1941. Personal identity,
Mind, vol. 50, pp. 330-50, repr. in J. R. Perry, Personal identity, University
of California Press, Berkeley, David Hume, Hume's quandary about personal
identity, Hume on personal identity, Hume's account of personal identity,
personal identity, revisited, the logical-construction theory of personal
identity, 1977, The H. P. Grice Papers, Series II (Essays), carton 4-folder 12
and Series V (Topical), carton 7-folders 7-9, BANC MSS 90/135c, The Bancroft
Library, The University of California, Berkeley. Keywords: ‘I,’ personal
identity, first person, first personal pronoun, Locke, Hume, someone, somebody.
If in 'Negation and privation,' Grice tackles Aristotle, he now tackles Locke.
Indeed, seeing that Grice went years later to the topic as motivated by, of all
people, J. C. Haugeland, rather than perhaps the more ‘academic’ milieu that
Perry offers, Grice became obsessed with Hume’s sceptical doubts! Hume writes
in the “Appendix” that when he turns his reflection on himself, Hume never can
perceive this self without some one or more perceptions.
Nor can Hume ever perceive any thing but the perceptions. It is the
composition of these, therefore, which forms the self, Hume thinks.
Hume grants that one can conceive a thinking being to have either many or few
perceptions. Suppose, says Hume, the mind to be reduced even below the life of
an oyster. Suppose the oyster to have only one perception, as of thirst or
hunger. Consider the oyster in that situation. Does the oyster conceive any thing
but merely that perception? Has the oyster any notion of, to use Gallie’s
pretentious Aristotelian jargon, self or substance? If not, the addition of
this or other perception can never give the oyster that notion. The
annihilation, which this or that philosopher, including Grice’s first post-war
tutee, A. G. N. Flew, supposes to follow upon death, and which
entirely destroys the oyster’s self, is nothing but an
extinction of all particular perceptions; love and hatred, pain
and pleasure, thought and sensation. These therefore must be the
same with self; since the one cannot survive the other.
Is self the same with substance? If it be, how can that question have
place, concerning the subsistence of self, under a change
of substance? If they be distinct, what is the difference betwixt them? For his
part, Hume claims, he has a notion of neither, when conceived
distinct from this or that particular perception. However extraordinary Hume’s
conclusion may seem, it need not surprise us. Most philosophers,
such as Locke, seems inclined to think, that ‘personal identity’
arises from consciousness. But consciousness is
nothing but a reflected thought or perception, Hume suggests. This
is Grice’s quandary about personal identity and its implicata. Some
philosophers have taken Grice as trying to provide an exegesis of Locke.
However, their approaches surely differ. What works for Grice may not work for
Locke. For Grice it is analytically true that it is not the case that Person1 and Person may have the same experience. Grice
explicitly states that he thinks that his logical-construction theory is a
modification of Locke's theory. Grice does not seem terribly interested to find
why it may not, even if the York-based Locke Society might! Rather than introjecting
into Locke's shoes, Grice's strategy seems to dismiss Locke, shoes and all.
Specifically, it not clear to Grice what Locke's answer in the 'Essay' would be
to Grice's question about this or that 'I' utterance that he sets his analysis
with. Admittedly, Grice does quote, albeit briefly, directly from Locke’s
'Essay.' As far as any intelligent being can repeat the idea of any past action
with the same consciousness it had of it at first, and with the same
consciousness it has of any present action, Locke claims, so far the being is
the same personal self. Grice tackles Locke’s claim with four objections. These
are important to consider since Grice sees as improving on Locke. A first
objection concerns icircularity, with which Grice easily disposes by following
Hume and appealing to the experience of memory or introspection. A second
objection is Reid's alleged counterexample about the long-term memory of the
admiral who cannot remember that he was flogged as a boy. Grice dismisses this
as involving too long-term of a memory. A third objection concerns Locke’s
vagueness about the 'aboutness' of 'consciousness,’ a point made by
Hume in the ‘Appendix.’ A fourth objection concerns again circularity, this
time in Locke's use of 'same' in the definiens ‒ cf. Wiggins, 'Sameness and
substance.' It’s extraordinary that Wiggins is philosophising on anything
Griceian. Grice is concerned with the implicatum involved in the use of the
first person singular. 'I will be fighting soon.’ Grice means ‘in body and
soul.’ The utterance also indicates that this is Grice’s pre-war days at
Oxford. No wonder his choice of an example. What else could he have in his
soul? The topic of 'personal identity,’ which label Hume and Austin found
pretentious, and preferred to talk about the illocutionary force of 'I,’ has a
special Oxonian pedigree, perhaps as motivated by Hume’s challenge, that Grice
has occasion to study and explore for his M. A. Lit. Hum. with Locke’s ‘Essay’
as mandatory reading. Locke, a philosopher with whom Oxford identifies most,
infamously defends this memory-based account of 'I.’ Up in Scotland, Reid reads
it and concocts this alleged counter-example. Hume, or Home, if you must,
enjoys it. In fact, while in the 'Mind' essay he is not too specific about
Hume, Grice will, due mainly to his joint investigations with J. C. Haugeland,
approach, introjecting into the shoes of Hume ‒ who is idolised in The New
World ‒ in ways he does not introject into Locke's. But Grice's quandary is
Hume's quandary, too. In his own approach to 'I,’ the Cartesian ego, made
transcendental and apperceptive by Kant, Grice updates the time-honoured
empiricist mnemonic analysis by Locke. The first update is in 'style.' Grice
embraces, as he does with ‘negation,’ a logical construction,’ alla Russell,
via Broad, of this or that 'I' utterance, ending up with an analysis of a
'someone,’ less informative, utterance. Grice's immediate source is W. P.
Gallie's essay on self and substance in the pages of ‘Mind.’ ‘Mind’ was still a
'review of psychology and philosophy,’ so poor Grice had no much choice. In
fact, Grice is being heterodoxical or heretic enough to use the Broad’s
taxonomy, straight 'from the other place' of ‘I’ utterances. The
logical-construction theory is a third proposal, next to the Bradleyian
idealist 'pure-ego' theory and the misleading 'covert-description' theory.
Grice deals with the Reid's allged counterexample of the brave
officer. “Suppose,” Reid says, and Grice quotes verbatim, “a brave officer
to have been flogged when a boy at school, for robbing an orchard, to have
taken a standard from the enemy in his first campaign, and to have been made a
general in advanced life. Suppose also, which must be admitted to be possible,
that when he-2 took the standard, he2 was conscious of his having been flogged at school, and
that, when made a general, he3 was conscious of
his2 taking the standard, but had absolutely
lost the consciousness of his1 flogging. These
things being supposed, it follows, from Locke's doctrine, that he1 who is flogged at school is the same person as him2 who later takes the standard, and that he2 who later takes the standard is the same person as him3 who is still later made a general. When it follows, if there
be any truth in logic, that the general is the same person with him1 who is flogged at school. But the general’s consciousness
does emphatically not reach so far back as his1 flogging. Therefore, according to Locke's doctrine, he3 is emphatically not the same person as him1 who is flogged. Therefore, we can say about the general that he3 is, and at the same time, that he3 is not the same person as him1 who was flogged at school. Grice, who’ll later add a temporal
suffix to “=,” yielding, “The flogged boy =t1 the brave officer,
and the brave officer =t2 the admiral. But the admiral ≠t3 the flogged boy. In ‘Mind,’ Grice tackles the basic
analysans, and comes up with a rather elaborate analysans for a simple 'I' or
‘Someone’ statement. Grice just turns to a generic affirmative variant of the
utterance he had used in 'Negation.' It is now 'Someone, viz. I, hears that the
bell tolls.’ It is the affirmative counterpart of the focus of his earlier
essay on negation, 'I do not hear that the bell tolls. Grice dismisses what,
‘in the other place,’ was referred to as privileged-access, and the
indexicality of 'I,' an approach that will be made popular by J. R. Perry, who
however reprints Grice's essay in his influential collection for the University
of California Press. By allowing for ‘someone, viz. I,’ Grice seems to be relying
on a piece of reasoning which he’ll later, in his first Locke lecture, refer to
as ‘too’ good.' 'I hear that the bell tolls; therefore, someone hears that the
bell tolls.' Grice attempts to reduce this or that 'I' utterance ('Someone,
viz. I, hears that the bell tolls’) is in terms of a chain or sequence of
mnemonic states. It poses a few quandaries itself. While quoting from this or
that recent philosopher such as Gallie and Broad, it is a good thing that Grice
has occasion to go back to, or revisit, Locke and contest this or that infamous
and alleged counterexample presented by Reid and Hume. Grice adds a
methodological note to his proposed logical-construction theory of personal
identity. There is some intricacy of his reductive analysis, indeed logical
construction, for an apparently simple and harmless utterance (cf. his earlier
essay on 'I do not hear that the bell tolls'). But this intricacy does not
prove the analysis wrong. Only that Grice is too subtle. If the reductive
analysis of ‘not’ is in terms of 'each state which I am experiencing is
incompatible with ...'), that should not be a minus, or drawback, but a plus,
and an advantage in terms of philosophical progress. The same holds here in
terms of the concept of a ‘temporary state.’ Much later,
Grice reconsiders, or revisits, indeed, Broad's remark and re-titles his
approach as ‘the’ or ‘a’ ‘logical-construction theory of personal identity.’
And, with Haugeland, Grice re-considers Hume's own vagaries, or quandary, with
personal identity. Unlike the more conservative Locke that Grice favours in the
pages of ‘Mind,’ eliminationist Hume sees 'I' as a conceptual muddle, indeed a
metaphysical chimæra. Hume presses the point for an 'empiricist'
verificationist account of 'I.' For, as Russell would rhetorically ask, 'What
can be more direct that the experience of myself?,' The Hume Society should
take notice of Grice's simplification of Hume's implicatum on 'I,’ if The Locke
Society won’t. As a matter of fact, Grice calls one of his metaphysical construction
routines the 'Humeian projection,' so it is not too adventurous to think that
Grice considers 'I' as an intuitive concept that needs to be
'metaphysically re-constructed' and be given a legitimate Fregeian sense. Why
that label for a construction routine? Grice calls this metaphysical
construction routine 'Humeian projection,' since the 'mind' (or soul) as it
were, 'spreads over' its objects. But, by 'mind,' Hume does not necessarily
mean the 'I.' Cf. 'The mind's I.' Grice is especially concerned with the
poverty and weaknesses of Hume's criticism to Locke's account of personal
identity. Grice opts to revisit the Lockeian memory-based of this or that
'someone, viz. I' utterance that Hume rather regards as 'vague,' and
'confusing.' Unlike Hume's, neither Locke's nor Grice's reductive analysis of
personal identity is reductionist and eliminationist. The
reductive-reductionist distinction Grice draws in Retrospective epilogue as he
responds to J. M. Rountree-Jack on this or that alleged ‘wrong’ on ‘meaning
that.’ It is only natural that Grice would be sympathetic to Locke. Grice
explores these issues with J. C. Haugeland mainly at seminars. One may wonder
why Grice spends so much time in a philosopher such as Hume, with whom he
agreed almost on nothing! The answer is Hume’s influence in the Third World
that forced Grice to focus on this or that philosopher. Surely Locke is less
popular in the New World than Hume is. One supposes Grice is trying to save
Hume at the implicatum level, at least. The phrase or term of art, 'logical
construction' is Russell's and Broad's, but Grice loved it. Rational
reconstruction is not too dissimilar. Grice prefers Russell's and Broad's more
conservative label. This is more than a terminological point. If Hume is right
and there is NO 'intuitive' concept behind 'I,' one cannot strictly
re-construct it, only 'construct' it. Ultimately, Grice shows that, if only at
the implicatum level, we are able to provide an analysandum for this or
that 'someone, viz. I' utterance without using 'I,' by implicating only
this or that mnemonic concept, which belongs, naturally, as his theory of
‘negation’ does, in a theory of philosophical psychology, and again a lower
branch of it, dealing with ‘memory.’ The topic of personal identity unites various
interests of Grice. The first is ‘identity’ (‘=’) simpliciter. Instead of
talking of the meaning of 'I,' as, say, Anscombe would, Grice sticks to the
traditional category, or keyword, for this, i. e. the theory-laden, personal
identity, or even personal sameness. Personal identity is a type of identity,
but ‘personal’ adds something to it. Surely Hume was stretching ‘person’ a bit
when using the example of a soul ‘with a life lower than an oyster. Since Grice
follows Aristotle’s De Anima, he enjoys Hume’s choice, though. It may be argued
that ‘personal’ adds Locke’s ‘consciousness,’ and rational agency. Grice plays
with the body-soul distinction. 'I, viz someone or somebody, fell from the
stairs,’ perhaps differs from ‘I will be fighting soon.’ This or that 'someone,
viz. I’ utterance may be purely 'bodily.' Grice would think that the idea that
his soul fell from the stairs sounds, as it would to Berkeley, harsh. But then
there’s this or that one may be mixed utterance. 'Someone, viz. I, plays
cricket,’ where surely your bodily mechanisms require some sort of control by
the soul. Finally, this or that may be purely 'souly' ‒ the one Grice ends up
analysing, 'Someone, viz. I, hear that the bell tolls.' At the time of his
‘Mind’ essay, Grice may have been unaware of the complications that the concept
of a ‘person’ may bring as attached in adjective form to 'identity.’ Ayer did,
and Strawson and Wiggins will, and Grice learns much from Strawson. Since
Parfit, this has become a common-place topic for analysis at Oxford. A person
as a complexum of a body-soul spatio-temporal continuant substance. Ultimately,
Grice finds a theoretical counterpart here. A pirot may become a human, which
Grice understands ‘physiologically.’ That is not enough. A pirot must aspire,
via meteousis, to become a person. Thus, 'person' becomes a technical term in
Grice’s grand metaphysical scheme of things. 'Someone, viz. I, hear that the
bell is tolls' is analysed as ≡df, or if and only if, a hearing
that the bell tolls is a part of a total temporary tn souly state S1 which is one
in a series such that any state Sn, given this
or that condition, contains as a part a memory Mn of the experience of hearing that the bell tolls, which is a
component in some pre-sequent t1n item, or contains an experience of hearing that the
bell tolls a memory M of which would, given this or that condition, occur
as a component in some sub-sequent t2>tn item, there being no sub-set of items which is
independent of the rest. Grice simplifies the reductive analysans. ‘Someone,
viz. I, hears that the bell tolls’ iff ‘a hearing that the bell tolls is a
component in an item of an ‘interlocking’ series, with emphasis on
‘lock,’ series of this or that ‘memorable’ and ‘memorative’ total
temporary tn state S1. Is Grice’s 'Personal
identity' ever referred to in the Oxonian philosophical literature? Indeeed.
Parfit mentions, which makes it especially memorable and memorative. P. Edwards
includes a reference to Grice's ‘Mind’ essay in the entry for 'Personal
identity,' as a reference to Grice et al on ‘Metaphysics,’ is referenced in
Edwards's encyclopædia entry for 'metaphysics.' Grice does not attribute
privileged access or incorrigibility to 'I' or the first person. He always
hastens to add that 'I' can always be substituted, salva veritate (if baffling
your addressee A) by 'someone or other,' if not 'some-body or other,’ a
colloquialism Grice especially detested. Grice's agency-based approach requires
that. I am rational provided thou art, too. If, by explicitly saying he is a
Lockeian, Grice surely does not wish us to see him as trying to be original, or
the first to consider this or that problem about 'I; i.e. someone.’ Still,
Grice is the philosopher who explores most deeply the 'reductive analysis' of
'I, i.e. someone.' Grice needs the reductive analysis because human agency
(philosophically, rather than psychologically interpreted) is key for his
approach to things. By uttering 'The bell tolls,' U means that someone, viz.
himself, hears that the bell tolls, or even, by uttering 'I, hear, viz. someone
hears, that the bell tolls,' U means that the experience of a hearing that
the bell tolls is a component in a total temporary state which is a member
of a series such that each member would, given certain conditions, contain
as an component one memory of an experience which is a component in a
pre-sequent member, or contains as a component some experience a memory of
which would, given certain conditions, occur as a component in a
post-sequent member; there being no sub-set of members which is
independent of the rest. ‘Thanks,’ the addressee might reply. ‘I didn’t know
that! The 'reductive' bit to Grice’s analysis needs to be emphasised. For
Grice, a person, and consequently, a ‘someone, viz. I’ utterance, is, simpliciter,
a logical construction out of this or that Humeian experience. Whereas
in Russell, as Broad notes, a logical construction of this or that
philosophical concept, in this case ‘personal identity,’ or cf. Grice’s earlier
reductive analysis of ‘not,’ is thought of as an 'improved,' 'rationally
reconstructed' conception. Neither Russell nor Broad need maintain that the
logical construction 'preserves' the original meaning of the analysandum
'someone, viz. I, hears that the bell tolls,’ or ‘I do not hear that the bell
tolls’ ‒ hence their paradox of reductionist analysis. This ‘change of subject’
does not apply to Grice. Grice emphatically intends to be make explicit,
if rationally reconstructed (if that's not an improvement) through reductive
(if not reductionist) analysis, the concept Grice already claims to have. One
particular development to consider is within Grice’s play group, that of A. M.
Quinton. Grice and Quinton seem to have been the only two philosophers in
Austin’s play group who showed any interest on ‘someone, viz. I.’ Or not!The
fact that Quinton entitled his thing ‘The soul’ didn’t help. Note that Woozley
was editing Reid on “Identity” in 1941. Cf. A. E. Duncan-Jones on ‘man’s
mortality.’ Note that Quinton’s immediate trigger is Shoemaker. Grice writes
that he is not “merely a series of perceptions,” for he is “conscious of a
permanent self, an I who experiences these perceptions and who is
now identical with the I who experienced perceptions yesterday.” So, leaving
aside that he is using ‘I’ with the third person verb, but surely this is no
use-mention fallacy, it is this puzzle that provoked his thoughts on
temporal-relative “=” later on. As Grice notes, Butler argued that
consciousness of experience can contribute to identity but not define it. Grice
will use Butler in his elaboration of conversational benevolence versus
conversational self-interest. Better than Quinton, it is better to consider A.
G. N. Flew in Philosophy, vol. 96, on Locke and the problem of personal
identity, obviously suggested as a term paper by Grice! Wiggins cites Flew.
Flew actually notes that Berkeley saw Locke’s problem earlier than Reid, which
concerns the ‘transitiveness’ of ‘=.’ Recall that Wiggins’s tutor at Oxford was
a tutee by Grice, J. L. Ackrill.
Thursday, April 2, 2020
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment