Speranza
Context and Implicature
Luciana Benotti and Patrick Blackburn
Abstract This paper introduces Paul Grice’s notion of conversational implicature.
The basic ideas — the cooperative principle, the maxims of conversation, and the
contrast between implicature and presupposition — make it clear that conversational
implicature is a highly contextualized form of language use that has a lot in common
with non-linguistic behavior. But what exactly is its role? We invite the reader
to view conversational implicature as a way of negotiating meaning in conversational
contexts. Along the way, the reader will learn something of the theoretical
properties of implicatures, why they are tricky to work with empirically, what can
be done with them computationally, and (perhaps) where future research on the topic
may lead. But the basic message of the paper is actually quite simple: context and
conversational implicature are highly intertwined, and unravelling their interactions
is a challenging and worthwhile research goal.
1 Introduction
The notion of conversational implicature is important in both philosophy of language
[Grice, 1989; Davis, 2010] and pragmatics [Horn, 2004; Levinson, 1983],
the branch of linguistics which studies how human languages are actually used. The
key ideas were first presented in 1967 in Paul Grice’s William James lectures at Harvard,
and eventually appeared in the paper Logic and Conversation [Grice, 1975].
The paper draws our attention to the fact that in typical linguistic exchanges, many
things are meant without being explicitly said, and attempts to explain how this is
possible. Let’s start with an example from Grice’s paper:
(1) Man standing by his car: I am out of petrol.
Passer-by: There is a garage around the corner.
Grice’s analysis runs as follows. The utterance made by the passer-by (let’s call
him B) wouldn’t have been relevant (to the conversational exchange) if B knew that
the garage was closed or that it had run out of petrol. If B is a local person who
knows about local garages, it is thus reasonable to assume that B is directing the
man standing by the car (let’s call him A) to a garage that is open and currently
selling petrol. That is, according to Grice, during the exchange (1), B made the
conversational implicature (2):
(2) The garage is open and has petrol to sell.
Well, so far, so good. But isn’t this just the sort of thing that goes on all the
time? Where’s the mystery? If this is all there is to conversational implicature, what
exactly requires explanation? What makes the concept so important? And why is it
considered difficult?
As we hope to make clear, even this little exchange conceals many problems.
Conversational implicature involves highly contextualized inferences that draw on
multiple sources of information. For instance, in the garage example, presumably
the visual information provided by A standing beside his stationary car plays an
important role in initiating the exchange. Moreover, by their very nature — we
will soon explain what we mean by this — implicatures tend to be resistant to the
usual tools of empirical linguistic investigation. Furthermore, they are ubiquitous:
get two people talking, and the conversational implicature flies thick and fast. In
short, Grice’s garage example is the tip of a large iceberg concerning meaning and
inference in context. In the pages that follow, we show how deep it extends below the
surface, and discuss recent attempts to reveal its contours theoretically, empirically
and computationally.
We proceed as follows. In Section 2 we present conversational implicature as a
form of contextualized inference, and make a first pass at explaining why it tends to
resist the usual tools of empirical linguistic analysis. In Section 3 we sketch some
of Grice’s ideas on the subject, notably his cooperative principle and his conversational
maxims. In Section 4 we note five key theoretical properties of conversational
implicature, and in Section 5 we discuss further difficulties with empirical
work. This leads us to one of the main points we wish to make: conversational
implicature is a form of negotiation. In Section 6, we sketch the relevance of clarification
requests to this conception, and in Section 7 we briefly note some recent
computational work. Section 8 concludes with a nod to the future.
Computational implicature is a huge subject, one that has been investigated from
many angles. We cannot hope to cover them all, and have opted instead to present a
birds-eye-view of relevance to researchers interested in context. But there are many
good points of entry to the topic. For a start, Grice’s own Logic and Conversation is
a must: it is clear, accessible and covers many topics we do not have space to consider,
but we’d also like to draw the reader’s attention to his Further Notes on Logic
and Conversation; these conveniently appear as Chapters 2 and 3 respectively of
Context and Implicature 3
[Grice, 1989]. Moreover, excellent surveys exist: we particularly recommend Chapter
3 of Levinson’s textbook Pragmatics [Levinson, 1983]. Furthermore, searching
for ‘conversational implicature’ in the (free) online Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
will lead to several informative and up-to-date articles (for example, [Davis,
2010]) with detailed bibliographical information.
2 Implicature as contextual inference
In this section we have two main goals: to convince the reader that conversational
implicatures are a highly general form of contextualized inference, and to make a
first attempt to explain why conversational implicatures tend to be resistant to standard
empirical linguistic techniques. A good way into the discussion is to compare
conversational implicatures with what linguists call presuppositions.
Presuppositions are another ubiquitous form of inference, one that all known
human languages exploit. Consider the following sentence. Imagine it is uttered to
you out of the blue, with no prior conversational context:
(3) Anthony regrets that Brenda is pregnant.
Now, you know nothing about Anthony or Brenda or who they are or what their life
is like. But by reading this sentence (let’s assume that you don’t have any reason to
distrust its source) you have effortlessly internalized a certain piece of information:
namely, that Brenda is pregnant. But now consider the following sentence:
(4) Anthony does not regret that Brenda is pregnant.
Once again, you have once internalized the information (or: accommodated the
information, as a linguist would say) that Brenda is pregnant. And this is surprising
because it shows that we are dealing with a very strange form of inference indeed. It
is certainly not an ordinary logical inference. In ordinary logical inference, replacing
a positive premise with its negation will typically destroy the inference. But here
replacing ‘regrets’ with ‘does not regret’ has no effect: in both cases the inference
to Brenda’s pregnancy goes through immediately.
Such presuppositions are ubiquitous, and their ability to survive negations is one
of their better known characteristics. Consider the following pair of sentences
(5) Candy knows that Dave is dead.
Candy does not know that Dave is dead.
Once again — positive or negative — we infer the same information: Dave is dead.
Now, presupposition is an interesting phenomena. Like conversational implicature
it is a ubiquitous fact about language in action. But in at least one crucial respect
it is simpler than implicature: we can point to concrete linguistic triggers that
set the presuppositional process in motion, no what matter the context is. In the
first pair of examples, the trigger is the word ‘regret’. In the second pair of examples,
the trigger is the word ‘knows’. Part of the effect of using these words —
4 Luciana Benotti and Patrick Blackburn
part of their meaning — is that they induce presuppositional phenomena of this
sort, and every competent language user instinctively knows how to make good
use of this. Now, it should be stressed that presupposition is not a simple phenomena,
nonetheless, we now have detailed theoretical accounts of it [Beaver, 2001;
Geurts, 1999] and understand how to incorporate presuppositional phenomena into
computational work [Venhuizen et al., 2013; Bos, 2003; Blackburn et al., 2001].
And much of this understanding stems from the basic fact just noted: we can trace
presuppositions to specific linguistic locations, namely, certain trigger words (and
grammatical constructions).
But conversational implicatures can’t be linguistically localized in the same way.
As we said earlier, conversational implicatures are highly contextualized inferences,
capable of exploiting multiple information sources. Consider Grice’s garage example
again. First, and most obviously, it rests on an assumed common knowledge
context: both A and B need to share the knowledge that “petrol can be bought at
open garages which have not run out of petrol”. Secondly, this example draws on
the situational context, most obviously on B knowing that the garage is around the
corner and that A can walk there. But a lot also hinges on the fact that we are in a
conversational context. It is quite obvious that the implicature could not have been
triggered without considering the immediate conversational context: if A had said
“Where do you come from?” instead of “I am out of petrol”, B’s utterance would
have had a quite different meaning. But even more basic components of the interaction
context are crucial: A and B take for granted that the other is a language user,
with intentions and goals, who may be prepared to take part in a cooperative exchange
in order to overcome undesired states such as “being out of petrol”. In fact,
as we shall soon discuss, Grice called one of the central principles driving conversational
implicature the cooperative principle. Moreover, other contextual parameters
may play a role in how the scenario unfolds, such as information about race, gender
and status (is A unshaven, sloppily dressed, and standing by a beat-up old car, or is
he wearing a suit and tie and standing by a spiffy new Mercedes?).
So: conversational implicatures are a highly contextualized form of inference.
Moreover (unlike presuppositions) there is no simple linguistic trigger with relatively
well defined rules which we can analyze to ‘solve the implicature problem’
in the general case. There is no linguistic trigger in the garage example that sets the
implicative process in motion. For example, it would be highly implausible to claim
that B’s behavior is induced by the word ‘garage’, or by any other word in the exchange
for that matter. Words like ‘regrets’ and ‘know’ induce presuppositions, but
Grice’s little scenario has more complex origins. The same scenario would work if
we used the words ‘service station’ or ‘petrol station’ instead of ‘garage’. Moreover,
the initial trigger may well have been non-linguistic: the sight of A (perhaps in his
suit and tie) standing forlornly by his new Mercedes may have been the spark that
set the little scene in motion.
Conversational implicatures are, in general, not closely tied to the inner-workings
of the lexical system in the way that presuppositions are. Rather, they are a type
of behavior exemplified by agents with intentions and goals — but special agents,
namely human beings, who have a highly refined form of behavior in their arsenal:
Context and Implicature 5
linguistic behavior. We might say: conversational implicature constitutes a large
part of the meaning conveyed and received by goal seeking, linguistically competent
agents when they interact in a given context. Hopefully this goes some way towards
explaining why conversational implicatures are interesting and important — and
why they are highly relevant to the study of context. But note the downside: it also
tells why they are likely to be be resistant to straightforward empirical linguistic
investigation. We can’t compile a list of trigger words (as we can for presupposition)
and explore their effects in a corpus of example sentences. As we have said, in
general it is difficult or impossible to point to critical lexical or grammatical triggers
when it comes to conversational implicature, because so much of what is going on in
conversational implicature is not specifically linguistic behavior; rather, it’s part of
the general human behavior displayed by linguistically adept agents. It spills over
into, draws richly on, and is guided by, the surrounding context in all its variety. So
empirical investigation will be a tricky business, a point we will return to later.
3 Grice on conversational implicature
We now outline Grice’s account of conversational implicature, and in particular his
cooperative principle and the conversational maxims. We draw attention to the possibility
of observing, flouting and violating maxims; these are not merely practical
distinctions, they are also helpful in understanding Grice’s motives. We further note
that the conversational maxims are linked to non-linguistic behavior, that they can
be used to classify conversational implicatures, and draw the reader’s attention to
both relevance implicatures, the conversational implicatures that embody contextual
inference in its most general form, and scalar implicatures, those that probably
embody it least. Our discussion will establish some standard ideas and terminology
and pave the way for our discussion in subsequent sections. Page references here
are to the version of Logic and Conversation in [Grice, 1989].
At the heart of Grice’s discussion lies the following principle (see page 26):
The cooperative principle: Make your contribution such as is required, at the stage at
which it occurs, by the accepted purpose or direction of the talk exchange in which you are
engaged.
In addition, he presents the following maxims (pages 26–27):
Maxims of Quantity:
(i) Make your contribution as informative as is required (for the current purposes of the
exchange).
(ii) Do not make your contribution more informative than is required.
Maxims of Quality: Try to make your contribution one that is true.
(i) Do not say what you believe to be false.
(ii) Do not say that for which you lack adequate evidence.
The Maxim of Relevance: Be relevant.
6 Luciana Benotti and Patrick Blackburn
Maxims of Manner: Be perspicuous.
(i) Avoid obscurity.
(ii) Avoid ambiguity.
(iii) Be brief (avoid unnecessary prolixity).
(iv) Be orderly.
Grice calls the cooperative principle a “rough general principle” and it is clear
from his discussion on pages 26–28 that the maxims are a tentative attempt to understand
how human beings interact in conversation. But at this point, the reader may
have doubts. Aren’t the cooperative principle and the maxims far too neat and tidy?
They seem to describe an ideal world of effective, rational, maximally cooperative
conversational interaction. And, all too obviously, real life just isn’t like that at all.
But it is a mistake to dismiss Grice and conversational implicature on these
grounds. Grice is not suggesting that all human conversational interactions live up
to these principles, or even that it would be better if they did. Rather, Grice is trying
to indicate the existence of deep-seated norms of conversational interaction. Humans
are social animals. They interact. Moreover they are social animals graced (or
cursed) with the power of speech. Grice is suggesting (see page 29) that assumptions
somewhat like the cooperative principle or the maxims must guide this process. And
of course — as Grice himself points out —- what is expected of others swiftly becomes
a resource to be exploited. We may communicate by observing the maxims,
but sometimes we can communicate more effectively by deliberately flouting them;
we will give examples of both strategies shortly. Indeed, sometimes we may choose
to distance ourselves still further from communicative norms and deliberately violate
the maxims: tricksters and ironists thrive on the socially expected.
Grice views his conversational maxims as direct analogs of norms governing the
way we cooperate in non-linguistic settings. He is quite explicit on this point. As he
says on page 28:
[O]ne of my aims is to see talking as a special case of purposive, indeed, rational behavior. . .
and then lists analogies between the conversational maxims and physical actions.
For example, with regard to the Maxim of Quality, which says we should seek to
be truthful, he points out that if we are cooperating to make a cake, and I need
sugar, then I expect you to pass me sugar, and not (say) salt, and that if I need a
spoon for stirring the cake mixture, I expect you to hand me a real spoon not (say) a
trick spoon made of rubber. The strong analogy that Grice draws between linguistic
and non-linguistic behavior is important, and we shall return to it when we discuss
implicature as negotiation.
The maxims are also useful in that they give us a (somewhat rough-and-ready)
way of classifying conversational implicatures. Consider, for example, the maxims
of quantity. This has given rise to an extensive literature on what are now called
quantity or scalar implicatures (see, for example, [Hirschberg, 1985; Geurts,
2011]). Let’s briefly consider an example which we will return to in more detail
when we discuss empirical work. Consider the situation depicted in Figure 1 and
suppose I say to you (6).
Context and Implicature 7
B B B A A A C B C
Fig. 1 Illustration of the conversational implicature Not all of the B’s are in the box on the left.
(6) Some of the B’s are in the box on the left.
then I would often be taken as having implicated that
(7) Not all of the B’s are in the box on the left.
Why? The point is this. If I am observing the maxims, and in particular the Maxim
of Quantity that tells us to make your contribution as informative as is required then
I must be making the strongest claim possible. Logically, the claim that some of the
B’s are in the box on the left is compatible with the (logically stronger) claim that
they all are. So why did I not make the stronger claim? Well, assuming that I am
observing to the maxims, this must be because I was not in a position to (truthfully)
do so (and looking at the image we see that I was not, for there is a B in the box
on the right). Hence I implicated that not all the items are in the box on the left.
In short, assuming that conversational agents are observing the maxims gives us
explanatory power: it enables us to appeal to and reason about communicative goals
and intentions.
But so does flouting. Stephen Levinson has a nice example involving Maxims of
Manner (see page 104 of [Levinson, 1983]):
(8) A: Let’s get the kids something.
B: Okay, but I veto I-C-E-C-R-E-A-M-S
Why on earth would B spell out the word ice creams? This is not a perspicuous
presentation: indeed it’s (deliberately) obscure and prolix! And of course, every
parent knows why: the maxim has been flouted because B’s message is not simply
“Yes, I agree we should get the kids something”, but the more desperate “For God’s
sake let’s not get them whining for ice creams!”
The logic of flouting is interesting. Once again, it involves appealing to and reasoning
about communicative goals and intentions, but in a more subtle way: a flouting
seems to function as an invitation to look beyond the surface level of maxim
failure and to search for a deeper vein of cooperativity. Given such possibilities, it
is hardly surprising that many authors have found game theory (and related disciplines
which focus on strategic thinking) useful tools for exploring conversational
implicature; see [van Rooij, 2011] for a useful overview.
Finally, we remark that we can now see that conversational implicatures come in
all shapes and sizes. For example, the sort of scalar implicature involved in some of
the B’s are in the box on the left example is relatively specific, and is clearly tied
to the meaning of the word some — though as we shall learn later, this simple example
is not as innocent as it looks. Others, such as the garage example with which
we started, are more general. This is because the garage example is a relevance
8 Luciana Benotti and Patrick Blackburn
implicature, governed simply by the splendidly general: Be relevant! Some authors
(notably Deirdre Wilson and Dan Sperber [Wilson and Sperber, 2004]) have insisted
that the notion of relevance is the real gold in Grice’s work. Indeed, Grice himself
seems to be partly of this opinion. As he remarks on page 27:
Though the maxim itself is terse, its formulation conceals a number of problems that exercise
me a good deal: questions about what different kinds and focuses of relevance there
may be, how these shift in the course of a talk exchange, how to allow for the fact that the
subjects of conversation are legitimately changed, and so on. I find the treatment of such
questions exceedingly difficult, and I hope to revert to them in later work.
The problems involving relevance implicature remain exceedingly difficult to this
day; some of the hardest problems of contextual inference live there.
4 A little theory
So far, our discussion has been relatively informal; in this section we make it more
precise. We first give a definition of conversational implicature; this won’t play a role
in our subsequent work, but it will indicate how the role of context is made explicit
in formal pragmatics. Following this, we will briefly discuss five basic properties of
conversational implicatures; three of them will play a key role in the the concept of
negotiability introduced in the following section.
The following definition is adapted from [Hirschberg, 1985]. We have made explicit
the role of context and the role of the conversation participants as agents that
can modify context:
Definition 1. Proposition q is a conversational implicature of utterance U by agent
B in context C if and only if:
(i) B believes that it is mutual, public knowledge inC of all the discourse participants
that B is obeying the cooperative principle.
(ii) B believes that, to maintain (i) given U, the hearer will assume that B believes q
holds in C, or that C can be modified to bring about q.
(iii) B believes that it is mutual, public knowledge of all the discourse participants
that, to maintain (i) given U, the hearer will assume that B believes q holds in C,
or that C can be modified to bring about q.
What does this mean? Let’s return to the garage example, where B implicated
The garage is open and has petrol to sell (that is, q) by uttering There is a garage
around the corner (that is, U). If B believes it is common knowledge to all the
participants (namely A and B) that B is obeying the cooperative principle, and B
further believes that A will assume, on the basis of B’s utterance, that the garage is
open and has petrol to sell or that the context can be modified to bring those about–
for example, B can add, It is closed now but I know the owner and he can open it
for you, then q is an implicature of U. It’s a tricky definition, and we won’t pause
to discuss it further, but do note the following: the form of the definition, with its
Context and Implicature 9
explicit appeals to an agent’s beliefs and to what is mutual public knowledge make it
clear that implicature is being modeled as a form of epistemic reasoning that draws
on contextual knowledge.
Now let’s examine the properties of conversational implicatures, for these will
play an important role in our discussion. Hirschberg argues that we need to insist
that conversational implicatures have the following five: 1) deniability, 2) reinforceability,
3) non-lexicality, 4) non-detachability, and 5) calculability.
First, conversational implicatures are deniable without contradiction. Let’s stick
with Grice’s garage example. B can append material that is inconsistent with the
implicature — for example, B can add but I don’t know whether it’s open — and the
resulting exchange will not be contradictory. Indeed, the resulting exchange would
be extremely natural: B would be implicating potentially useful information about
the garage, but then expressing a reservation.
Second, note that B can also add material to the exchange that explicitly asserts
the implicature — and I know it’s open — without any sense that he is repeating
himself. That is, B can reinforce the implicature without redundancy. Indeed, once
again, this is very natural language use: we implicate the extra information and
then (if it seems important) ram the message home to make sure our conversational
partner gets the point.
Third, implicatures are non-lexical: they do not trace back to particular lexical
items. We have already mentioned this. For example, in Grice’s garage example,
the implicature is not triggered by any particular word in the exchange (such as
‘garage’) but is a result of the overall semantic content.
Fourth — again something we have discussed — since an implicature is attached
to the semantic content of what is said and not to the particular lexical items involved,
a conversational implicature cannot be detached from the utterance simply
by changing the words of the utterance by synonyms. B can replace each word in
his utterance with a word with the same meaning — he can say petrol station or
service station instead of garage — and the implicature will still go through. Note
that non-detachability and non-lexicality are not really two independent properties:
non-lexicality can only be tested by evaluating non-detachability. Basically, these
two properties are another way of getting at the basic point that conversational implicatures
are not part of the conventional meaning of the words uttered, but depend
on features of the conversational context.
Fifth and last, conversational implicatures are traditionally considered to be calculable.
Calculability means that the addressee should be able to infer the implicatures
of an utterance. For example, in the garage example, A should be able to infer
that B conversationally implicates that the garage is open and has petrol to sell.
Three of these properties will shortly return in the guise of negotiability. To help
motivate this concept, first some intriguing empirical results.
10 Luciana Benotti and Patrick Blackburn
5 Towards Negotiability
The empirical literature on conversational implicature is based almost entirely on
evidence obtained using the inference method [Chemla, 2009], a pragmatic-level
analog of the introspective method traditionally used in linguistics and philosophy
(basically, the introspective approach is to obtain native-speaker judgments on linguistic
examples). However, Geurts and Pouscoulous [2009] have shown that the
inference method is a biased tool when it comes to gathering data on conversational
implicatures. Let’s briefly consider the Geurts and Pouscoulous (henceforth G&P)
argument.
Consider the scalar implicature example we gave in Section 3. Experimenters
using the traditional inference paradigm might ask experimental subjects whether
they think that sentence (9a) implies sentence (9b):
(9) a. Some of the B’s are in the box on the left.
b. Not all of the B’s are in the box on the left.
Now, G&P argue that to ask oneself — or an experimental subject — whether or
not (9a) implies (9b) is already to suggest that it might be implied. That is, presenting
these two sentences to an experimental subject signals that whether or not all of
the B’s are in the box on the left is the significant issue — the issue at stake. In
conversation, the issues at stake are constructed as part of the exchange and are part
of the conversational context — for example, A needing petrol is the issue at stake
in Grice’s example.
Consider the image we used back in Section 3 reproduced in Figure 2.
B B B A A A C B C
Fig. 2 Illustration of the conversational implicature Not all of the B’s are in the box on the left.
In Section 3, when we discussed example (9), we carefully placed a B in the
right-hand box. Now, this is an effective way of explaining the concept of implicature:
it makes the implicature explicit and forces the reader to think about it. But the
inference method does much the same thing: it explicitly states the potential implicature
(9b) (though it does not show a picture as we did). That is, the implicature is
artificially put at stake; it is added to the conversational context. Is this really a good
way of investigating implicatures empirically? G&P argue that it is not: precisely
because it draws attention to what is at stake, the inference method may not tell us
much about how (9a) is interpreted in situations where (9b) is not at stake; that is,
when it is is not part of the context.
G&P investigated the matter experimentally. They did so by comparing the inference
method with what they call the verification method. In the verification version
of the previous experiment, subjects simply have to decide whether (9a) correctly
Context and Implicature 11
describes the situation shown in the Figure 3. Notice that the picture is intentionally
modified so that the implicature does not hold: all the Bs are in the left-hand box.
The experimental subject is simply asked whether some of the B’s are in the box on
the left is a good description of the depicted situation or not. Crucially, the potential
implicature not all of the B’s are in the box on the left is not mentioned to the
subject, he only sees the picture and the sentence (9a). In a nutshell, the verification
task attempts to minimize signaling of what is at stake. That is, it tries not to alter
the conversational context.
Someone who interprets (9a) as implicating (9b) should deny that (9a) gives a
correct description of the picture (for note: there are no Bs in the right-hand box, all
the Bs are in the left-hand box).
B B B A A A C C C
Fig. 3 It is the case that All of the B’s are in the box on the left, the implicature does not go through.
G&P’s results were striking. Participants detected the implicature that not all of
the B’s are in the box on the left only half as frequently under the verification condition
(34%) as they did twice under the inference condition (62%). The inference
task, which alters the context, does increase the rate of detection of conversational
implicatures, and the effect is substantial.
G&P show that the effect is even more evident in complex sentences such as
(10a) describing the situation depicted in Figure 4.
Fig. 4 One of the squares is connected to all of the circles, the implicature does not go through.
Someone who interprets (10a) as implicating (10b) should deny that (10a) gives
a correct description of the picture (for note: one of the squares is connected to all
of the circles).
12 Luciana Benotti and Patrick Blackburn
(10) a. All the squares are connected with some of the circles.
b. All the squares are connected with some but not all of the circles.
Studies carried out using these more complex sentences result in participants deriving
the conversational implicature (10b) from (10a) in 46% of the cases with
the inference method, and in 0% of the cases with the verification method! As we
have said before, empirical investigation of conversational implicatures is not easy.
G&P’s work shows another source of difficulty.
But what is the lesson we should draw? Is it simply that the verification method
is better than the inference method? We think not. G&P’s experiments show that
the inference method does not tell us much about how utterances are interpreted
when a certain issue (such as how we use the words ‘some’ and ‘all’) is not at stake.
However the verification method used by G&P has the opposite weakness: it does
not tell us much about how utterances should be interpreted when the issue is at
stake. In our view, what G&P’s experiments show is that whether or not an issue is
at stake is a crucial contextual factor when it comes to implicature.
Another interesting aspect of their work is that it concerns scalar implicatures.
Scalar implicatures are usually considered ‘better behaved’ than (say) relevance implicatures.
Clearly the above scalar implicatures have something to do with how we
interpret the logical words ‘some’ and ‘all’, and such inferences are often felt to be
less contextually sensitive than full-blown relevance implicatures such as Grice’s
garage examples. And this makes G&P’s results even more intriguing: even allegedly
simple and well-understood implicatures such as scalar implicatures involving
‘some’ and ‘all’ can be dramatically manipulated by playing with the context.
G&P’s experiments simply change one pragmatic factor — whether something is at
stake or not — and the effects are striking.
And this brings us, at last, to the heart of the paper, and back to the work of Paul
Grice. In conversation, whether an issue is at stake or not is naturally determined
by what Grice calls “the accepted purpose or direction of the talk exchange”. But
how is this accepted purpose or direction established? Quite simply, by negotiation.
Instead of asking “How did B generate the implicature that the garage is open and
had petrol to sell?” we need to ask ”How did the conversational agents arrive at a
state of mutual understanding?” or at least, a mutual understanding sufficient for the
contextually relevant purposes.
Recall the properties of of deniability and reinforceability we noted in the previous
section. As we saw, these are natural conversational options for expressing
degrees of certainty and uncertainty. Indeed, they are not so much two independent
properties as two sides of the same coin: they reflect the fact that implicatures
are often open-ended contributions to an exchange, potential contributions that the
speaker can usefully deny or reinforce.
And it’s not just the speaker who can do this. Recall calculability: implicatures
are meant to be calculable by the hearer. But in conversational interaction, uncertainty
abounds. Which potential contributions are on offer? The hearer needs tools to
clarify. And what are these tools? The same options of deniability and reinforceability
that are available to the speaker. For example, A can naturally continue Grice’s
garage example with — I went there, it’s closed — thereby denying the conversa-
Context and Implicature 13
tional implicature. But A can also continue the exchange by reinforcing the implicature
— oh, and it must be open because it’s only 3pm! I’ll go there right away!
Putting it together: deniability, reinforceability and calculability can be summarized
by saying that computational implicatures are negotiable. Implicature is not
a one way flow of information from speaker to hearer. Rather, speaker and hearer
negotiate — they deny, reinforce, calculate, and switch roles as the conversation
precedes. In this fashion they explore the issue at stake until (all being well) both
are satisfied. Conversational implicature is truly conversational. In the following
section we will make these issues concrete and see how they give rise to a new way
to investigate conversational implicatures empirically.
6 Conversational examples
We argued that deniability, reinforceability and calculability can be summed up by
saying that conversational implicatures are negotiable. The hearer can infer the implicatures
of an utterance but cannot be completely certain that the speaker meant
them (and the speaker knows this) so both speaker and the hearer can talk — negotiate
— without redundancy or contradiction.
We find this account theoretically satisfying, but it is of additional interest because
it suggests a novel empirical approach to conversational implicature. The idea,
first suggested in [Benotti, 2009], is to track the negotiation process by noting what
linguists call clarification subdialogues. Consider, for example, the clarification
request which can naturally follow Grice’s garage example:
(11) A: and you think it’s open?
B will have to answer and either support the implicature (“yes, it’s open till midnight”)
if he wants to get it added to the common ground, or, if he realizes he was
being a little too optimistic, he can reject it without contradiction (“well, you have a
point there, they might have closed”). Conversational implicatures are invisible by
definition; negotiation subdialogues make them visible.
Let’s see some examples of clarification, rejection and reinforcement of conversational
implicatures in real dialogues between two players of a multiplayer online
game [Stoia et al., 2008]. In this game, the player DF (Direction Follower) is collaborating
with the player DG (Direction Giver) in order to reach the goal of the
game. Since the DG knows the game world and how to reach the goal, most of
her contributions come in the form of instructions on how to perform actions in
the game world. Situated instructions are a kind of language that maintains a tight
link between physical actions and conversational maxims. Recall the analogy Grice
drew between his conversational maxims and non-linguistic behavior; situated instructions
in this game world offer a concrete scenario in which to investigate the
mechanisms governing conversational implicatures and their interaction with nonlinguistic
and linguistic aspects of context. Moreover, they show that negotiation
14 Luciana Benotti and Patrick Blackburn
subdialogues (clarifications, rejections and reinforcements) make conversational implicatures
explicit and amenable to empirical studies in their natural context.
Clarifying conversational implicatures
In the following dialogue, the players are trying to move a picture from one wall to
another. The utterance being interpreted is the one uttered by the DG in (1). Using
the common knowledge context that “in order to put something somewhere you need
to have it in your hands first” and the situational context of “DF is not holding the
picture”, the DF infers a conversational implicature that involves picking up the
picture. This implicature, foreshadowed by (2) and (3), is finally made explicit as a
clarification request in (4):
DG(1): well, put it on the opposite wall
DF(2): ok, control picks the .
DF(3): control’s supposed to pick things up and .
DF(4): am I supposed to pick this thing?
Rejecting conversational implicatures
Here, the players are trying to find a gun that is supposed to be hidden. As in the
previous example, the inference of the conversational implicature in (2) is licensed
by the common knowledge context, here “in order to take something from a container
is has to be open”. However, the situational context of “the cabinet is closed” was
unknown by the DG and is an obstacle for carrying out instruction (1). As a result,
DF rejects the implicature “the cabinet is open” by uttering (2):
DG(1): take the gun from the cabinet .
DF(2): the cabinet is closed
Reinforcing conversational implicatures
In this fragment, DG asks DF to go back where he started. This instruction relies
on its previous conversational context, indeed it requires the DF to remember the
beginning of the game, which was also the beginning of the conversation. The DF
remembers what was said, and is thus able to infer a sequence of conversational
implicatures. He incrementally grounds them, making them explicit in (2), (4), and
(6) while he simultaneously executes them. Uttering the implicatures of an utterance
is a frequently used method for performing acceptance acts. As before, the
conversational implicatures of (1) are strongly dependent on the situational context.
In particular, note that if the DF was already near the steps at the moment of uttering
(1), he would only need to infer (6), not (2) and (4) as well.
DG(1): let’s go back where you started . so
DF(2): ok . so I have to go back through here .
DG(3): yeah
DF(4): and around the corner .
DG(5): right
Context and Implicature 15
DF(6): and then do I have to go back up the steps
DG(7): yeah
DF(8): alright, this is where we started
Conversational implicatures are negotiable, and dialogue provides mechanisms
for carrying out required negotiations of meaning. As these examples show, conversational
implicatures are a rich source of negotiation subdialogues. When talking,
we do not make explicit everything in the world that serves “the accepted purpose
or direction of the talk exchange in which we are engaged”, but only those parts that
are necessary for the addressees to fill in the details. If the addressee is not sure that
he has filled in the details properly (that is, if he is not sure he had interpreted our
conversational implicatures) a negotiation subdialogue will typically emerge.
A pleasant aspect of this approach is that it brings us closer to modern corpusbased
linguistic techniques: essentially the idea is to find conversational implicatures
in corpora by identifying negotiation subdialogues. The characteristics and
functions of clarification subdialogues have been deeply studied by dialogue system
researchers [Gabsdil, 2003; Purver, 2004; Rodr´ıguez and Schlangen, 2004;
Rieser and Moore, 2005; Skantze, 2007] and sociolinguists. Indeed, in discourse
analysis, this has been a favored theme for almost three decades now; see [Schegloff,
1987] as a representative example. As we have emphasized throughout this paper,
investigating conversational implicatures empirically is a delicate task; a novel approach
here could be useful.
The approach has the additional merit of anchoring the study of conversational
implicatures in their natural habitat, that is, in natural occurring conversation. It can
be difficult to decide whether something is a conversational implicature if we simply
have a two-line example (often an artificial one) of a speaker saying something to a
hearer. But in naturally occurring dialogue, the follow up conversational turns often
provides good evidence of the implicatures that have been made, because they reveal
what is being negotiated, thereby making the implicatures explicit.
7 Recent Computational work
Recall the five properties of conversational implicature we isolated in Section 4.
Two of them, namely non-detachability and non-lexicality, are closely related and
together they tell us that conversational implicatures are not part of the conventional
meaning of the words involved but depend on features of the conversational context;
indeed (as the experiments of G&P show) this is true even of seemingly-simple
scalar implicatures. This is where conversational implicatures differ from presuppositions.
As we pointed out in Section 2, words like ‘knows’ and ‘regret’ carry, as a
part of their conventional meaning, the ability to trigger certain presuppositions, but
the inferences conversational implicature gives rise too are not so easily localized.
To put it another way, non-detachability (and non-lexicality) have an obvious
computational downside. While progress has been made on computing presupposi-
16 Luciana Benotti and Patrick Blackburn
tions, computing implicatures is a heavier task, for work that models the inference
of conversational implicatures has to model the (linguistic and non-linguistic) context,
and it is often unclear which aspects of it are relevant. However, in spite of the
difficulties involved, there has been some recent work on the topic, which we shall
briefly note here. These approaches differ not only on the conversational context
elements that they model, but also in the inference techniques used.
First, [Vogel et al., 2013b] show that a team of interacting agents collaborating
to maximize a global reward using only local information reach implicature-rich interpretations
simply as a by-product of the way they reason about each other beliefs.
The technique used to model the interaction is multi-agent Decentralized POMDP
which uses only local information to maximize joint utility. A similar approach is
taken by [DeVault and Stone, 2009] who instead of POMDPs use Maximum Entropy
models over abductive interpretations to model the maximization of interpretation
success. These two approaches provide a rich representation of the conversational
context and the goals shared by the agents. Using such techniques, the cooperative
principle and the associated maxims of relevance, quality, and quantity have been
shown to emerge from agent interaction because they maximize utility. For instance,
agents do not lie to each other and do not give more information than necessary to
make collaboration more effective. The main problem of these two approaches is
their intractability, although [Vogel et al., 2013a] use cognitively-inspired heuristics
to simplify the otherwise intractable task of reasoning jointly about actions, the
environment, and the nested beliefs of other actors.
An alternative approach is not to explicitly reason about the nested beliefs but to
model and reason on the common ground using cheap causal reasoning techniques
such as classical planning [Benotti, 2010; Benotti and Blackburn, 2011]. Such have
been used to computationally explore the idea of conversational implicature as negotiation,
and have also proven to be useful in large scale practical applications [Smith,
2012]. The main problem with this approach is the limited expressive power offered
by the classical planing paradigm which is able to model only some kinds of conversational
implicatures. An interesting way around this problem might be to use
Dynamic Epistemic Planning [Bolander and Andersen, 2011], though, at least at
present, the additional expressivity this offers is likely to come with a hefty price in
terms of tractability.
8 Towards the future
In this paper we introduced conversational implicature, contrasted this notion with
presupposition, explained the cooperative principle and the maxims of conversation
on which it rests, and invited the reader to view conversational implicature as a way
of negotiating meaning in conversational contexts. We discussed theoretical, empirical
and computational perspectives, and hope it is now clear that context and
conversational implicature are deeply intertwined, and that unraveling their interactions
is a worthwhile research goal.
Context and Implicature 17
But what of the future? There has been interesting recent work in pragmatics that
points towards new research directions. In this paper we simply contrasted conversational
implicature with presupposition in an attempt to make clear just how important
context is to conversational implicature. But presupposition and conversational
implicature are only two examples (albeit important ones) of pragmatic reasoning,
and two strands of recent work hint at a more unified view. First, in [Simons et al.,
2011; Tonhauser et al., 2013] and related publications, a determined attempt has
been to make to more accurately map the contours of what are called projectable
inferences (presuppositions are an important example here, but there are many others).
On the other hand, in [Beaver and Zeevat, 2007] there are signs that linguists
are beginning to better understand the process of accommodating new information
that is inferred in context. These lines of work both hint at deeper theoretical analyses
of some of the key concepts in pragmatics, so the theoretical landscape may
well look very different a few years from now.
Nonetheless, despite these new insights, it is clear that Paul Grice got a lot right.
We do use language in conversational contexts, this does involve reasoning about the
intentions and goals of those we interact with, and this is a norm-governed process
open to exploitation. And — above all — when we negotiate with our conversational
partners and adversaries, it seems that we draw upon and reason about the
information made available by the context in deep and intriguing ways. Paul Grice:
still relevant after all these years!
Acknowledgments
This work was partially supported by grants ANPCyT PICT-2008-306, PICT-2010-
688, PICT-2012-712, and the FP7-PEOPLE-2011-IRSES Project MEALS.
References
[Beaver and Zeevat, 2007] David Beaver and Henk Zeevat. Accommodation. In The Oxford
Handbook of Linguistic Interfaces, pages 503–539. Oxford University Press, 2007.
[Beaver, 2001] David Beaver. Pragmatics, and that’s an order. In Logic, Language and Visual
Information. CSLI Publications, 2001.
[Benotti and Blackburn, 2011] Luciana Benotti and Patrick Blackburn. Classical planning and
causal implicatures. In Michael Beigl, Henning Christiansen, Thomas R. Roth-Berghofer, Anders
Kofod-Petersen, Kenny R. Coventry, and Hedda R. Schmidtke, editors, Modeling and Using
Context, volume 6967 of Lecture Notes in Computer Science, pages 26–39. Springer Berlin Heidelberg,
2011.
[Benotti, 2009] Luciana Benotti. Clarification potential of instructions. In Proceedings of the
2009 SIGDIAL Conference on Discourse and Dialogue, pages 196–205, 2009.
[Benotti, 2010] Luciana Benotti. Implicature as an Interactive Process. PhD thesis, Universite´
Henri Poincare, INRIA Nancy Grand Est, France, supervised by Patrick Blackburn, 2010. ´
18 Luciana Benotti and Patrick Blackburn
[Blackburn et al., 2001] Patrick Blackburn, Johan Bos, Michael Kohlhase, and Hans de Nivelle.
Inference and computational semantics. In Harry Bunt, Reinhard Muskens, and Elias Thijsse,
editors, Computing Meaning, volume 2, pages 11–28. Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2001.
[Bolander and Andersen, 2011] Thomas Bolander and Mikkel Birkegaard Andersen. Epistemic
planning for single- and multi-agent systems. Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics, 21:9–
34, 2011.
[Bos, 2003] Johan Bos. Implementing the binding and accommodation theory for anaphora resolution
and presupposition projection. Computational Linguistics, 29(2):179–210, 2003.
[Chemla, 2009] Emmanuel Chemla. Universal implicatures and free choice effects: Experimental
data. Semantics and Pragmatics, 2(2):1–33, May 2009.
[Davis, 2010] Wayne Davis. Implicature. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, Stanford, CA: CSLI winter 2010 edn., 2010.
[DeVault and Stone, 2009] David DeVault and Matthew Stone. Learning to interpret utterances
using dialogue history. In Proceedings of the 12th Conference of the European Chapter of the
ACL (EACL 2009), pages 184–192, Athens, Greece, 2009. Association for Computational Linguistics.
[Gabsdil, 2003] Malte Gabsdil. Clarification in spoken dialogue systems. In Proceedings of the
AAAI Spring Symposium on Natural Language Generation in Spoken and Written Dialogue,
pages 28–35, Palo Alto, California, 2003.
[Geurts and Pouscoulous, 2009] Bart Geurts and Nausicaa Pouscoulous. Embedded implicatures?!?
Semantics and Pragmatics, 2(4):1–34, July 2009.
[Geurts, 1999] Bart Geurts. Presuppositions and Pronouns, volume 3 of Current Research in the
Semantics/pragmatics Interfaces. Elsevier, Amsterdam, 1999.
[Geurts, 2011] Bart Geurts. Quantity implicatures. Cambridge University Press, 2011.
[Grice, 1975] Paul Grice. Logic and conversation. In P. Cole and J. Morgan, editors, Syntax and
Semantics, volume 3, pages 41–58. Academic Press, New York, 1975.
[Grice, 1989] Paul Grice. Studies in the Way of Words. Harvard University Press, 1989.
[Hirschberg, 1985] Julia Linn Bell Hirschberg. A theory of scalar implicature. University of
Pennsylvania, 1985.
[Horn, 2004] Larry Horn. Implicature. In Handbook of Pragmatics, pages 3–28. Blackwell, Oxford,
2004.
[Levinson, 1983] Stephen Levinson. Pragmatics. Cambridge textbooks in linguitics, 1983.
[Purver, 2004] Matthew Purver. The Theory and Use of Clarification Requests in Dialogue. PhD
thesis, King’s College, University of London, 2004. Supervised by Jonathan Ginzburg.
[Rieser and Moore, 2005] Verena Rieser and Johanna D. Moore. Implications for generating clarification
requests in task-oriented dialogues. In Proceedings of the 43rd Annual Meeting on
Association for Computational Linguistics, (ACL 2005), pages 239–246, Ann Arbor, Michigan,
2005. Association for Computational Linguistics.
[Rodr´ıguez and Schlangen, 2004] Kepa Rodr´ıguez and David Schlangen. Form, intonation and
function of clarification requests in german task oriented spoken dialogues. In Proceedings of
8th Workshop on the Semantics and Pragmatics of Dialogue (SEMDIAL), pages 101–108, 2004.
[Schegloff, 1987] Emanuel Schegloff. Some sources of misunderstanding in talk-in-interaction.
Linguistics, 8:201–218, 1987.
[Simons et al., 2011] Mandy Simons, Judith Tonhauser, David Beaver, and Craige Roberts. What
projects and why. In Proceedings of 20th Semantics and Linguistic Theory Conference (SALT
2010), volume 20, pages 309–327, 2011.
[Skantze, 2007] Gabriel Skantze. Error Handling in Spoken Dialogue Systems. PhD thesis, KTH
- Royal Institute of Technology, Sweden, 2007. Supervised by Rolf Carlson.
[Smith, 2012] Dustin Smith. Managing implicit assumptions in natural language interfaces. In
Proceedings of the 2012 ACM international conference on Intelligent User Interfaces, IUI ’12,
pages 383–388, New York, NY, USA, 2012. ACM.
[Stoia et al., 2008] Laura Stoia, Darla Magdalene Shockley, Donna K. Byron, and Eric FoslerLussier.
Scare: A situated corpus with annotated referring expressions. In Proceedings of the
6th International Conference on Language Resources and Evaluation (LREC 2008), Marrakesh,
Morocco, May 2008.
Context and Implicature 19
[Tonhauser et al., 2013] Judith Tonhauser, David Beaver, Craige Roberts, and Mandy Simons. Toward
a taxonomy of projective content. Language, 89(1):66–109, 2013.
[van Rooij, 2011] Robert van Rooij. Optimality-Theoretic and Game-Theoretic Approaches to
Implicature. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Stanford, CA:
CSLI Dec 1, 2006, substantive revision Feb 17, 2011 edn, 2011.
[Venhuizen et al., 2013] Noortje Venhuizen, Johan Bos, and Harm Brouwer. Parsimonious semantic
representations with projection pointers. In Proceedings of the 10th International Conference
on Computational Semantics (IWCS 2013) – Long Papers, pages 252–263, Potsdam,
Germany, 2013.
[Vogel et al., 2013a] Adam Vogel, Max Bodoia, Christopher Potts, and Dan Jurafsky. Emergence
of Gricean maxims from multi-agent decision theory. In Human Language Technologies: The
2013 Annual Conference of the North American Chapter of the Association for Computational
Linguistics, pages 1072–1081, Stroudsburg, PA, June 2013. Association for Computational Linguistics.
[Vogel et al., 2013b] Adam Vogel, Christopher Potts, and Dan Jurafsky. Implicatures and nested
beliefs in approximate Decentralized-POMDPs. In Proceedings of the 2013 Annual Conference
of the Association for Computational Linguistics, pages 74–80, Stroudsburg, PA, August 2013.
Association for Computational Linguistics.
[Wilson and Sperber, 2004] Deirdre Wilson and Dan Sperber. Relevance theory. In The Handbook
of Pragmatics, pages 607–632. Blackwell, Oxford, 2004.
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment