The Grice Club

Welcome

The Grice Club

The club for all those whose members have no (other) club.

Is Grice the greatest philosopher that ever lived?

Search This Blog

Wednesday, June 23, 2010

Revolutions in a Griceian Key

From Quinton, "From Wodehouse to Wittgenstein"

--- on the origin of modern science and its revolution:

Some commented excerpts:

Quinton writes:

"The scientific revolution which created the ['modern'] world is rightly described as taking place in the seventeenth century."

"Certainly the first signal achievement, the publication of Copernicus's heliocentric theory, occurred in 1548. But the main work was done in the following century. Copernicus's theory of the heavens was comparatively speculative, even if it benefited from improvements in observational astronomy which had come about in response to the needs of navigation. But the work of Kepler, Galileo and, culminatingly, Newton, was based on an altogether more exalted variety of empirical evidence about the movements of heavenly bodies."

One is reminded of Newton's "Hypotheses non fingo", a favourite motto of my teacher in early modern philosophy.

Quinton goes on:

"Galileo's main contribution was in mechanics, the mathematically formulated theory of the movement of matter, starting out from the study of projectiles and failing bodies. It lent support to the helio-centrism of Copernicus. So did Galileo's use of his improved telescope to discover imperfections on the sun and moon which undermined the old theory that the heavens are made of different material from the earth and are subject to different laws. Newton's Principia brought the movements of matter in the heavens and on the earth under a single scheme of laws which seemed to have attained an unimprovable completeness."

From cosmologia to anthropologia:

"The implication of seventeenth-century physics that the physical universe as a whole is a vast machine was extended to cover the human body. The first step here was Harvey's discovery of the circulation of the blood, which was actually observed by Leeuwenhoek, who also used the microscope to observe micro-organisms."

--- Hypothesis and hypostasis:

"The central feature of these advances is that they involve the explanation of straightforwardly observable things by what is not straightforwardly observable. In some cases the unobserved explanatory factors turn out to be discoverable by instrumentally assisted observation — hitherto unknown planets by the telescope, spermatozoa by the microscope. In other cases the hidden factor is an
intuitively unobvious order which makes systematic sense of what appears at first to be a confused variety, as in celestial mechanics."

Apperance and reality:

"The lesson of these dey elopments is that the world is not what it appears to be. The earth is not at rest but is in axial and orbital rotation. And there is more to the world than there appears to be: the corpuscles that prefigure the developed atomism of nineteenth-century physics and chemistry and the micro-organisms that prefigure the cells of nineteenth-century biology."

Ontology:

"This, more or less ontological aspect of the scientific revolution is bound up with its most important methodological characteristic: the application of mathematics to natural fact embodied in the practice of exact numerical measurement. There were new mathematical developments which directly served the investigation of nature. Some of these were notational: Stevin's decimals and Napier's logarithms.
Others were substantive new disciplines: Descartes' analytic geometry, Pascal's probability theory and, above all, the calculus of Newton and Liebniz."

----- R. B. Jones has extended on the idea of Leibniz's 'characteristica universalis', elsewhere, which somehow prefigures Frege's conceptual script or notation.

Quinton:

"The general upshot was the idea that the essential determinants of natural happenings are the measurable properties of things, many of them beyond the range of unassisted observation, acting in accordance with mathematically formulated laws whose values are to be established by or inferred from observation and experiment.

The proof of the pudding:

"The immediate technological fruit was not so much productive as instrumental. The theory of projectiles was of use to artillerymen; the theory of chances to gamblers. But the primary technological application of the new scientific knowledge was in the production of instruments for the acquisition of further knowledge and not for
the Baconian purpose of the, relief of man's estate: accurate pendulum clocks, reliable compasses, telescopes, microscopes, barometers, thermometers. It was only in the eighteenth century that the absolutely transforming event of the introduction of steam power took place. The first steam engines were used to pump water out of mines and so enable immense new deposits of coal to be mined. Then came the use of steam to convey railway wagons and to drive textile machinery, which thus become independent of human muscles and a convenient supply of failing water. The development of mechanical power enormously accelerated in the nineteenth century. Oil supplemented coal as a source of steam. The petrol-burning internal combustion engine increased human mobility on land and in the air. Electricity was recruited to supply light, heat and, eventually, power. A scientific revolution in chemistry took place in the nineteenth century in close association with the development of the chemical industry, a process, beginning with synthetic dyes, that was soon to supply mankind with a host of new, artificial materials. Electromagnetic theory led to the discovery of radio waves with the result of enormously increased long-distance communication and, in due course, a major change in the human use of leisure."

The underlying principle: mechanism.

"The governing idea behind this complex of Western scientific and technological advances is that the natural world and everything in it is mechanical in character, that every natural process, from the Movements of the planets to the circulation of the blood, operates in accordance with mathematically formulated laws, which we must rely on observational or experimental measurement to establish."

The pre-moderns:

"Aristotle's physics was qualitative and unsystematic. It registered the evident distinguishing features of different natural kinds and classified them on the basis of their evident similarities. It could explain what happened sufficiently to
appease a curiosity that was not too penetrating by saying that things act as they do because it is their nature to do so."

"But if it was cognitively comforting it was practically useless since it was unable to predict."

"All action is directed towards the future. As agents we want to know what will happen if we do this or do not do that. Explanation that is not tied to prediction gratifies a merely contemplative appetite."

Plato, the mathematician:

"In the Renaissance the authority of Plato had been invoked to combat that of Aristotle. For the most part the effect of this revival of Plato was confined to the humanities. Dog-Latin, syllogistic logic and metaphysical theology were discarded for Ciceronian Latin, rhetoric and scholarly cultivation. It is an historical mistake, which many have absorbed from the Renaissance humanists, to suppose that the authority of Aristotle in the Christian West stretches right back to the beginning of the Middle Ages."

"Although a fragment of [Aristotle's] logic was available from the first, the main body of his writings did not come into the possession of the turopean West until it was retrieved from the Arabs from the mid-twelfth century onwards and that was after the deaths of the first generation of truly medieval philosophers: Anselm, Abelard, and Peter Lombard, compiler of the Sentences which became the formal basis of the bulk of later medieval thought."

"Before the recovery of Aristotle, medieval thought had been Platonic and, in particular, neo-Platonic. The Platonic dialogue most influential in the early Middle Ages was the Timaeus, Plato's Pythagorean cosmological speculation, which puts forward a mathematical conception of the world as fashioned by a Demiurge out of geometrical figures. For Plato [...], the physical world is not wholly real. All that is real, all that can be truly known, is timeless. [... T]he physical world, to the extent that it can be known, must be understood by pure mathematical speculation."

EMPIRICISM.

"The conscious opposition of the scientific revolution of the seventeenth century to Aristotle's doctrine of the physical world received some impulsion from the fifteenth and sixteenth century revival of Plato. But the Pythagorean mysticism which holds that all that exists is made of numbers was brought down to earth by the idea that the numbers which matter are the measured characteristics of empirically observable things."

"It was a crucial moment in the process of deliverance from Platonism when Kepler was forced by his devotion to truth to admit that the planets move, not in perfect circles, but in elliptical orbits."

"The main thesis that I wish to propose is that [the character of modern science] can be attributed to [religion], in particular to the cosmological element, the general theory of the nature of the world, which in each case the ... religion embodies." "[Neo-platonic] Christianity ... accepts the reality of the sensible world: on the other hand, it affirms a supernatural order in which the omnipotent creator of the natural world is located, together with other spiritual beings, intervening in nature once he has created it by means of miracles and other revelations of his existence and purposes, and, most dramatically, by his
personal incarnation in it in human form."

"In the reverse direction, so to speak, the immortality of the soul is linked in Christianity with the doctrine of the resurrection of the body. One of the first heresies proscribed by Christianity is Gnosticism with its conception of the
natural world as evil, and although during the neo-Platonic phase of Christian theology the secondary, derivative, more or less minimal reality of the natural world is affirmed, it was never declared to be an illusion."

"Two aspects of the orthodox Christian cosmology serve as foundation stones for the great Western scientific constructions of the seventeenth century."

"First there is the idea of God as a rational intelligence setting his creation to work in accordance with a unitary scheme of intelligible laws."

---- Grice was fascinated by this and would literally "play 'God'", i.e. in his words: 'use 'God' as an explanatory device'. Notably in metaethics, this has come to be seen as the theory of the ideal observer. Grice preferred to call it the 'genitorial programme'.

Quinton:

"Secondly, there is the idea of God as something behind the perceptible surface of the world but constantly involved with it. Under these assumptions the sensible world is neither a chaos nor autonomous. It works in accordance with unobvious laws and the ultimate cause of what happens is also unobvious, hidden behind its perceptible surface."

"The scientific revolution naturalises these two notions: the underlying causes of what is perceived are not absolutely or metaphysically transcendental, but simply
beyond the reach of straightforward observation."

-----


mental laws in accordance with which the perceptible world works
are not perceptible regularities, but laws of the behaviour of hidden
explanatory factors. Newton's first law of motion illustrates the
.second point: nothing that we perceive is in direct conformity with
it, nothing that we perceive continues permanently in the same state
of motion, since everything we perceive is subject to impressed forces
of some kind or other.

The three cosmologies — Confucian immanence, Hindu transcen-
dence and Christian dualism — correspond to three distinct attitudes
to the life of mankind on earth. For the Confucian, the right mode
of life is one of peaceful coexistence with nature, taking such conve-
nient advantage of it as one can, but for the most part
accommodating oneself harmoniously to it. For the Hindu, nature
is a kind of bad dream to which one should take up an attitude of
passive submission, principally concerning oneself while it lasts with
the search. for liberation from it, like a prisoner who does not seek
to make himself comfortable in jail, but is always preoccupied with
thoughts of escape. Indian magical beliefs are a marginal mitigation
of this cast of mind, like the unpredictable benevolence of a guard,
a chink in the system that leads nowhere beyond itself. For the
Western, nature is a field of opportunity, for adventure and enter-
prise, a gift to be made use of. The technological implications of these
attitudes hardly need to be set out in detail.

There is a final parallel which I shall mention briefly. In the history
of philosophical reflection on scientific knowledge three main
competing theories have been developed. The first of these, which
takes a formal deductive system as the ideal model of a science, rests
such knowledge on the rational intuition of axiomatic first princi-
ples. The second, instrumentalism, takes the theoretical elements of
science to be a kind of conceptual shorthand for propositions about
what can be directly perceived. The third, realistic doctrine, takes
scientific theory to be inferred but literal truth about the hidden, fine
structure of the physical world. Intuitionism, the doctrine of Plato
and Descartes, has an affinity with Indian assumptions about nature
and our knowledge of it. Instrumentalism, the theory of scientific.
knowledge of the pragmatists, and before them of Berkeley and Ernst
Mach, is Chinese in spirit. (So also is the practice of Aristotle, even
if in theory he shows his dependence on Plato by endorsing an
axiomatic theory of the nature of scientific knowledge.) Realism is
broadly the position of Locke in all its none too coherent good sense.
I must confess that I share the belief attributed to my distinguished
Oxford predecessor, H.A. Prichard: 'In the end, when the truth is
known, I think it will turn out to be not very far from the philos-
ophy of Locke.' Locke regards the hidden reality of the material
world as altogether too inaccessible and takes too subjective a view
of the direct objects of perception. But no major structural modifi-
cations are needed.

It could be objected to what I have been arguing that all I have
done is to show some rough general parallel between the cosmolo-
gies of Confucianism, Hinduism and Christianity on the one hand
-and, respectively, the sciences of China, India and the West on the
other. But I have surely wanted to claim more than that, specifically
that the religious cosmologies are causally related to the corre-
sponding bodies of scientific knowledge and belief. I do indeed want
to make that claim. The principal justification for doing so must be
that which must support any such claim: in each case the alleged
cause is precedent in time and contiguous in space to the alleged
effect. Together with the fact — and I have tried to make out that it
is a fact — of the near-identity of content between the cosmological
teaching of the religions and the operating assumptions of the corre-
sponding sciences, that ought to be enough.

But to prevent some possibilities of misinterpretation, some qual-
ifications must be made. In particular, I am not claiming that the
cosmologies are the sole and entire cause of the forms of science to
which they are connected, nor am I claiming that they are the indis-
pensably necessary conditions of the sciences that correspond to
them. My claim, in other words, is limited by acknowledging the two
factors called by Mill the complexity and the plurality of causes.

The cosmological assumptions I have picked out as causes are, as
is usual in such cases of explanation, each only one of the factors
which, in the circumstances of each case, had to be present for the
effect to ensue. There are plenty of societies with traditional religious
cosmologies which have not produced any science at all, nothing
even to be compared with the comparatively limited or partial scien-
tific achievement of the Chinese and Indian civilisations. Clearly
social factors must also be taken into account: stability, a degree of
prosperity to provide the requisite leisure for scientific work, some
urbanisation to provide for the development of a critical community
of investigators, a fairly substantial amount of literacy.

Some historians of thought, attracted to more or less Marxist
styles of historical explanation, have attributed the rise of modern
Western science to the existence of a confident and secure merchant
class, not preoccupied with politics and war, nor constrained by the
disciplines imposed by priestly status, their minds broadened by the

-14-

10 comments:

  1. Bravo! Masterpiece Thea-turr theme now.

    I like this--especially his points on the limits of raw empiricism--though it seems a bit...quotidian. Baron Quinton (von Quinton? Bill n Hillary Quinton) often pens an eloquent synopsis without saying a great deal, or arguing for anything in particular. And affirming Lockean empirical realism 101 as structurally sound?? I doubt Grice (not to say most analytical phil.s) would approve of that.

    ReplyDelete
  2. Yes, he was a master of style, Baron Quinton. And it's hard to find what he is arguing for. He belongs to that category of litterateurs, as it were. It is interesting that when Grice gives a more or less full list of the members of the Play Group, Quinton is not featured. My guess is that he socialised more with Ayer and others at Ayer's group. Of D. F. Pears, in his obituary, for example, it is said that he participated in BOTH Austin's Play Group AND the Ayer group. So I think we have here, with Baron Quinton, one who participated mainly in Ayer's group.

    Apparently, what he wants to argue is the influence of neo-platonic cosmology, as embodied in some kind of religion, but science has been notably secular. His point about mechanism combines with his point about extensionalism (in "Properties and classes"), so these WERE topics that interested Grice.

    Grice dedicates a bit of his 1957 "Metaphysics" to the 'metaphysic' of science -- he notes (along with Strawson and Pears -- it's a joint essay) that Kant incorporates the science of his day onto his metaphysics (critical rationalism), and that Collingwood is the first to consider the historical presuppositions of the 'science' of the day to yield cosmological pictures.

    Grice would have indeed a thing or two to say about each of the generalisations by Quinton. On the whole Quinton presents himself as an empiricist, a diagnostic realist, and a materialist, and a linguistic analyst -- whereas Grice described himself as an 'irreverent, conservative, dissenting, rationalist'.

    ReplyDelete
  3. Appearance and reality:

    "The lesson of these developments is that the world is not what it appears to be. The earth is not at rest but is in axial and orbital rotation. And there is more to the world than there appears to be: the corpuscles that prefigure the developed atomism of nineteenth-century physics and chemistry and the micro-organisms that prefigure the cells of nineteenth-century biology."


    That doesn't sound so sympatico with Locke's basic empiricism (tho' admittedly ECHU's a bit more subtle than many philo-hacks realize.... primary/secondary qualities, abstract ideas, so forth). Newtonian mechanics was confirmed by experience, but the new mathematics (ie calculus) had a great deal to do with it as well--similarly for Kepler's equations (K.'s importance often disregarded).

    Inferring heliocentrism was a profound step forward, but proving, mathematically, that planets move in elliptical orbits round El Sol--a somewhat greater inference in terms of sublimity, I believe (and was not too appealing to monotheists of any sort--).

    Here Baron Q. suggests rationalism was a key part of the rise of experimental science, regardless of his supposed empiricism. Or perhaps...it's Kantian in some sense. I've never been convinced of the synthetic a priori (maybe you can sell me on it), but at times sense that Kant was attempting a somewhat...cognitive explanation of knowledge--including scientific, reconciling sensibility and the understanding. One wants to think physics for example has a certain necessity (and it does), but the syn.a priori may not quite work--didn't Sellars say it was...a contradiction of sorts? (moreover Kant's example of Syn.a Pri...."every event has a cause" itself was already in question in 19th century; after quantum mechanics, seemingly untenable (tho' some determinists might claim that's more about the limits of human knowledge than against classical causality, perhaps...and it's Kant's..mechanistic aspects that I respect, actually...)

    ReplyDelete
  4. Yes, the synthetic a priori is SOME swallow! Grice would like to play with the playmates of his own children (aged 9 and 11), "Can a sweater be red and green all over? No stripes allowed" -- and there are unpublished notes on the synthetic a priori he left out of his "Studies in the Way of Words". And you are very right that Locke´s ECHU is a pretty subtle thing. I was fascinated to learn that the manuscript of that thing read, "Essay concerning HumanE understanding" -- my type of empiricism, Locke anyway. This essay by Quinton is from his potpourri "From Wodehouse to Wittgenstein", but apparently he has written especifically on Kant, too. And of course Hume -- he has a whole book on him. And also Bacon. Into the history of ideas, indeed! Kant was indeed into the harmony of "sensibility" and "understanding" -- but, warts and all, I think I prefer Strawson´s to Quinton´s Kant -- and I thought it was genial of Strawson to entitle his little treatise on Kant, "The bounds of SENSE" -- which is precisely what for Kant "science" is mainly all about!

    The point about "appearance" and reality has a stronger bite than Quinton allows and I loved his analysis of the three main "uses" of "appear" in "The Problem of Perception". In this essay, intended more to the general public, he could care less about those three uses and just speaks generally about the "weltanschauung" that Science brought to the picture. Or something.

    His dismissal of Aristotelianism is also slightly simplistic, as when he claims Aristotelian science is NOT predictive. Indeed, the whole point of the "potency" or power qua causal force has been defended recently by neo-Aristotelians who claim there is more to the Stagirite´s idea of science than the moderns ever allowed.

    ReplyDelete
  5. I have read a bit of Strawson's BOS, and frankly was unimpressed. He's one of these philosophers who believes he can get rid of all the spooky, vague metaphysics of Kant and have something remaining. I can understand a slightly "cognitive" reading of Kant (tho' traditionalists, like Herr Scruton claim das ist Verboten), but with Strawson, there's hardly anything remaining (tho' I don't pretend to be pro-Kantian...). However my point was more about the synthetic a priori in particular, especially in regard to scientific/classical physics. If it can't be defended (and IM of the opinion it ..Kan't, whether in regard to cl.physics, or mathematics), then it seems the honest filosopher must ask whether the First Critique can even....like stand, as a whole?? Not sure. Why bother with the obscure and vast Deduction, if the Syn. AP doesn't even...work

    By that, Im not saying that entails Hume or empiricists won, btw. Maybe Leibniz--and rationalism-- was in some sense closer to metaphysical truth (tho' that's not to bless his...theodicy).

    I attempted some discussion of this topic a while ago on my humble blog--Synthetic a priori

    ReplyDelete
  6. That's very good. I'll have a look. Indeed, I was thinking of the expression, silly one, 'eye-opener', as when some people say, "Grice was an eye opener" to them, and I was thinking that Kant getting awoken from dogmatic slumbers by eye-opening Hume compared! Yes, the synthetic a priori is all we need -- and I am vastly frustrated by all those philosophy teachers who have the schema on blackboards -- as Kripke has --: a double entry schema: justification: a priori/a posteriori, S included in P or not: analytic, synthetic. It seems the Kantian thing REQUIRES the synthetic a priori, and then it's not forthcoming! I think you are right that Leibniz was closer to the truth. The problem with Kant was trying to provide a synthesis between rationalism and empiricism and I think, alas, a cognitive reading is just the right thing. What I don't like about cognitive science, though, with Scruton, is two things: the word, 'science' as applied to it, and the adjective 'cognitive' -- but hey, you kant have everything!

    ReplyDelete
  7. Since your blog entry relates to "Every event has a cause" perhaps we can discuss that separately!

    ReplyDelete
  8. Every event has a cause

    Yes, that's a rather daunting topic, however (see Heisenberg's ...not completely sympathetic comments on Kant as well)--.

    Re the traditional and/or Scrutonian reading of the First Critique: that would hold only---I posit--if...substance dualism, a Res Cogitans holds (and Kant hisself refers to St. Descartes in the Deduction, does he not) in some sense--in brief. Too brief, probably (see my comment on the Kant post as well) I for one can't quite accept substance dualism (tho' object to raw materialism as well).

    Or when you die, and are transported to the judgment hall, and ....chingada, some small, prussian looking gent sits with his wig on and says ...my account of the synthetic a priori was true--into hell, knave. Or not

    ReplyDelete
  9. Yes -- some small prussian looking gent -- with a tall Scots grandfather, though! (Just teasing). But then, perhaps we can look from the Kantian side of things. I sometime things HIS intellect was TOO determined. What he found he was impossible to conceive without he instilled on ALL humanity. "Every event has a cause" is one of those. Imagine you get to a place, where something happened.

    "No. This event did NOT have a cause" -- they explained to you (once properly translated to your vernacular). I would not think I would understand the comment. It sounds too much like Grice's account of the analytic (in "In defense of a dogma", with Strawson):

    "My neighbour's three-year old son is an adult!".

    Grice accepted that some things work for one's idiolect. So, in Kant's idiolect, that was possibly NOT something analytic to say ("This event was not caused") --. It may even be a German thing, or something.

    ReplyDelete
  10. You are right that if there was a revolution with Heisenberg, it's all about every event NOT having a cause. Mario Bunge has written extensively on this -- and his must be one of the earliest books devoted to causation or lack thereof in science! Ah, for a return to Mill's more modest methods! (as I say alliteratively).

    ReplyDelete