The Grice Club

Welcome

The Grice Club

The club for all those whose members have no (other) club.

Is Grice the greatest philosopher that ever lived?

Search This Blog

Tuesday, March 3, 2015

Legal Implicatures: Grice and Hart

Speranza

Herbert Lionel Adolphus Hart (1907-1992) became a leading scholar in the field of legal philosophy after publishing his most influential work, "The Concept of Law", in 1961.

Hart was a foremost proponent of legal positivism.

H.L.A. Hart was born on July 18, 1907, in Harrogate, England, the son of Jewish parents, Simeon, a wool merchant, and Rose (Samson) Hart.

He received his early education at Cheltenham College and Bradford Grammar School.

He then enrolled in New College, Oxford, where he studied under H. W. B. Joseph.

Hart was an exceptional student, especially in the classics, ancient history, and philosophy.

He earned his bachelor's degree in 1929 and was admitted to the bar in 1932.

For the next eight years Hart practiced as a barrister in the Chancery courts of London.

He established a successful legal office handling complex cases involving trusts, family settlements, and taxes.

Although he was asked to become a philosophy tutor at New College, he declined the offer and remained with his law practice.

During World War II, the British War Department called on Hart to serve in military intelligence.

From 1939 to 1945, he was a civil servant with the MI5, the British intelligence division.

While at this post, Hart worked with two Oxford philosophers, Gilbert Ryle and S. N. Hampshire.

Their frequent philosophical conversations spurred Hart's interest in the subject.

During this time he married Jenifer Fischer Williams.

The couple had one daughter and three sons.

He also managed to fulfill the requirements for an advanced degree and was awarded an M.A. from Oxford in 1942.


When the war ended, Hart was again invited to return to New College.

He became a Fellow and Tutor in philosophy at Oxford from 1946 to 1952.

He was also appointed as a university lecturer in philosophy in 1948.

According to Neil McCormick in the book "H.L.A. Hart", after sixteen years of intensely practical work in the law and then in war service he returned to the academic life.

His aims had nothing to do with applying philosophy to legal problems.

But, as it turned out, his legal experience in the Chancery was particularly relevant to the current concerns of his fellow philosophers, for whom the study of the uses of language in practical as well as theoretical ways had assumed a new urgency.

Thus Hart came to the field of jurisprudence almost by accident.

After A. L. Goodhart's resignation in 1952, Hart was selected to replace him as the Chair of Jurisprudence at Oxford.

From 1952 to 1968 Hart served as a professor of jurisprudence and an Oxford University Fellow.

He was a visiting professor at Harvard from 1956 to 1957 and at the University of California at Los Angeles from 1961 to 1962.

From 1959 to 1960 he served as the president of the Aristotelian Society.

In 1968 he resigned as the Chair of Jurisprudence and spent the next four years as a Nuffield Foundation Senior Research Fellow at University College, Oxford.

In 1972 he was named Principal of Brasenose College, Oxford, where he remained until his retirement in 1978.

He was a delegate of Oxford University Press beginning in 1960, a member of the Monopolies Commission from 1967 to 1973, and chairperson of the Oxford University Enquiry into Relations with Junior Members in 1969.


As a legal philosopher, Hart drew heavily on the tradition of legal positivism, especially the works of Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832) and John Austin (1790-1859), as well as their follower John Stuart Mills (1806-1873).

Legal positivists based their theories on three basic tenets.

First, they argued that what the law is and what the law should be are two separate questions.

Therefore, there is no connection between legality and morality.

A law can be legitimized by a society but also be immoral, and an evil regime can still institute a system of laws.

Second, logical positivists hold that the analysis of legal concepts, such as a legal system, rules, and rights, is an important endeavor.

Third, logical positivists argue that laws are commands issued by a sovereign whom the public obeys out of habit.

Hart concurred on the first two points.

However, he disagreed that the FOUNDATION of a legal system rests in the power of a sovereign to command.

Laws are not obeyed because of the coercive demands of the government, he argued.

Rather, obligation stems from the social "rules" of a given society.

In The Philosophy of Law: An Introduction to Jurisprudence, Jeffrie G. Murphy and Jules L. Coleman refer to Hart's The Concept of Law (1961), as being "universally regarded as the most significant contribution to legal philosophy of [the 20th] century.

Hart gives the theory of legal positivism the most systematic and powerful statement it has ever received and is ever likely to receive.

In The Concept of Law, Hart argued that Austin laid a foundation for an excellent theory of law by delineating between laws and morals but erred in viewing law as a weapon of a large bully who demands compliance by force.

Hart argued that a legal system is not a compilation of individual laws, but rather a union of primary and secondary rules.

A primary rule imposes an obligation: what a citizen may or may not do.

A secondary laws define specifics of the primary rule.

To exemplify his theory, Hart asks his readers to imagine a pre-legal society, that is, one that lacked laws, and then imagine the types of problems that might plague such a society.

To make changes to eliminate these pathologies would be to make laws.

The legal system is then, simply defined, those changes prescribed by a society to cure social problems.

Hart notes that even a pre-legal society would follow social norms.

Even if there were no specific law against it, walking around naked in most societies would be considered outside the range of acceptable social behavior -- except Sparta.

Hart called these primary rules.

A rule is primary iff directed to all individuals in a given society that impose an obligation.

Unlike John Austin, who suggests that such rules are followed in order to avoid punishment, Hart argues that a primary rule imposes an obligation because it sets a standard for criticism or justification within the society.

A society formed around a primary rule alone, Hart acknowledges, would suffer from a few difficulties.

First, uncertainty would arise concerning WHAT the rules are, how rules are applied, and what to do if rules conflict -- or clash.

Second, a primary rule is static and does not change as the social, economic, and political environment changes.

Third, a primary rule alone is inefficient because there is no systematically prescribed recourse for when there is conflict over another rule or when the rule is broken.

In response to these apparent difficulties, Hart suggests the addition of secondary rules, or rules about rules, as he noted in The Concept of Law:

"They specify the ways in which the primary rules may be conclusively ascertained, introduced, eliminated, varied, and the fact of their violation conclusively determined."

According to Hart, three basic secondary rules exist:

-- rules of recognition
-- rules of change, and
-- rules of adjudication.

These are the "laws" that establish the authoritative structure by which a primary rule is defined and enacted.

Hart maintained that a legal system must be approached from an internal viewpoint.

As a participant within the system, an observer brings an assumption that the law ought to be obeyed.

In The Legal Philosophy of H.L.A. Hart, Michael Martin discusses Hart's theory of internalization.

Social actors can view their own behaviour in different ways.

An agent can accept a rule of a system S and use it to guide his actions and to evaluate the actions of others.

Or an agent can follow the rule without accepting it.

***************************************************


Hart maintains that to have a legal system at least the officials of the system must take the internal point of view.

They must ACCEPT the rules of the system and evaluate others' actions in terms of them.

The Concept of Law became the yardstick by which both Hart's supporters and detractors were measured.

As McCormick noted, it is a work of international eminence which even its strongest critics have acknowledged as a masterpiece worth at least the compliment of careful refutation.


The Concept of Law was not Hart's only important book.

In 1959 he published Causation in the Law, co-authored by A.M. Honore, which examined questions of causality in matters of civil and criminal liability.

Hart and Honore argued for a definition of "cause" that employed common, everyday language, which is fundamental to basic understanding of what is fair and just in punishment or compensation.

In Law, Liberty, and Morality, published in 1963, Hart set forth an argument against legal moralism.

He argued that laws and morals are not related by necessity.

In 1965 he published The Morality of Criminal Law, in which he laid out a defense of the limits of law in regulating moral behaviour.

Punishment and Responsibility: Essays in the Philosophy of Law followed in 1968.

In it, Hart offered a complex theory of punishment that combines elements of both retribution and utility.

Hart edited three books on Bentham: Jeremy Bentham, Of Laws in General (1970), Bentham, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation (1970), and Bentham, Comment on the Commentaries [and] A Fragment on Government (1977).

Hart published two more works after his retirement: Essays on Bentham: Studies in Jurisprudence and Political Theory (1982) and Essays on Jurisprudence and Philosophy (1983).

Over the course of his distinguished career, Hart wrote numerous published essays.

The most influential were "Definition and Theory in Jurisprudence" (inaugural lecture, Oxford, 1953), "Are There Any Natural Rights?" (1967), and "Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals" (1958).

Books
Audi, Robert, The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, 2nd edition, Cambridge University Press, 1999.

Blackburn, Simon, The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy, Oxford University Press, 1994.
Bunnin, Nicholas and E.P. Tsui-James, editors, The Blackwell Companion to Philosophy, Blackwell Publishers, 1996.
Devine, Elizabeth; Michael Held, James Vinson, and George Walsh, editors, Thinkers of the Twentieth Century: A Biographical, Bibliographical and Critical Dictionary, Gale Research Company, 1983.
Edwards, Paul, editor, The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Macmillian, 1967.
MacCormick, Neil, H. L. A. Hart, Stanford University Press, 1981.
Martin, Michael, The Legal Philosophy of H. L. A. Hart: A Critical Appraisal, Temple University Press, 1987.
Murphy, Jeffrie G., and Jules L. Coleman, The Philosophy of Law: An Introduction to Jurisprudence, Rowman & Allanheld, 1984.
Parry, Melanie, editor, Chambers Biographical Dictionary, 6th edition, Chambers Harrap Publishing, 1997.
Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy:
Herbert Lionel Adolphus Hart
Top

Hart, Herbert Lionel Adolphus (1907-92) English philosopher of law. Hart's first career was as a lawyer; he became Fellow and Tutor in philosophy at New College, Oxford (1945-52), then professor of jurisprudence at Oxford (1952-68), and Principal of Brasenose College (1973-8).

He was the most influential legal philosopher of his time, whose masterpiece The Concept of Law (1961) set the agenda for a generation of jurisprudence.

The work applies techniques from linguistic philosophy to a sophisticated defence of the view that law consists essentially in a system of rules located in social practices: a version of legal positivism.

Hart also wrote, with A. M. Honoré, Causation in the Law (1959), a study of causation in questions of civil and criminal liability.

A liberal in his political views, Hart became well known to a wider public through the debate with Lord Devlin over the Wolfenden report on the function of the law in the sphere of sexual behaviour, where his The Morality of the Criminal Law (1965) remains a classic defence of the liberal position on the limits of law in moral matters.

Other works include Punishment and Responsibility (1968), Essays on Bentham: Jurisprudence and Political Theory (1982), and Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy (1983). The definitive biography is by Nicola Lacey (2004).
Columbia Encyclopedia:

Hart, Herbert Lionel Adolphus, 1907-, British legal philosopher. A lawyer and trained philosopher, Hart subjected legal concepts to scrutiny in such works as The Concept of Law (1961) and Law, Liberty, and Morality (1963).

Hart argued that law is premised on the notion of duty as the support of civic and societal existence and that law is not based on any moral code, so it is improper to legislate on matters of private morality.

His other works include Punishment and Responsibility (1968) and Essays on Bentham (1982).

No comments:

Post a Comment