We might then formulate a rough general
principle which participants will be expected (ceteris paribus) to observe,
namely: Make your conversational contribution such as is required, at the stage
at which it occurs, by the accepted purpose or direction of the talk exchange
in which you are engaged. One might label this the COOPEHATIVE PIUNCIPLE. On
the assumption that some such general principle as this is acceptable, one may
perhaps distinguish four categories under one or another of which will fall
certain more specific maxims and submaxims, the following of which will, in
general, yield results in accordance with the Cooperative Principle. Echoing
Kant, I call these categories Quantity, Quillity, Relation, and Manner. The
category of QUANTITY relates to the quantity of information to be provided, and
under it fall the following maxims: 1. Make your contribution as informative as
is required (for the current purposes of the exchange). 2. Do not make your
contribution more informative than is required. • 46 H. P. Grice (The second
maxim is disputable; it might be said that to be overinfoimative is not a
transgression of the CP but merely a waste of time. However, it might be answered
that such overinformativeness may be confusing in that it is liable to raise
side issues; and there may also be an indirect effect, in that the hearers may
be misled as a result of thinking that there is some particular POINT in the
provision of the excess of information. However this may be, there is perhaps a
different reason for doubt about the admission of this second maxim, namely,
that its effect will be secured by a later maxim, which concems relevance.)
Under the category of QUALITY falls a supennaxim-'Try to make your contribution
one that is true' -and two more specific maxims: 1. Do not say what you believe
to be false. 2. Do not say that for which you lack adequate evidence. Under the
category of RELATION I place a single maxim, namely, 'Be relevant.' Though the
maxim itself is terse, its formulation conceals a number of problems that
exercise me a good deal: questions about what different kinds and focuses of
relevance there may be, how these shift in the course of a talk exchange, how
to allow for the fact that subjects of conversation are legitimately changed,
and so on. I find the treatment of such questions exceedingly difficult, and I
hope to revert to them in a later work. Finally, under the category of MANNER,
which I understand as relating not (like the previous categories) to what is
said but, rather, to HOW what is said is to be said, I include the
supermaxim-'Be perspicuous' -and various maxims such as: 1. Avoid obscurity of
expression. 2. Avoid ambiguity. 3. Be brief (avoid unnecessary prolixity). 4.
Be orderly. And one might need others. It is obvious that the observance of
some of these maxims is a matter of less urgency than is the observance of
others; a man who has expressed himself with undue prolixity would, in general,
be open to milder comment than would a man who has said something he believes
to be false. Indeed, it might be felt that the importance of at least the first
maxim of Quality is such that it should not be included in a scheme of the kind
I am constructing; other maxims come into operation only on the assumption that
this maxim of Quality is satisfied. While this may be correct, so far as the
generation of ' I Logic and Conversation 47 implicatures is concerned it seems
to play a role not totally different from the other maxims, and it will be
convenient, for the present at least, to treat it as a member of the list of
maxims. There are, of course, all sorts of other maxims (aesthetic, social, or
moral in character), such as 'Be polite', that are also nom1ally observed by
participants in talk exchanges, and these may also generate nonconventional
implicatures. The conversational maxims, however, and the conversational
implicatures connected with them, are specially connected (I hope) with the
particular purposes that talk (and so, talk exchange) is adapted lo serve and
is prilllarily employed to serve. I have stated my maxims as if this purpose
were a maximally effective exchange of information; this specification is, of
course, too narrow, and the scheme needs to be generalized to allow for such
general purposes as influencing or directing the actions of others. As one of
my avowed aims is to see talking as a special case or variety of purposive,
indeed rational, behavior, it may be worth noting that the specific expectations
or presumptions connected with at least some of the foregoing maxims have their
analogues in the sphere of transactions that are not talk exchanges. I list
briefly one such analog for each conversational category. 1. Quantity. If you
are assisting me to mend a car, I expect your contribution to be neither more
nor less than is required; if, for example, at a particular stage I need four
screws, I expect you to hand me four, rather than two or six. 2. Quality. I
expect your contributions to be genuine and not spurious. If I need sugar as an
ingredient in the cake you are assisting me to make, I do not expect you to
hand me salt; if I need a spoon, I do not expect a trick spoon made of rubber.
3. Relation. I expect a partner's contribution to be appropriate to immediate
needs at each stage of the transaction; if I am mixing ingredients for a cake,
I do not expect to be handed a good book, or even an oven cloth (though this
might be an appropriate contribution at a later stage). 4. Manner. I expect a partner
to make it clear what contribution he is making, and to execute his performance
with reasonable dispatch. These analogies are relevant to what I regard as a
fundamental question about the CP and its attendant maxims, namely, what the
basis is for the assumption which we seem to make, and on which (I hope) it
will appear that a great range of implicatures depend, that talkers will in
general (ceteris paribus and in the absence of indica- .. 48 H. P. Grice tions
to the contrary) proceed in the manner that these principles prescribe. A dull
but, no doubt at a certain level, adequate answer is that it is just a
well-recognized empirical fact that people DO behave in these ways; they have
learned to do so in childhood and not lost the habit of doing so; and, indeed,
it would involve a good deal of effort to make a radical departure from the
habit. It is much easier, for example, to tell the truth than to invent lies. I
am, however, enough of a rationalist to want to find a basis that underlies
these facts, undeniable though they may be; I would like to be able to think of
the standard type of conversational practice not merely as something that all
or most do IN FACT follow but as something that it is HEASONAllLE for us to
follow, that we SHOULD NOT abandon. For a time, I was attracted by the idea
that observance of the CP and the maxims, in a talk exchange, could be thought
of as a quasi-contractual matter, with parallels outside the realm of
discourse. If you pass by when I am struggling with my stranded car, I no doubt
have some degree of expectation that you will offer help, but once you join me
in tinkering under the hood, my expectations become stronger and take more
specific forms (in the absence of indications that you are merely an
incompetent meddler); and talk exchanges seemed to me to exhibit,
characteristically, certain features that jointly distinguish cooperative
transactions: 1. The participants have some common immediate aim, like getting
a car mended; their ultimate aims may, of course, be independent and even in
conflict-each may want to get the car mended in order to drive off, leaving the
other stranded. In characteristic talk exchanges, there is a common aim even
if, as in an over-the-wall chat, it is a second-order one, namely, that each party
should, for the time being, identify himself with the transitory conversational
interests of the other. 2. The contributions of the participants .should be
dovetailed, mutually dependent. 3. There is some sort of understanding (which
may be explicit but which is often tacit) that, otl1er things being equal, the
transaction should continue in appropriate style unless both parties are
agreeable that it should terminate. You do not just shove off or start doing
something else. But while some such quasi-contractual basis as this may apply
to some cases, there are too many types of exchange, like quarreling and letter
writing, that it fails to fit comfortably. In any case, one feels that the
talker who is irrelevant or obscure has primarily let Logic and Conversation 49
down not his audience but himself. So I would like t< be able to show that
observance of the CP and maxims is reasonal de (rational) along the following
lines: that any one who cares about the goals that are central to
conversation/communication (e.g., giving and receiving information, influencing
and being influenced by others) must be expected to have an interest, given
suitable circumstances, in participation in talk exchanges that will be
profitable only on the assumption that they are conducted in general accordance
with the CP and the maxims. Whether any such conclusion can be reached, I am
uncertain; in any case, I am fairly sure that I cannot reach it until I am a
good deal clearer about the nature of relevance and of the circumstances in
which it is required. It is now time to show the connection between the CP and
maxims, on the one hand, and conversational implicature on the other. A
participant in a talk exchange may fail to fulfill a maxim in various ways,
which include the following: 1. He may quietly and unostentatiously VIOLATE a
ma;.,im; if so, in some cases he will be liable to mislead. 2. He may OPT OUT
from the operation both of the maxim and of the CP; he may say, indicate, or
allow it to become plai 1 that he is unwilling to cooperate in the way the
maxim requires. I le may say, for example, I cannot say more; my lips are
sealed. 3. He may be faced by a CLASH: He may be unable, for example, to
fulfill the first maxim of Quantity (Be as informative as is required) without
violating the second maxim of Quality (Have aclequate evidence for what you
say). 4. He may FLOUT a maxim; that is, he may BLATANTL. fail to fulfill it. On
the assumption that the speaker is able to fulfill the maxim and to do so
without violating another maxim (because oi a clash), is not opting out, and is
not, in view of the blatancy of his pt~rformance, trying to mislead, the hearer
is faced with a minor problem: How can his saying what he did say be reconciled
with the supposition that he is observing the overall CP? This situation is one
that characteristically gives rise to a conversational implicature; and when a
conversational implicature is generated in this way, I shall say that a maxim
is being EXPLOITED. I am now in a position to characterize the notion of
conversational implicature. A man who, by (in, when) saying (or making as if to
say) that p has implicated that q, may be said to have conversationally
implicated that q, PROVIDED THAT (1) he is to be presumed to be ob- - 50 H. P.
Grice serving the conversational maxims, or at least the cooperative principle;
(2) the supposition that he is aware that, or thinks that, q is required in
order to make his saying or making as if to say p (or doing so in THOSE terms)
consistent with this presumption; and (3) the speaker thinks (and would expect
the hearer to think that the speaker thinks) that it is within the competence
of the hearer to work out, or grasp intuitively, that the sup:_)osition
mentioned in (2) IS required. Apply this to my initial example, to B's remark
that C has not yet been to prison. In a suitable setting A might reason as
follows: '(1) B has apparently violated the maxim 'Be relevant' and so may he
regarded as having flouted one of the maxims conjoining perspicuity, yet I have
no reason to suppose that he is opting out from the operation of the CP; (2)
given the circumstances, I can regard his irrelevance as only apparent if, and
only if, I suppose him to think that C is potentially dishonest; (3) B knows
that I am capable of working out step (2). So B implicates that C is
potentially dishonest.' The presence of a conversational implicature must be
capable of being worked out; for even if it can in fact be intuitively grasped,
unless the intuition is replaceable by an argument, the implicature (if present
at all) will not count as a CONVERSATIONAL implicature; it will be a
CONVENTIONAL implicature. To work out that a particular conversational
implicature is present, the hearer will reply on the following data: (1) the
conventional meaning of the words used, together with the identity of any
references that may be involved; (2) the CP and its maxims; (3) the context,
linguistic or otherwise, of the utterance; (4) other items of background
knowledge; and (5) the fact (or supposed fact) that all relevant items falling
under the previous headings are available to both participants and both
participants know or assume this to be the case. A general pattern for the
working out of a conversational implicature might be given as follows: 'He has
said that p; there is no reason to suppose. that he is not observing the
maxims, or at least the CP; he could not be doing this unless he thought that
q; he knows (and knows that I know that he knows) that I can see that the
supposition that he thinks that q IS required; he has done nothing to stop me
thinking that q; he intends me to think, or is at least willing to allow me to
think, that q; and so he has implicated that q.'
Wednesday, April 29, 2020
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment