But Tarski stays on the straight and narrow: he talks
about truth only in the special case where AA is the class of all individuals.
For other values of AA, he speaks not of truth but of correctness in the domain
AA. These truth or correctness definitions dont fall out of a definition of
satisfaction. In fact they go by a much less direct route, which Tarski
describes as a purely accidental possibility that relies on the specific
peculiarities of the particular object language. There is no hope of giving a
definition of satisfaction by recursion on the complexity of formulas. The
remedy is to note that the explicit form of Tarskis truth definition in Section
2.1 above didnt require a recursive definition; it needed only that the
conditions on the satisfaction relation SS pin it down uniquely. For Henkins
first style of language this is still true, though the reason is no longer the
well-foundedness of the syntax. For Henkins second style of language, at least
in Hintikkas notation (independence friendly logic), the syntax is
well-founded, but the displacement of the quantifier scopes means that the
usual quantifier clauses in the definition of satisfaction no longer work. How
can we analyze satisfaction? The answer to this question is in some ways
reminiscent to our answer of how to construct a theory of truth for a language
with only finitely many sentences. So see how, first suppose that our language
has only three Namess and three predicates, Bob, Jane, and Nancy and is nice,
is mean, and is lazy. We can then give the following analysis, indeed,
definition, of satisfaction. An item I satisfies predicate p ≡df [(p=is nice
and i is nice) ∨ (n=is mean and i
is mean) ∨ (n=is lazy and i
is lazy)] There is an analogy between the material-adequacy constraint which Tarski
set on the theory of truth, and similar constraints which we should expect a
definition of satisfaction to meet. Just as a theory of truth should imply
every instance of S is 1 in L iff S so we should expect our theory of
satisfaction to imply every instance of the following schema. I satisfies is F
in L iff i is F. We arrive at Tarskis first-order definition as a definition of
satisfaction which makes no use of concepts other than those employed in the
object-language itself. By stress, Grice means suprasegmental phonology, but he
was too much of a philosopher to let that jargon affect him!
IMPLICATUM: This is truth-functional Grice. For
substitutional-quantificational Grice we have to wait for his treatment of the.
In Prolegomena, Grice had quoted verbatim from Strawsons infamous idea that
there is a SENSE of inferrability with if. While the lecture covers much more
than if (He only said if; Oh, no, he said a great deal more than that! the
title was never meant to be original. Grice in fact provides a rational
justification for the three connectives (and, or, and if) and before that, the
unary functor not. Embedding, Indicative conditionals: embedding, 1971, Not and
If, Sinton on Grice on denials of indicative conditionals, not,
if. Strawson had elaborated on what he felt was a divergence between
Whiteheads and Russells horseshoe, and if. Grice thought Strawsons observations
could be understood in terms of entailment + implicatum (Robbing Peter to Pay
Paul). But problems, as first noted to Grice, by Cohen, of Oxford, remain, when
it comes to the scope of the implicatum within the operation of, say, negation.
Analogous problems arise with implicata for the other earlier dyadic functors,
and and or, and Grice looks for a single explanation of the phenomenon.
The qualification indicative is modal. Ordinary language allows for if
utterances to be in modes other than the imperative. Counter-factual, if you
need to be philosophical krypto-technical, Subjectsive is you are more of a
classicist! Grice took a cavalier to the problem: Surely it wont do to say You
couldnt have done that, since you were in Seattle, to someone who figuratively
tells you hes spend the full summer cleaning the Aegean stables. This, to
philosophers, is the centerpiece of the lectures. Grice takes good care of not,
and, or, and concludes with the if of the title. For each, he finds a métier,
alla Cook Wilson in Statement and Inference. And they all connect with
rationality. So he is using material from his Oxford seminars on the principle
of conversational helpfulness. Plus Cook Wilson makes more sense at Oxford than
at Harvard! The last bit, citing Kripke and Dummett, is meant as jocular. What
is important is the teleological approach to the operators, where a note should
be made about dyadicity. In Prolegomena, when he introduces the topic, he omits
not (about which he was almost obsessed!). He just gives an example for and (He
went to bed and took off his dirty boots), one for or (the garden becomes
Oxford and the kitchen becomes London, and the implicatum is in terms, oddly,
of ignorance: My wife is either in Town OR Country,making fun of Town AND
Country), and if. His favourite illustration for if is Cock Robin: If the
Sparrow did not kill him, the Lark did! This is because Grice is serious about
the erotetic, i.e. question/answer, format Cook Wilson gives to things, but he
manages to bring Philonian and Megarian into the picture, just to impress! Most
importantly, he introduces the square brackets! Hell use them again in
Presupposition and Conversational Implicature and turns them into subscripts in
Vacuous Namess. This is central. For he wants to impoverish the idea of the
implicatum. The explicitum is minimal, and any divergence is
syntactic-cum-pragmatic import. The scope devices are syntactic and eliminable,
and as he knows: what the eye no longer sees, the heart no longer grieves
for! The modal implicatum. Since Grice uses indicative, for the
title of his third James lecture (Indicative Conditionals) surely he implicates
subjunctive ‒ i.e. that someone might be thinking that he should
give an account of indicative*-cum-Subjectsive* if. This relates to an example
Grice gives in Causal theory, that he does not reproduce in Prolegomena. Grice
states the philosophical mistake as follows. What is actual is not also
possible. Grice seems to be suggesting that a Subjectsive conditional
would involve one or other of the modalities, he is not interested in
exploring. On the other hand, Mackie has noted that Grices conversationalist
hypothesis (Mackie quotes verbatim from Grices principle of conversational
helpfulness) allows for an explanation of the Subjectsive if that does not
involve Kripke-type paradoxes involving possible worlds, or other. In Causal
Theory, Grice notes that the issue with which he has been mainly concerned may
be thought rather a fine point, but it is certainly not an isolated one. There
are several philosophical theses or dicta which would he thinks need to be
examined in order to see whether or not they are sufficiently parallel to the
thesis which Grice has been discussing to be amenable to treatment of the same
general kind. An examples which occurs to me is the following. What is actual
is not also possible. I must emphasise that I am not saying that this example
is importantly similar to the thesis which I have been criticizing, only that,
for all I know, it may be. To put the matter more generally, the position
adopted by Grices objector seems to Grice to involve a type of manoeuvre which
is characteristic of more than one contemporary mode of philosophizing. He is
not condemning that kind of manoeuvre. He is merely suggesting that to embark
on it without due caution is to risk collision with the facts. Before we rush
ahead to exploit the linguistic nuances which we have detected, we should make
sure that we are reasonably clear what sort of nuances they are. If was also of
special interest to Grice for many other reasons. He defends a dispositional account
of intending that in terms of ifs and cans. He considers akrasia conditionally.
He explored the hypothetical-categorical distinction in the buletic mode. He
was concerned with therefore as involved with the associated if of
entailment.
COMMUNICATION: This is
Grice’s reply to Popular Ogden. They want to know what the meaning of meaning
is? Heres Grices Oxononian response, with a vengeance! Grice is not an animist
nor a mentalist, even modest. While he allows for natural phenomena to
mean (smoke means fire), meaning is best ascribed to some utterer, where this
meaning is nothing but the intentions behind his utterance. This is the
fifth James lecture. Grice was careful enough to submit it to The Philosophical
Review, since it is a strictly philosophical development of the views expressed
in Meaning which Strawson had submitted on Grices behalf to the same Review and
which had had a s. of responses by various philosophers. Among these
philosophers is Strawson himself in Intention and convention in the the theory
of speech acts, also in The Philosophical Review. Grice quotes from very
many other philosophers in this essay, including: Urmson, Stampe,
Strawson, Schiffer, and Searle. Strawson is especially relevant since
he started a s. of alleged counter-examples with his infamous example of the
rat-infested house. Grice particularly treasured Stampes alleged
counter-example involving his beloved bridge! Avramides earns a D. Phil Oxon.
on that, under Strawson! This is Grices occasion to address some of the
criticisms ‒ in the form of alleged counter-examples, typically, as
his later reflections on epagoge versus diagoge note ‒ by Urmson,
Strawson,and other philosophers associated with Oxford, such as Searle, Stampe,
and Schiffer. The final analysandum is pretty complex (of the type that he did
find his analysis of I am hearing a sound complex in Personal
identity ‒ hardly an obstacle for adopting it), it became yet
another target of attack by especially New-World philosophers in the pages of
Mind, Nous, and other journals, This is officially the fifth James lecture.
Grice takes up the analysis of meaning he had presented way back at the Oxford
Philosophical Society. Motivated mainly by Urmsons and Strawsons attack in
Intention and convention in speech acts, that offered an alleged
counter-example to the sufficiency of Grices analysis, Grice ends up
introducing so many intention that he almost trembled. He ends up seeing
meaning as a value-paradeigmatic concept, perhaps never realisable in a
sublunary way. But it is the analysis in this particular essay where he is at
his formal best. He distinguishes between protreptic and exhibitive utterances,
and also modes of correlation (iconic, conventional). He symbolises the utterer
and the addressee, and generalises over the type of psychological state,
attitude, or stance, meaning seems to range (notably indicative vs.
imperative). He formalises the reflexive intention, and more importantly, the
overtness of communication in terms of a self-referential recursive intention
that disallows any sneaky intention to be brought into the picture of meaning-constitutive
intentions. By uttering x the utterer U means that ψb-d p iff (Ǝφ) (Ǝf) (Ǝc):
I. The utterer U utters x intending x to be such that anyone who has φ will think that (i) x has f (ii) f
is correlated in way c with ψ-ing that p (iii) (Ǝφ): U intends x to be such that anyone who has φ will think, via thinking (i) and (ii), that U
ψ-s that p (iv) in view of (3), U ψ-s that p; and II (operative only for
certain substituends for ψb-d) U utters x intending that, should there
actually be anyone who has φ, he
will, via thinking (iv), himself ψ that p; and III. It is not the case
that, for some inference-element E, U intends x to be such that anyone who
has φ will both (i) rely
on E in coming to ψ (or think that U ψ-s) that p and (ii) think that (Ǝ φ): U intends x to be such that anyone
who has φ will come to ψ (or think that U ψ-s) that p without relying on E. Grice
thought he had dealt with Logic and conversation enough! So he feels of
revising his Meaning. After all, Strawson had had the cheek to publish Grices
Meaning and then go on to criticize it in Intention and convention in speech
acts. So this is Grices revenge, and he wins! He ends with the most elaborate
theory of mean that an Oxonian could ever hope for. And to provoke the
informalists such as Strawson (and his disciples at Oxford – led by Strawson)
he pours existential quantifiers like the plague! He manages to quote from
Urmson, whom he loved! No word on Peirce, though, who had originated all this!
His implicature: Im not going to be reprimanted in informal discussion about my
misreading Peirce at Harvard! The concluding note is about artificial
substitutes for iconic representation, and meaning as a human institution. Very
grand.
COMMUNICATION: This is
Grices metabolical projection of utterers meaning to apply to anything OTHER
than utterers meaning, notably a token of the utterers expression and a TYPE of
the utterers expression, wholly or in part. Its not like he WANTS to do it, he
NEEDS it to give an account of implicatum. The phrase utterer is meant to
provoke. Grice thinks that speaker is too narrow. Surely you can mean by just
uttering stuff! This is the sixth James lecture, as published in The
Foundations of Language. As it happens, it became a popular lecture, seeing
that Searle selected this from the whole set for his Oxford reading in
philosophy, The philosophy of language. It is also the essay cited by Chomsky
in his influential John Locke lectures. Chomsky takes Grice to be a
behaviourist, even along Skinners lines, which provoked a reply by Suppes,
later reprinted in P(hilosophical) G((rounds of) R(ationality:) I(ntentions,)
C(ategories,) E(nds) (In The New World, the H. P. was often given in a more
simplified form.). Grice wants to keep on playing. In Meaning, he had said
x means that p is surely reducible to utterer U means that p. In this lecture,
he lectures us as to how to proceed. In so doing he invents this or that
procedure: some basic, some resultant. When Chomsky reads the reprint in
Searles Philosophy of Language, he cries: Behaviourist! Skinnerian! It was
Suppes who comes to Grices defence. Surely the way Grice uses expressions like
resultant procedure are never meant in the strict behaviourist way. Suppes
concludes that it is much fairer to characterise Grice as an intentionalist.
Published in The Foundations of Language, ed. by Staal, Repr.in Searle, The
Philosophy of Language, Oxford, the sixth James Lecture, Foundations of
Language, resultant procedure, basic procedure. Staal asked Grice to
publish the sixth James lecture for a newish periodical publication of whose
editorial board he was a member. The fun thing is Grice complied! This is
Grices shaggy-dog story. He does not seem too concerned about resultant
procedures. As hell later say, Surely I can create Deutero-Esperanto and become
its master! For Grice, the primacy is the idiosyncratic, particularized utterer
in this or that occasion. He knows a philosopher craves for generality, so he
provokes the generality-searcher with divisions and sub-divisions of mean. But
his heart does not seem to be there, and he is just being overformalistic and
technical for the sake of it. I am glad that Putnam, of all people, told me in
an aside, Youre being too formal, Grice. I stopped with symbolism since!
IMPLICATURE: A rather
obscure exploration on the connection of semiotics and philosophical
psychology. Grice is aware that there is an allegation in the air about a
possible vicious circle in trying to define category of expression in terms of
a category of representation. He does not provide a solution to the problem
which hell take up in his Method in philosophical psychology, in his role of
President of the American Philosophical Association. It is THE IMPLICATURE
behind the lecture that matters, since Grice will go back to it, notably in the
Retrospective Epilogue. For Grice, its all rational enough. Theres a pirot, in
a situation, say of danger – a bull ‒. He perceives the bull. The bulls attack
causes this perception. Bull! the Pirot1 G1 screams, and causes
in Pirot2 G2 a rearguard movement. So where is the circularity?
Some pedants would have it that Bull cannot be understood in a belief about a
bull which is about a bull. Not Grice. It is nice that he brought back
implicature, which had become obliterated in the lectures, back to title
position! But it is also noteworthy, that these are not explicitly rationalist
models for implicature. He had played with a model, and an explanatory one at
that, for implicature, in his Oxford seminar, in terms of a principle of
conversational helpfulness, a desideratum of conversational clarity, a
desideratum of conversational candour, and two sub-principles: a principle of
conversational benevolence, and a principle of conversational self-interest!
Surely Harvard could be spared of the details!
No comments:
Post a Comment