Speranza
One of Grice's unpublications is about conjunctions and disjunctions in the scope of non-doxastic attitude verbs.
Yes, you heard that right!
To see what is at issue, consider the following scenarios and reports that follow them (the embedded
question in (2b) is a disjunctive polar question rather than an alternative question)
1
:
Visitors:
On Friday, Bill gets a letter from his friends Alice and Ted saying that they will visit
Bill on Sunday if they find enough free time.
On Saturday, Bill gets a message from Alice saying
that she won’t be able to manage a visit — the message is silent about the prospects of Ted
visiting.
On Sunday, Bill hears a knock on the door and rushes to open it.
Before Bill answers,
I utter:
(1) a. Bill hopes that Ted is at the door.
b. ?? Bill hopes that Alice or Ted is at the door.
(2) a. Bill wonders whether Ted is at the door.
b. ?? Bill wonders whether or not Alice or Ted is at the door.
Dessert: Bill is having a dinner party and each guest brought something to eat. Bill’s favorite
desserts are apple pie and cherry pie.
Bill sees that Mary brought apple pie, but he doesn’t yet
know what Chris brought.
I utter:
(3) a. Bill hopes that Chris brought cherry pie.
b. ?? Bill hopes that Mary brought apple pie and Chris brought cherry pie.
(4) a. Bill wonders whether Chris brought cherry pie.
(Cfr. Chris Barker, Cian Dorr, Ben Holgu´ın, and Jim Pryor)
(Disjunctive polar questions are distinguished from alternative questions by their intonation contours
(Biezma and Rawlins), as well as the fact that alternative questions, but not disjunctive polar questions,
presuppose that exactly one of the relevant disjuncts hold.
I follow others in using ‘whether or not’ for
disjunctive polar questions.
See §5 for further discussion.
(4) b. ?? Bill wonders whether Mary brought apple pie and Chris brought cherry pie.
While (1a)-(4a) are acceptable in their respective contexts, (1b)-(4b) are not.
Intuitively,
what seems to be required for (1b)-(2b) to be acceptable is that it is compatible with Bill’s
knowledge that Alice is at the door.
And what seems to be required for (3b)-(4b) to be acceptable
is that it is compatible with Bill’s knowledge that Mary did not bring apple pie.
That is, Bill
cannot know that Alice will not be coming, and he cannot know that Mary brought apple pie.
Let us call these inferences ignorance implicatures.
I argue that the best way to account for ignorance implicatures is by appealing to a notion
of contextual redundancy. In short, (1b)-(4b) are infelicitous because they have constituents
that are redundant in context: the propositions that they express could have been expressed
by syntactically simpler sentences, namely (1a)-(4a). This pragmatic approach to ignorance
implicatures stands in contrast to a recent semantic account of ignorance implicatures involving
disjunctions under ‘wonder’ developed by Roelofsen and Uegaki (2016) (henceforth ‘R&U’). I
argue that R&U’s account makes problematic predictions when conjunctions are embedded
under ‘wonder’, as in (4b). Thus, the pragmatic, redundancy-theoretic account is superior.2
2 Redundancy and Ignorance Implicatures
2.1 Redundancy
Consider the following scenarios and reports that follow them:
Wimbledon: We are watching the men’s Wimbledon semi-final. Unfortunately, we all see
Federer lose to Nadal in five sets. Then I utter:
(5) ?? Federer won or Nadal will win the final.
Holiday: A group of us are discussing our holiday plans. I ask Ted where he intends to
spend the summer. He tells the group: ‘I’m going to Costa Rica’. Then Ben utters:
(6) ?? Ted is going to Costa Rica and it is going to be very humid there.
Neither (5) nor (6) are felicitous in their respective contexts. Intuitively, this is explained by
the fact that both have parts that are trivial or redundant in the relevant scenarios (in (5) this
is the first disjunct, and in (6) this is the first conjunct). That is, the content communicated
by (5) and (6) could have been communicated by simpler sentences. If we suppose that more
economical expressions are preferred to more complex ones, the unacceptability of (5) and (6)
can be accounted for.3
I maintain that a similar account of the infelicity of (1b)-(4b) can be
given: these reports are problematic because their content could have been expressed by simpler
sentences in context.
A theory that explains why (5) and (6) are redundant in their respective contexts is a
theory of redundancy. A rather simple theory of redundancy accounts for (5) and (6), as well
as (1b)-(4b):
2As a reviewer points out, ignorance implicatures also arise with disjunctions embedded under doxastics,
e.g. ‘Bill believes that Alice or Ted is at the door’ is infelicitous when it is common knowledge that Bill believes
Alice is not at the door. The account developed here can handle these cases as well. However, we focus on
non-doxastics since, unlike both ‘hope’ and ‘wonder’, conjunctions under ‘believe’ do not give rise to ignorance
implicatures.
3This is only to say that this is one way to account for their infelicity, there could be other explanations as
well.
2
Ignorance Implicatures Blumberg
(7) Redundancy 1: (to be revised)
a. φ cannot be used in context C if φ is contextually equivalent4
to ψ, and ψ is a
simplification of φ.
b. ψ is a simplification of φ if ψ can be derived from φ by replacing nodes in φ with
their subconstituents
To illustrate, (5) is contextually equivalent to ‘Nadal will win the final’ in W imbledon, since
every world in the context set is one in which Fed lost the match. Since ‘Nadal will win the
final’ is a simplification of (5) (by (7b)), (5) is predicted to be unacceptable (by (7a)). Similarly,
(6) is contextually equivalent to ‘It is going to be very humid in Costa Rica’ in Holiday, since
every world in the context set is one in which Ted is going to Costa Rica. Since ‘It is going to
be very humid in Costa Rica’ is a simplification of (6), (6) is predicted to be unacceptable.
2.2 Some attitude semantics
2.2.1 ‘hope’
(1a)-(4a) are simplifications of (1b)-(4b), respectively. So, if we can show contextual equivalence
for each pair then we would have an explanation for the (b) member’s infelicity. In order to
show contextual equivalence we need to have a semantics for ‘hope’ and ‘wonder’ on the table.
For ‘hope’ let us assume a simplified “ideal worlds” analysis (von Fintel, 1999). This acccount
employs a notion of an “ideal” set of worlds with respect to a subject’s desires: a set of worlds
compatible with everything that S desires in w (denoted by Bulw,S). On this approach, ‘S
hopes that p’ is defined at w iff S does not believe p, S does not believe ¬p, and S’s hopes are
constrained by S’s beliefs (Bulw,S ⊆ Doxw,S).5
If defined, the report is true iff all of S’s desire
worlds are p-worlds. A bit more formally:
(8) Semantics for ‘hope’
a. ‘S hopes that p’ is defined at w iff (i) Doxw,S ∩ p 6= ∅, (ii) Doxw,S − p 6= ∅, (iii)
Bulw,S ⊆ Doxw,S
b. If defined, ‘S hopes that p’ is true at w iff Bulw,S ⊆ p
It is straightforward, but tedious, to show that (1a)-(1b) and (3a)-(3b) are contextually
equivalent on this semantics for ‘hope’.6 Thus, both (1b) and (3b) are predicted to be unac4Sentences
φ and ψ are contextually equivalent with respect to context C iff {w ∈ C : JφK(w) = 1} = {w ∈
C : JψK(w) = 1} Singh (2011).
5As Heim (1992) points out, ‘I hope to teach Tuesdays and Thursdays next semester’ can be true even when
there are worlds compatible with everything that I desire in which I don’t teach at all. Instead, hope reports
only make a claim about the relative desirability of the worlds compatible with the subject’s beliefs. (As Heim
(1992) notes, the relevant constraint isn’t quite the subject’s belief worlds, but as far as I can tell this subtlety
shouldn’t impact our argument.)
6Let us call the context of V isitors V . Take an arbitrary w ∈ V . Suppose that (1a) is undefined at w. Then
at least one of (i)-(iii) in (8) fail with respect to (1a). If (iii) fails then clearly (1b) is also undefined at w. If (i)
fails, then at w it is doxastically impossible for Bill that Ted is at the door. Since it is doxastically impossible
for Bill that Alice is at the door, it follows that (1b) is undefined at w. If (ii) fails, then at w it is doxastically
necessary for Bill that Ted is at the door. It follows that it is doxastically necessary that Ted or Alice is at the
door, hence (1b) is undefined at w. So, if (1a) is undefined at w, then (1b) is undefined at w. Now suppose that
(1a) is defined at w. Then it is doxastically possible but not necessary for Bill that Ted is at the door at w.
Since it is doxastically impossible for Bill that Alice is at the door in w, it follows that it is doxastically possible
but not necessary for Bill that Ted or Alice is at the door. Furthermore, if (1a) is defined at w then condition
(iii) of (8) is satisfied. Thus, if (1a) is defined at w, (1b) is defined at w. Now suppose that (1a) is true at w.
Then all of the worlds compatible with what Bill desires are worlds in which Ted is at the door. Hence, all of
3
Ignorance Implicatures Blumberg
ceptable given Redundancy 1.7 More generally, if it is common knowledge that S believes p
is false, ‘S hopes that p or q’ will be contextually equivalent to ‘S hopes that q’. Thus, by
Redundancy 1 the report will be unacceptable. Similarly, if it is common knowledge that S
believes p is true, ‘S hopes that p and q’ will be contextually equivalent to ‘S hopes that q’.
Thus, by Redundancy 1 the report will be unacceptable.8
2.2.2 ‘wonder’
I will assume the semantics for ‘wonder’ developed by Ciardelli and Roelofsen (2015). Their
theory is set in the framework of inquisitive epistemic logic, which combines notions from
standard epistemic logic and inquisitive semantics. In epistemic logic, an information state is
modeled as a set of possible worlds—those worlds that are compatible with the information
available in the state. In inquisitive semantics, the basic propositional object is an issue I: a
non-empty set of information states that is closed under subsets, i.e. if s ∈ I and s
0 ⊂ s then
s
0 ∈ I. The maximal elements of I are called the alternatives of I. The meaning of a sentence,
whether declarative or interrogative, is the issue that it expresses. For example, Jwhether Ted
is at the doorK = {s | ∀w ∈ s : Ted is at the door in w} ∪ {s | ∀w ∈ s : Ted is not at the door
in w}. An information state s settles an issue I iff s ∈ I. For instance, if Ted is at the door at
the actual world w@, then {w@} settles the issue of whether Ted is at the door.
Each agent α is assigned an inquisitive state at a world w denoted as Σα(w): a set of
information states such that each information state settles all the issues that α entertains at
w. For instance, if at w Bill entertains the issue of whether Ted is at the door, then every
s ∈ ΣBill(w) settles that issue. Intuitively, Σα tells us ‘where the agent wants to get to’ in terms
of inquiry; how they would like their information state to be in the future, and which issues
they want to see settled. Like issues, inquisitive states are assumed to be non-empty and closed
under subsets. Moreover, it is assumed that Σα(w) forms a cover of α’s information state at
w, denoted as σα(w). That is, S
Σα(w) = σα(w).
In this system, α knows an issue I at w when σα(w) ∈ I. α entertains an issue I when
Σα(w) ⊆ I (all of the information states that α would like to get to are ones where I is settled).
The ‘wonder’ modality, denoted W, is given in terms of these notions and has the following
truth conditions: w |= Wαφ iffd σα(w) 6∈ JφK and Σα(w) ⊆ JφK. Finally, the semantics for
‘wonder’ is given in terms of this modality:
(9) Semantics for ‘wonder’
‘S wonders φ’ is true at w iff w |= WSφ (iff σS(w) 6∈ JφK and ΣS(w) ⊆ JφK)
In other words, S wonders about an issue when they do not know it, but would like to see it
settled, i.e. they entertain it. It is easy to check that (9) makes ‘wonder’ non-monotonic (since
the underlying ‘wonder’ modality is non-monotonic).9
the worlds compatible with what Bill desires are worlds in which Ted or Alice is at the door. So, if (1a) is true
at w, (1b) is true at w. Finally, suppose that (1a) is false at w. Then it is not the case that all of the worlds
compatible with what Bill desires are worlds in which Ted is at the door. Since Bill’s desire worlds are a subset
of his belief worlds, it follows that it is not the case that all of the worlds compatible with what Bill desires are
worlds in which Ted or Alice is at the door. Thus, if (1a) is false at w, (1b) is false at w. Hence, (1a) and (1b)
are contextually equivalent with respect to V . The other case is similar.
7The same result obtains if a “similarity” semantics for ‘hope’ is adopted (Heim, 1992).
8Note that the “Presupposed Ignorance Principle” of Spector and Sudo (2017) does not predict that either
(1b) or (3b) should be unacceptable in their respective contexts, since the negative and positive presuppositions
of ‘hope’ create a non-monotonic environment. See (Spector and Sudo, 2017) for further discussion.
9
In this framework, for issues I, G: I |= G iff I ⊆ G. See (Ciardelli et al., 2016) for more on the logic of
issues.
4
Ignorance Implicatures Blumberg
Given (9), it is straightforward to show that (2a)-(2b) and (4a)-(4b) are contextually equivalent.10
Similar cases involving alternative, rather than polar questions can also be handled
(but see §5 for further discussion).
To be clear, we have explained why, e.g. ‘S hopes that p or q’ is unacceptable when, e.g.
it is common knowledge that ‘S knows ¬p’ is true. However, what might be more naturally
called an “ignorance implicature” is the following phenomenon: ‘S hopes that p or q’ uttered
out of the blue suggests that (the speaker thinks that) ‘S knows ¬p’ is f alse. The account
presented here predicts something weaker; namely that such an utterance will merely suggest
that it is not common knowledge that ‘S knows ¬p’ is true. That is, what is predicted is ¬CK(S
knows ¬p), but what is required is CK(¬(S knows ¬p)). It is plausible that the strengthened
result is obtained by an “epistemic step” similar to those that have been proposed for inferences
involving scalar implicatures, e.g. (Sauerland, 2004), and presuppositions, e.g. (Chemla, 2007).
We leave the development of an account of such auxiliary pragmatic reasoning for future work.
3 A refinement
In this section, we refine the account of redundancy introduced above by considering some data
that has recently been discussed by Rostworowski (forthcoming). In the course of trying to
defend the Russellian analysis of definite descriptions, Rostworowski considers reports such as
the following:
(10) a. Bill hopes that the dictator is dead and was assassinated.
b. Bill wonders whether the dictator is dead and was assassinated.
(11) a. Bill hopes that Mary is pregnant and expecting a daughter.
b. Bill wonders whether Mary is pregnant and expecting a daughter.
These reports raise two issues. First, a report such as (10a) is unacceptable if Bill already
knows that the dictator is dead. Redundancy 1 can explain this: (10a) and ‘Bill hopes that the
dictator was assassinated’ are contextually equivalent in any context in which Bill knows that
the dictator is dead, so (10a) is ruled infelicitous. There are, however, contexts in which (10a)
is acceptable, e.g. when Bill has no idea about the health of the dictator. But Redundancy 1
predicts that (10a) will always be infelicitous. This is because ‘The dictator was assassinated’
entails ‘The dictator is dead’. So, (10a) and ‘Bill hopes that the president was assassinated’ are
contextually equivalent in any context. What is needed, then, is an account that predicts that
(10a) is problematic only in contexts where Bill knows that the dictator is dead.
Intuitively, the reason that (10a) can be acceptable is that the second conjunct adds information
to the first conjunct: once we have processed the first conjunct it is compatible with
what we know that the second conjunct is false. What needs to be done is somehow incorporate
the fact that we process sentences in linear order into the redundancy conditions. Thankfully,
this has already been done for us by Mayr and Romoli (2016) (following Fox (2008), who in
10Take an arbitrary w ∈ V . Suppose that (2a) is true in w. Then σBill(w) 6∈ Jwhether Ted is at the doorK =
{s | ∀w ∈ s : Ted is at the door in w} ∪ {s | ∀w ∈ s : Ted is not at the door in w}. Also, ΣBill(w) ⊆ Jwhether
Ted is at the doorK. JWhether-or-not Alice or Ted is at the doorK = {s | ∀w ∈ s : Alice or Ted is at the
door in w} ∪ {s | ∀w ∈ s : neither Alice nor Ted is at the door in w}. σBill(w) ∩ {w | Alice is at the door in
w} = ∅ (by assumption). It follows that σBill(w) 6∈ {s | ∀w ∈ s : Alice or Ted is at the door in w}, and that
σBill(w) 6∈ {s | ∀w ∈ s : neither Alice nor Ted is at the door in w}. Thus, σBill(w) 6∈ Jwhether-or-not Alice or
Ted is at the doorK. Given that ΣBill(w) covers σBill(w), it also follows that ΣBill(w) ⊆ Jwhether-or-not Alice
or Ted is at the doorK. Hence, (2b) is true in w. The other direction is similar (as is the other case).
5
Ignorance Implicatures Blumberg
turn follows Schlenker (2008)). The result is a more complex redundancy condition that allows
us to talk about parts or constituents of sentences being redundant:
(12) Redundancy 2
Incremental non-redundancy condition: φ cannot be used in context C if any part
ψ of φ is incrementally redundant in φ given C.
a. Incremental redundancy:
i. ψ is incrementally redundant in φ given a context C if it is globally redundant
in all φ
0
, where φ
0
is a possible continuation of φ at point ψ.
ii. φ
0
is a possible continuation of φ at point ψ iff it is like φ in its structure and
number of constituents, but the constituents pronounced after ψ are possibly
different.
b. Global redundancy:
i. ψ is globally redundant in φ given a context C if φ is contextually equivalent to
φ
0
, where φ
0
is a simplification of φ without ψ.
ii. ψ is a simplification of φ if ψ can be derived from φ by replacing nodes in φ
with their subconstituents.
Redundancy 2 handles Rostworowski’s reports. First, the ignorance implicature of, e.g.
(10a) is predicted, since the first conjunct in the complement is incrementally redundant in any
context where it has been established that Bill knows that the dictator is dead (the first conjunct
is globally redundant in any possible continuation of (10a) at the point of the first conjunct).
Moreover, Redundancy 2 does not predict that (10a) is always infelicitous. In contexts where
Bill does not know that the dictator is dead, there are continuations of (10a) at the point of
the first conjunct that are not globally redundant, e.g. ‘Bill hopes that the dictator is dead and
Mary is happy’.
4 Roelofsen and Uegaki’s (2016) account
R&U take as their point of departure Ciardelli and Roelofsen’s (2015) semantics for ‘wonder’ and
try to develop an account that captures the ignorance implicatures of disjunctions embedded
under this verb. R&U enrich Ciardelli and Roelofsen’s semantics with a built-in exhaustivity
operator:
(13) R&U’s semantics
pwonder Qq = λx.exh{Wx(pQ0q)|Q0.Q} Wx(pQq)
11
(13) can account for the ignorance implicatures that arise for (2b). On this entry, (2b) is
true just in case (14a) is true, (14b) is false, and (14c) is false.12 However, if Bill knows that
11The exhaustivity operator takes an expression ϕ and a set of alternatives A, and ‘strengthens’ ϕ by negating
every ψ ∈ A that is not entailed by ϕ: exhA(ϕ) := ϕ ∧
V
{¬ψ| ψ ∈ A and ϕ 6|= ψ} (strictly speaking only the
‘innocently excludable’ alternatives should be negated, but that complication won’t be relevant here). R&U
assume that the set of alternatives A is generated by considering the formal structure of ϕ, rather than its
semantic content. More specifically, ϕ
0 ∈ A with respect to ϕ just in case ϕ
0 . ϕ, where ϕ
0 . ϕ iff ϕ
0 can
be obtained from ϕ by deleting constituents or replacing them with other constituents of the same syntactic
category, taken either from the lexicon or from ϕ itself Katzir (2007).
12We leave the complements in English, since it makes the sentences easier to read.
6
Ignorance Implicatures Blumberg
Ann isn’t at the door, then the only way for (14a) to be true is for (14c) to be true.
13
(14) a. WBill (whether-or-not Ann or Ted is at the door)
b. WBill (whether-or-not Ann is at the door)
c. WBill (whether-or-not Ted is at the door)
As for conjunctions under ‘wonder’, R&U’s approach does predict that (4b) should be
unacceptable. Because W is non-monotonic, both (15b) and (15c) are alternatives for exhaustification
for (15a). But if Bill knows that Mary brought apple pie, then (15a) is true only if
(15c) is true.
(15) a. WBill (whether Mary brought apple pie and Chris brought cherry pie)
b. WBill (whether Mary brought apple pie)
c. WBill (whether Chris brought cherry pie)
Although it captures the relevant ignorance implicature in Dessert, overall R&U’s semantic
approach makes incorrect predictions when conjunctions are embedded under ‘wonder’. There
are two related problems here. First, the truth-conditions for sentences with conjunctions under
‘wonder’ seem too strong. It is a consequence of the account that (4b), ‘Bill wonders whether
Mary brought apple-pie’, and ‘Bill wonders whether Chris brought cherry pie’ cannot all be
true together (assuming that the second is false if (15b) is, and that the last is false if (15c) is).
But it is quite easy to imagine contexts where all three reports are acceptable, e.g. consider
a scenario like Dessert where Bill does not know whether Mary brought apple pie. More
generally, ‘S wonders whether A and B’, ‘S wonders whether A’, and ‘S wonders whether B’
can all be acceptable in a single context.
Second, R&U’s account does not predict ignorance implicatures in all cases. Consider (10b)
(‘Bill wonders whether the dictator is dead and was assassinated’) once again. As discussed
above, (10b) is only felicitous if Bill does not know that the dictator is dead. However, (16b)
is an alternative for exhaustification for (16a):14
(16) a. WBill (whether the dictator is dead and was assassinated)
b. WBill (whether the dictator is dead)
On R&U’s account, (10b) is true only if (16b) is false. (16b) is false just in case either
σBill(w) ∈ Jwhether the dictator is deadK = {s | ∀w ∈ s : the dictator is dead in w} ∪ {s | ∀w ∈ s :
the dictator is not dead in w} or ΣBill(w) 6⊆ Jwhether the dictator is deadK. If Bill knows that
the dictator is dead, then σBill(w) ∈ {s | ∀w ∈ s : the dictator is dead in w} ⊆ Jwhether the
dictator is deadK. Thus, R&U’s account does not predict that (10b) is unacceptable when Bill
knows that the dictator is dead.15
13If Bill knows that Ann isn’t at the door in w, then σBill(w) 6∈ Jwhether-or-not Ann or Ted is at the doorK
only if σBill(w) 6∈ Jwhether-or-not Ted is at the doorK. Also, ΣBill(w) ⊆ Jwhether-or-not Ann or Ted is at the
doorK only if ΣBill(w) ⊆ J whether-or-not Ted is at the doorK, since ΣBill(w) covers σBill(w).
14In inquisitive semantics, Jwhether the dictator is dead and was assassinatedK = Jwhether the dictator was
assassinatedK. So, ‘WBill (whether the dictator was assassinated)’ is not an alternative for exhaustification for
(16a), since the latter entails the former.
15Since ‘hope’ carries presuppositions, an analogue of the exhaustification entry for this verb presents various
options depending on how the exhaustification operator is defined. Spector and Sudo (2017) consider some of
these alternatives. Overall, these alternatives struggle with embedded conjunctions. Briefly, if EXH1 is used then
it is predicted that (3b) should always be infelicitous. Alternatively, EXH2 does not generate any alternatives
at all for (3b) assuming an “ideal worlds” semantics, so cannot account for its ignorance implicatures. If a
“similarity” semantics is adopted then EXH2 raises problems similar to those raised by R&U’s account, namely
the truth conditions of (3b) are too strict and the ignorance implicatures of (10a) are not accounted for.
7
Ignorance Implicatures Blumberg
5 Further issues
Here we consider some concerns that have been raised about the pragmatic account developed
above, as well as pragmatic treatments of ignorance implicatures more generally. First, R&U
point out that ignorance implicatures involving alternative questions under ‘wonder’ seem to be
local in the sense that they take scope below operators, e.g. quantifiers, that are syntactically
above this verb:
Crime: There is a crime with three suspects, Ann, Bill, and Carol. There are five detectives
investigating the case; one has already ruled out Carol but is still wondering whether it was
Ann or Bill. The others don’t know anything yet. I say:
(17) Exactly four detectives are wondering whether it was Ann, Bill, or Carol.
As R&U comment, (17) is acceptable in context. However, it is f alse on (9) since all five
detectives are such that (i) they do not know whether it was Ann, Bill or Carol, and (ii) every
information state they want to be in resolves the issue of whether it was Ann, Bill or Carol. So,
the pragmatic, redundancy-theoretic approach cannot capture our judgments, although R&U’s
theory can.
However, the empirical picture here is rather complex. For one thing, embedded disjunctive
polar questions do not always seem to pattern the way of (17), nor do embedded disjunctions
under ‘hope’:
Cake: Bill and Alice run a birthday cake delivery service. Five of my friends are waiting
for a delivery for my surprise party. Everyone knows that either Alice or Bill will make the
delivery, but Ted is the only one that knows Bill is at home sick. Nobody is sure of the exact
time of the delivery. The doorbell rings. Consider:
(18) ?? Exactly four people are wondering whether-or-not Bill or Alice is at the door.
(19) ?? Exactly four people hope that Bill or Alice is at the door.
To my ear, (18) is unacceptable in context. This is predicted by (9), since this account
makes the report false (all five friends are such that (i) they do not know whether-or-not Bill
or Alice is at the door, and (ii) every information state they want to be in resolves the issue
of whether-or-not Bill or Alice is at the door). However, this report is true on R&U’s account,
since exhaustification takes place regardless of whether the embedded question is an alternative
question or a disjunctive polar question. Similarly, (19) is unacceptable in context. This is
predicted on (8), since this account makes the report false (all five friends are such that (i) it
is doxastically possible but not necessary that Bill or Alice is at the door, and (ii) every desire
world is one where Bill or Alice is at the door).
Moreover, the ignorance implicatures generated by embedded conjunctions also appear to
be local:
Dictator : Five professors heard a rumor that the dictator was killed by a sniper. One of
them knows for sure that the dictator is dead but isn’t sure how he died. I say:
(20) Exactly four professors are wondering whether the dictator is dead and was assassinated.
(21) Exactly four professors hope that the dictator is dead and was assassinated.
Like (17), (20) is acceptable in context. But just like (17), it is false and thus predicted to
be unacceptable on (9). However, it is also false on R&U’s account, since for all five professors
x, ‘Wx(the dictator was assassinated)’ is true. Similarly, (21) is acceptable, yet it is false on
(8).
8
Ignorance Implicatures Blumberg
To sum up, the ignorance implicatures of alternative questions embedded under ‘wonder’
do seem to be local, and thus are not predicted by pragmatic approaches that operate at
the utterance level. However, the ignorance implicatures of disjunctive polar questions under
‘wonder’ as well as disjunctions under ‘hope’ do not seem to be local, contrary to the predictions
of semantic accounts such as R&U’s. Furthermore, the ignorance implicatures of embedded
conjunctions do seem to be local, but this is captured by neither semantic nor pragmatic
accounts. Overall, then, the data appears to paint a rather complex picture and does not
clearly count in favor of either a pragmatic or semantic approach to ignorance implicatures.
Second, on (9) it makes a semantic difference whether an embedded alternative question
has exactly two alternatives, or more than two alternatives:
Visitors: Bill knows that either Alice or Ted will visit on Saturday at noon. On Friday, Bill
gets a message from Alice saying that she won’t be able to manage a visit. At noon on Saturday
Bill hears a knock on the door and rushes to open it. Before Bill answers, I utter:
(22) ?? Bill wonders whether Alice or Ted is at the door.
Visitors 2 : Bill knows that exactly one of Alice, Chris and Ted will visit Bill on Saturday at
noon. On Friday, Bill gets a message from Alice saying that she won’t be able to manage a
visit. At noon on Saturday Bill hears a knock on the door and rushes to open it. Before Bill
answers, I utter:
(23) ?? Bill wonders whether Alice, Chris or Ted is at the door.
Neither (22) nor (23) are acceptable in their respective contexts. However, it is easy to check
that (22) is f alse on (9) while (23) is true. Given that the pragmatic account developed here
uses (9) as a baseline semantics, it holds that while (22) is false, (23) is merely ‘pragmatically
unacceptable’. As several anonymous reviewers point out, this does not appear to be a good
prediction, since one can respond to (23) with ‘That’s false, since Bill knows that Alice isn’t at
the door’. That is, we seem to want to be able to say something stronger in response to (23)
than what is licensed by the pragmatic account. By contrast, R&U’s account predicts that both
(22) and (23) are false in their respective contexts.
But it is worth noting that it does not seem acceptable to respond to (2b) (‘Bill wonders
whether-or-not Alice or Ted is at the door’) with ‘That’s false, since Bill knows that Alice
isn’t at the door’. This is not predicted by R&U’s account, since (2b) is made false by it.
Also, it is acceptable to respond to (10b) (‘Bill wonders whether the dictator is dead and was
assassinated’) with ‘That’s false, since Bill knows that the dictator is dead’, but neither the
pragmatic approach nor R&U’s account predicts this. Once again, the data here does not
clearly speak in favor of either a pragmatic or semantic approach to ignorance implicatures.
6 Conclusion
Roelofsen and Uegaki (2016) showed that disjunctions embedded under inquisitive verbs such
as ‘wonder’ generate a certain type of ignorance implicature. I have suggested that a similar
sort of ignorance implicature arises from embedded conjunctions; moreover, that such implicatures
arise for a variety of non-doxastic attitude verbs. On the proposal developed here,
ignorance implicatures arising from both disjunctions and conjunctions are handled within the
same framework. On this account, these implicatures are fundamentally pragmatic, and can be
explained by a suitably sophisticated theory of contextual redundancy. I argued that such an
9
Ignorance Implicatures Blumberg
account is superior to a semantic approach to embedded disjunctions based on exhaustification,
since such accounts struggle with embedded conjunctions.
We have made progress on the topic of ignorance implicatures, but it should be clear from our
discussion that more work needs to be done. First, as mentioned at the end of §2, the account
presented here generates inferences that are often too weak; a strengthening mechanism needs to
be developed. Second, the judgments reported in §5 are based on introspection and discussion
with only a few native speakers; more work is needed to get a better sense of the empirical
landscape. Finally, it is not clear whether the sort of approach to redundancy presented in
§3 is ultimately adequate, and perhaps an account that employs local contexts should be used
instead (Mayr and Romoli, 2016). However, this would require giving a precise characterization
of the local contexts of attitude verbs which, as far as I am aware, has not yet been done.
*********
References
Maria Biezma and Kyle Rawlins, "Responding to alternative and polar questions," "Linguistics
and Philosophy", vol. 35
E. Chemla, "An epistemic step for anti-presuppositions", "Journal of Semantics," vol. 25
Ivano Ciardelli, Jeroen Groenendijk, and Floris Roelofsen. Inquisitive semantics. 2016. Lecture
notes.
Ivano A. Ciardelli and Floris Roelofsen. Inquisitive dynamic epistemic logic. Synthese, 192(6):
1643–1687, 2015.
Danny Fox. Two short notes on schlenker’s theory of presupposition projection. Theoretical
Linguistics, 34:237, 2008. ISSN 16134060. URL https://www.degruyter.com/view/j/
thli.2008.34.issue-3/thli.2008.016/thli.2008.016.xml.
Irene Heim. Presupposition projection and the semantics of attitude verbs. Journal of Semantics,
9(3):183–221, 1992.
Roni Katzir. Structurally-defined alternatives. Linguistics and Philosophy, 30(6):669–690, 2007.
Clemens Mayr and Jacopo Romoli. A puzzle for theories of redundancy: Exhaustification, incrementality,
and the notion of local context. Semantics and Pragmatics, 9(7):1–48, November
2016. doi: 10.3765/sp.9.7.
Floris Roelofsen and Wataru Uegaki. The distributive ignorance puzzle. In Proceedings of Sinn
und Bedeutung 21, 2016.
Wojciech Rostworowski. Descriptions and non-doxastic attitude ascriptions. Philosophical Studies,
forthcoming.
Uli Sauerland. Scalar implicatures in complex sentences. Linguistics and Philosophy, 27(3):
367–391, 2004.
Philippe Schlenker. Be articulate: A pragmatic theory of presupposition projection. Theoretical
Linguistics, 34(3):157–212, 2008.
Raj Singh. Maximize presupposition! and local contexts. Natural Language Semantics, 19
(2):149–168, Jun 2011. ISSN 1572-865X. doi: 10.1007/s11050-010-9066-2. URL https:
//doi.org/10.1007/s11050-010-9066-2.
Benjamin Spector and Yasutada Sudo. Presupposed ignorance and exhaustification: How scalar
implicatures and presuppositions interact. Linguistics and Philosophy, 40(5):473–517, 2017.
Kai von Fintel. Npi licensing, strawson entailment, and context dependency. Journal of Semantics,
16(2):97–148, 1999. doi: 10.1093/jos/16.2.97. URL http://jos.oxfordjournals.
org/content/16/2/97.abstract.
Thursday, December 14, 2017
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment