The Grice Club

Welcome

The Grice Club

The club for all those whose members have no (other) club.

Is Grice the greatest philosopher that ever lived?

Search This Blog

Sunday, March 29, 2020

Grice tries to distinguish between buletically iffy and non-iffy (or "Kantian," 'echoing Kant') utterances -- and he succeeds!


Grice explores at some length four alternative interpretations of  an iffy buletic (as opposed to a non-iffy buletic): three formal, one material. The first interpretation is the horseshoe interpretation. A blind logical nose might lead us or be led to the assumption of a link between an buletically iffy utterance and a doxastically iffy utterance. Such a link no doubt exists, but the most obvious version of it is plainly inadequate. At least one other philosopher besides Grice has noticed that "If he torments the cat, have him arrested!" is unlikely to express an buletically iffy utterance, and that even if one restricts oneself to this or that case in which the protasis specifies a will, we find pairs of examples like "If you will to go to Chicago,  travel by AA via Cleveland!" or "If you will to go to Philadelphia, see a psychiatrist!" -- where it is plain that one is, and the other is not, the expression of a buletically iffy utterance. For fun, Grice does not tell which!. A less easily eliminable suggestion, yet one which would still interprets the notion of a buletically iffy utterance in terms of that particular logical form to which "if", 'hypothetical' and 'conditional' attach, would be the following. Let us assume that it is established, or conceded, as legitimate to formulate an 'if' utterance in which not only the apodosis is couched in some mode other than
the doxastic, as in this or that conditional command. "If you see the whites of their eyes, shoot fire!" but also the protasis or some part (clause) of them. In which case all of the following might be admissible conditionals. Thus, we might have a doxastic protasis ("If the cat is sick, take it to the vet”), or a mixed (buletic-cum-doxastic protasis ("If you are to take the cat to the vet AND there's no cage available, put it on Martha's lap!), and buletic protasis ("If you are to take the cat to the vet, put it in a cage!”). If this suggestion seems rebarbative, think of this or that quaint "if" utterance (when it is quaint) as conditionalised versions of this or that "therefore"-sequence, such as:
buletic-cum-doxastic premises ("Take the cat to the vet! There isn't a cage. Therefore; Put the cat on Martha's lap!"), buletic premise (“Take the cat to the vet! Put it in a cage!"). And then, maybe, the discomfort is reduced. Grice next considers a second formal interpretation or approach to the buletically iffy/non-iffy utterance. Among 'if' utterances with a buletic apodosis some will have, then, a 'mixed’protasis  (partly judicative, partly volitival)
and some will have a purely doxastic protasis (“If the cat is sick, take him to the vet!). Grice proposes a definition of the iffy/non-iffy distinction. A buletically iffy utterance is an iffy utterance the apodosis of which is buletic and the protasis of which is buletic or mixed (buletic-cum-dxastic) or it is an elliptical version of such an iffy utterance. A buletically non-iffy utterance is a buletic utterance which is not iffy or else, if it is iffy, has a purely doxastic protasis. Grice makes three 'quick comments' on this second interpretation. First, re: REAL IMPERATIVES: The structures which are being offered as a way of interpreting an iffy and a non-iffy  imperative do not, as they stand, offer any room for the appearance this or that buletic modality like 'ought' and 'should' which are so prominently visible in the standard examples of those kinds of imperatives. The imperatives suggested by Grice are explicit imperatives. An explicit buletic utterance is "Do such-and-such!"; not 'You/one ought to do such and such'. Grice thinks one can modify this suggestion to meet the demand for the appearance or occurrence of 'ought' (etc) if such occurrence is needed. Second, it would remain to be decided how close the preferred reading of Grice’s 'deviant' conditional imperatives would be to the accepted interpretation of standard hypothetical imperatives. But even if there were some divergence, that might be acceptable if the 'new' interpretation turns out to embody a more precise notion than the standard conception. Third, NEUSTICAL vs TROPICAL protases. There are, Grice thinks, serious doubts of the admissibility of conditionals with a NON-doxastic protasis, which are for Grice connected with the very difficult question whether the doxastic and the buletic modes are co-ordinate or
whether the doxastic mode is in some crucial fashion (but not in other)  _prior_ (to use Suppes’s qualification) to the buletic. Grice confesses he does not know the answer to that question. A third formal interpretation  links the iffy/non-iffy distinction to the absolute-relative value distinction. An iffy imperatives would be _end-relative_ and might be analogous to an evidence-relative probability. A non-iffy imperatives would not be end-relative.
Finally, a fourth Interpretation is not formal, but _material_. This is close to part of what Kant says on the topic. It is a distinction between an imperative being _escapable_ (iffy), through the absence of a particular _will_ and its not being escapable (non-iffy). If we understand the idea of escabability sufficiently widely, the following imperatives are all escapable, even though their logical form is not in every case the same: "Give up popcorn!," "To get slim, give up popcorn!", “If you will to get slim, give up popcorn!" Suppose Grice has no will to get slim. One might say that the first imperative (“Give up popcorn!”) is 'escaped', provided giving up popcorn has nothing else to recommend it, by _falsifying_ 'You should give up popcorn'. The second and the third imperatives (“To get slim, give up pocorn!” and “If you will to get slim, give up popcorn!”) would not, perhaps, involve _falsification_ but they would, in the circumstances, be _inapplicable_  to Grice – and inapplicability, too, counts, as escape. A non-iffy imperative however, is in no way escapable. Re: the Dynamics of Imperatives in Discourse, Grice then gives three examples which he had discussed in _Aspects of Reason_, which concern _arguments_ (or “therefore”-chains). This we may see as an elucidation to grasp the logical form of buletically iffy utterance (elided by the ‘therefore’, which is an ‘if’ in the metalanguage) in its dynamics in argumentation. We should, Grice suggests, consider not merely imperatives of each sort,  together with the range of possible
characterisations, but also the possible forms of _argument_ into which_particular_ hypothetical imperatives might  enter. Consider: “ Defend the Philosophy Department! If you are to defend the philosophy department,
learn to use bows and arrows! Therefore, learn to use bows and arrows!" Grice says he is using the dichotomy of original-derived value. In this example, in the first premise, it is not specified whether the will is original or derived, the second premise specifies 'conducive to' (means), and the conclusion would involve a 'derived' will, provided the second premise is doxastically satisfactory. Another example would be: “Fight for your country! If you're to fight for your country, join up (one of the services)! Therefore, join up!” Here, the first premise and the conclusion do not specify the protasis. If the conclusion did, it would repeat the second premise. Then there’s "Increase your holdings in oil shares! If you visit your father, he'll give you some oil shares. Therefore, visit your father!” This argument (purportedly) transmits value. Let us explore these characterisations by Grice
with the aid of R. M. Hare's distinctions. For Hare in a hypothetical imperative, "the protasis contains a neustic/tropic" (_Language of Morals_, p.37). A distinction may be made between 'hypothetical  imperative' and a term
used by Grice in his first interpretation of  the hypothetical imperative, that of 'conditional command ('If you see the whites of their eyes, shoot fire!”). A hypothetical imperative can be distinguished from a _conditional_ imperative (“If you want to make bread, use yeast!”, “If you see anything suspicious, telephone the police!") by the fact that modus ponens is not valid for it. One may use 'conditional imperative' for an imperative which is
grammatically conditional, and reserve 'conditional command' for a command which is conditional on the  satisfaction of the protasis. Thus,on this view, treating the major premise of the following argument as a hypothetical imperative, turns the “therefore”-chain invalid'. Major Premise as Hypothetical Imperative (“If you will to make someone mad,  give him drug D! You will to make Peter mad; therefore, give Peter drug D!”). The hypothetical imperative tells one only what _means_ to adopt to achieve a given _end_ in  a way which does not necessarily _endorse_ the adoption of that end,  and hence of the means to it. Thus someone might say, "If you will to make someone mad, give him drug D!" But, of course, even if you will to do that, you must _not_ try to do so. On the other hand,  the following is arguably valid because the major premise is a 'conditional' imperative  and not a mere hypothetical one. Major Premise as Conditional Imperative: “You will to make someone mad, give him drug D! Make Peter mad! Therefore, give Peter drug D!”. We can explain this in terms of the  presence of the neustic in the antecedent of the imperative working as the major premise. The supposition that the protasis of a hypothetical imperative contains a clause in the buletic mode neatly explains why the argument with the major premise as a hypothetical imperative is not valid. But the argument with the major premise as a conditional imperative is, as well as helping to differentiate a hypothetical imperative from a _conditional_  one. For, if the protasis of the major premise in the hypothetical imperative is volitival, the mere fact that you will to make Peter mad does not license the inference of the imperative to give  him the drug; but this _can_ be inferred from the major premise of the  hypothetical imperative _together with an imperative -- the minor premise  in the conditional imperative – to make Peter mad. In other words,  whether the subordinate clause contains a
neustic thus does have have a consequence  as to the validity of inferences into which the complex sentence enters. The Principle of Mode Constancy in Buletic and Doxastic Inference. One may tries to elucidate Grice's ideas on the logical form of the hypothetical imperative proper. His suggestion is, admittedly, rather tentative. But it might be argued, in the spirit of it, that a  hypothetical imperative is of the form "i. If !p, !q,  .p, Therefore, !q.” But this violates a principle of MODE CONSTANCY. A phrastic must remain _in the same mode_ (within the scope of the same _tropic_) throughout an argument. A conditional imperative does not violate the principle of Modal Constancy, since it is of  the form “If p, !q, !p. Therefore, !q". The question of the logical form of the hypothetical imperative is too  obscure to base much on arguments concerning it. There is an
alternative to Grice’s account of the validity of an argument featuring a conditional imperative.  This is to treat the major premise of a conditional imperative,  "as some have urged it should be" as an _indicative_ tantamount to  "In order to make someone mad, you have to give him drug D".  Then an utterer who EXPLICITLY conveys or asserts the major  premise of a conditional imperative and _commands_ the second premise is in consistency
committed to commanding the conclusion. "If" does not always connect phrastic with phrastic but sometimes connects two expressions consisting of a phrastic and a tropic. Consider: "If you walk past the post office, post the letter!" The antecedent of this imperative states, it seems, the _CONDITION_ under which the imperative  expressed becomes operative, and so can _not_ be construed buletically, since by uttering a buletic utterance, an utterer cannot EXPLICITLY convey or assert that a condition obtains. Hence, the protasis ought not be within the scope of the buletic "!", and whatever  we take to represent the form of the utterance above we  must not take "!(if p, q)" to do so. One way out. On certain interpretation  of the Isomorphism or aequi-vocality Thesis between Indicative and Imperative Inference the utterance has to be construed as an imperative (in the generic sense)  to make the doxasatic conditional "If you will walk past the post office,  you will post the letter" satisfactory. Leaving aside issues of the implicature of "if", that the utterance can _not_ be so construed  seems to be shown by the fact that the imperative to make the associated doxastically “iffy” utterance satisfactory is conformed with by one who does not walk past the post office. But it seems strange at best to say that the utterance is  conformed with in the same circumstances. This 'strangeness’ or ‘bafflingliness,’ as Grice prefers, is aptly explained away in terms of the implicatum. At Oxford, Dummett was endorsing this idea that a conditional
imperative be construed as an imperative to make an indicative  material conditional true. Dummett urges to divide conditional imperatives into those whose antecedent is "within the power of the  addressee" --- like the
utterance in question -- and those in which it is not. Consider: "If you go out, wear your coat!" One may be not so much concerned with how to _escape_ this, as Grice was, but how to _conform_ it. A child may choose not to go out in order to comply with the imperative. For an imperative whose protasis is_not_ within the power of the addressee ("If anyone tries to escape, shoot him!”) it is indifferent whether we treat it as a conditional
imperative or not, so why bother. A  small caveat  here: If no one tries to escape, the imperative is _not violated_. One might ask, might there not be an important practical  difference bewteen saying that an imperative has not been violated and  that it has been complied with? Dummett ignores this distinction. One may feel think there is much of a practical difference  there (Is Grice an intuitionist? Suppose that you are a frontier guard and the antecedent has remained unfulfilled. Then, whether we say that you complied with it, or simply did not _violate_ it will  make a great deal of difference if you appear before a war  crimes tribunal.  For Dummett, the fact that in the case of  an imperative expressed by a conditional imperative  in which the antecedent is not within the agent's power, we should NOT say  that the agent had obeyed just on the ground that the protassi is false, is no ground for construing an imperative as expressing a conditional  command: for there is no question of fixing what shall constitute obedience  independently of the determination of what shall constitute disobedience. This complicates the issues. One may with Grice (and Hare, and Edgley) defend imperative inference against other Oxonian philosophers, such as A. J. P. Kenny or B. A. O. Williams. What is questioned by the sceptics about
imperative inference is whether if each one of a set of imperatives is used with the  force of a command, one can infer a _further_ imperative with that force  from them. Cf. Wiggins on Aristotle on the practical syllogism. One may be more conservative than Hare, if not Grice. Consider “If you stand by Jane, don't look at her! You stand by Jane. Therefore, don't look at her!” This is valid. However, the following, obtained by anti-logism, is not: “If you stand by Jane, don't look at her! Look at her! Therefore, you don't stand by Jane." It may seem more reasonable to some to deny Kant’s thesis, and maintain that anti-logism is valid in imperative inference than it is to hold onto Kant’s thesis and deny that antilogism is valid in the case in question. Then there’s the question of the implicate involved in the ordering of modes. Consider: “Varnish every piece of furniture you make! You are going to make a table; therefore, varnish it! This is _prima facie_ valid. The following, however, switching the order of the modes in the premises is not: “You are going to varnish every piece of furniture that you make. Make a table! Therefore; varnish it!” (The connection between the ‘if’ and the ‘therefore’ is metalinguistic, obviously – the validity of the ‘therefore’ chain is proved by the ‘associated’ “if” that takes the premise as, literally, the protasis and the consequence as the apodosis.  Conversational Implicature at the Rescue. Problems with "or": Consider Ross's infamous example: “Post the letter! Therefore, post the letter or burn it!” as 'invalid' (Ross 1944:38 -- endorsed by  B. Williams). To permit to do p or q is  to permit to do p and to permit to do q. Similarly, to give permission  to do something is to lift a prohibition against doing it. Admittedly,  Williams does not need this so
we are stating his claim more strongly than he  does. One may review Grice’s way out (defense of the validity of  the utterance above in terms of the implicatum. Grice claims that in Ross’s infamous example (valid, for Grice), whilst (to state it roughly) the premise's "permissive presupposition" (to use the rather clumsy term introduced by Williams) is entailed by it, the conclusion's is  only _conversationally implicated_.  Typically for an isomorphist, Grice says this is something  shared by indicative inferences. If, being absent-minded, Grice asks his wife, ‘What have I done with the letter?' and she replies, ‘You have posted it or burnt it,’ she
conversationally implicates that she is not in a position to say which Grice has done. She  also conversationally implicates that Grice may not have post it,  so long as he has burnt it. Similarly, the future  tense indicative, "You are going to post the letter" has the conversational implicature  "You may be not going to post the letter so long as you are going to burn it".  But this surely does not validate the introduction rule for “OR,” to wit:  "p; therefore, p or q"" One _can_ similarly, say: "Eclipse will win. He may not, of course, if it rains. And I _know_ it will not rain". Problems with "and.” Consider: “Put on your AND jump out! Therefore, jump out!” Someone who _only_ jumps out of an aeroplane  does not fulfil 'Put on your parachute and jump out!'  He has done only what is necessary, but not sufficient to fulfil it.  Imperatives do not differ from indicatives in this respect, except that fulfilment takes the place of belief or ‘doxa’, which is the form of  acceptance apprpriate to a doxasatic utterance, as the name implies.  Someone who is told "Smith put on his parachute AND jumped out"  is entitled to believe that
Smith jumped out. But if he believes that this is _all_ Smith did he is in error” (Cf. R. Edgley). One may discuss Grice’s test of cancellability in the case of the transport officer who says: "Go via Coldstream or Berwick!" It seems the transport officer's way of expressing  himself is extremely _eccentric_, or ‘conversationally baffling,’ as Grice prefers – yet ‘validly.’If the transport officer  is not sure if a storm may block one of  the routes, what he should say is “_Prepare_ to go via Coldstream or Berwick!" As for the application of Grice's test of EXPLICIT cancellation here, it yield, in the circumstances, the transport officer uttering: "Go either via Coldstream or Berwick!  But you may not go via Coldstream if you do not go via Berwick, and you may not go via Berwick if you do not go via Coldstream." Such qualifications (what Grice calls ‘explicit cancellation of the implicature’) seem to the addressee to empty the buletic mode of utterance of all content and is thus reminiscent of Henry Ford's utterance to the effect that people can choose what colour car they like provided it is black. But then Grice doesn’t think Ford is being illogical, only Griceian and implicatural!

ARISTOTLE. Practical syllogism.
CLARKE D. Mode constancy in mixed
inferences. _Analysis_ 30.
DUNCAN-JONES AE. Symposium on
imperatives. See MITCHELL.
FOOT P. Morality as a system of a
hypothetical imperatives. In _Moral
Philosophy_.
Discussed by Grice in _The Conception of
Value_.
GEACH PT. Imperative inference. _Analysis_ 23
GREGOR MJ. _The categorical imperative_.
GRICE HP. The conception of value. Clarendon
Aspects of Reason. Clarendon
HARE RM. _The language of morals_.
Clarendon.
Some alleged differences between imperatives
& indicatives.
_Mind_ 76, repr. in _Practical Inferences_.
HOLDCROFT D. _Words & deeds_.
Ch V: Hare's theses: phrastics & neustics.
KENNY AJP. Practical inferences. _Analysis_ 26
MAYO B. Symposium on imperatives.
See MITCHELL.
MITCHELL B. Imperatives.
Aristotelian Society 52.
PATON HJ. _The categorical imperative_
WILLIAMS BAO. Imperative inference.
_Analysis_ 23
WILLIAMS T. The concept of the categorical
imperative.

No comments:

Post a Comment