Thursday, May 14, 2020
H. P. Grice, "Chomsky and his transformations"
Noam Avram Chomsky, born in Philadelphia, Pennsylvania, received his
Ph.D. in linguistics from the University of Pennsylvania in 1955. Since 1955 he
has taught at MIT, where he currently holds the position of Institute
Professor. Chomsky gained the attention of philosophers early on in his career
by the introduction of mathematical/logical tools for the description of
linguistic phenomena. In this respect his early work was influenced by figures
such as Nelson Goodman and W. V. Quine, both of whom are thanked in the
introduction to his Syntactic Structures(1957). Nevertheless, Chomsky’s
principal philosophical significance relates to his rejection of the approach
to language and mind taken by Quine and many other analytic philosophers.
Indeed, Chomsky has been a direct participant in several key philosophical
debates in the last half century, taking issue with interlocutors such as
Quine, Donald Davidson, Hilary Putnam, Saul Kripke, and John Searle on the
nature of language and mind. In the view of many analytic philosophers, language
is a social object that has been established by convention for purposes of
communication. Chomsky’s take is different: the conception of language as an
external social object is unfruitful (if not incoherent), and the only
plausible strategy for the empirical scientist is to view language, or rather,
the language faculty, as a natural object that is part of our biological
endowment.1 The exact nature of this picture has evolved since the 1960s, and
it has taken the form of a “principles and parameters model,” which can be
viewed in the following way: think of the language faculty as being a largely
pre-wired mechanism with a set of switches (parametric settings) which can be
set in various ways depending upon the environmental setting into which the language-learner
is born. The task of the linguist is to study this mechanism, to deduce its
initial state, and to understand what the possible parametric settings are,
that is, to determine precisely what variation is allowed by the language
faculty. Chomsky (1986a) introduces the terms “I-language” and “E-language” to
distinguish his general thesis about the language faculty from the loose
collection of theories about language that hold that it is social or external.
The I-language/E-language distinction is useful, since it highlights the idea
that the object of study in linguistics is “internal” in a sense, and is not
directly concerned with “external” phenomena like written corpora of data.
Chomsky is thus opposed to the conception reflected in the definition given by
the American linguist Leonard Bloomfield: language is “the Blackwell Companions
to Philosophy: A Companion to Analytic Philosophy Edited by A. P. Martinich,
David Sosa Copyright © Blackwell Publishers Ltd 2001 totality of utterances
that can be made in a speech community.” For Chomsky, Ilanguages are “in the
mind, ultimately the brain.” To highlight the difference between these two
approaches, consider the two different pictures of linguistic rules that
emerge. Traditional grammarians (citing conventions and common practice for
written English) give us superficial rules such as “Do not end a sentence with
a preposition” or “Use ‘whom’, not ‘who’ when the pronoun has accusative or
dative case.” On the other hand, generative grammarians like Chomsky note that
there are more subtle and interesting linguistic rules which go unnoticed by
the traditional grammarian but which seem to be employed by a broad class of
speakers. For example, no native speaker of English would recognize (1) (below)
as a wellformed question in English, even though there are seemingly similar
structures like (2) that are quite acceptable to language users: 1 *Who did
John see the boy that Bill hit? 2 Who did John say that Bill hit? The account
for the difference in these cases is subtle, and the details of the explanation
have changed as generative grammar has evolved.2 The fact remains, however,
that native speakers of English know that (2) is acceptable and that (1) is
not, and further it is clear that no one is taught to have this preference.
Whatever rules account for the judgments about (1) and (2) they are far more
subtle than the usual prescriptive rules. Similar considerations apply to the
following examples, discussed in Chomsky (1986b; see also 1982, 1986a). 3 John
filed every letter without reading it. 4 What letter did John file without
reading it? Somehow speakers of English know that if we delete the pronoun “it”
in these two sentences (as in (3¢) and (4¢)) the effects on meaning are
different. 3¢ John filed every letter without reading. 4¢ What letter did John
file without reading? (4¢) is ambiguous in a way that (3¢) is not. Both (3¢)
and (4¢) have the meaning in which the filing was done without some
(unspecified) reading taking place, but (4¢) also preserves the most salient
possible meaning of (4): it can still be understood as asking what letter John
filed without reading it – the filed letter. Clearly, no one taught us this,
there is no convention (tacit or otherwise) to use language in this way, and no
prescriptive grammarian ever stipulated that we should interpret these
sentences in this manner. But, just as clearly, these facts describe the
linguistic competence of a large class of individuals. This is just one of the
problems for traditional grammars and for the more general assumption that
languages are objects that are established by convention. Our best attempts to
stipulate the rules – or to make explicit the conventions – just scratch the
surface about our linguistic competence. In Chomsky’s words, Traditional
grammars do not describe the facts of language; rather, they provide hints to
the reader who already has, somehow, the requisite “notion of structure” and
general conceptual resources, and can use the hints to determine the
expressions of the language and PETER LUDLOW 420 what they mean. The same is
true of dictionaries. . . . Traditional grammars and dictionaries, in short,
presuppose “the intelligence of the reader”; they tacitly assume that the basic
resources are already in place. (1994b: 160) Likewise, institutions such as the
Académie Française do not stipulate as much as they think they do. At best they
give some superficial rules of thumb for proper linguistic behavior regarding
French. They cannot even begin to cover the range of facts of interest to
practicing linguists. Indeed, for a generative linguist, the traditional notion
of a language like French or German is suspect at best (see Chomsky 1980b: ch.
6). In what sense is a “speaker of German” from the Dutch border of Germany and
a “speaker of German” from Bavaria speaking the same language? (Especially
given that their languages are not mutually intelligible?) The fact that we say
these individuals speak the same language is more of a political decision than
anything else, and indeed an individual raised in northern Germany and an
individual raised in The Netherlands may find that their languages are more
mutually intelligible than the two aforementioned German citizens do. Saying
that the two German citizens speak the same language is at best a loose way of
talking about some contextually relevant (and certainly political rather than
linguistic) similarities. Chomsky (1994b) compares it to saying that two cities
are “near” each other; whether two cities are near depends on our interests and
our mode of transportation and virtually not at all on brute facts of
geography. The notion of “same language” is no more respectable a notion in the
study of language than “nearness” is in geography. Informally we might group
together ways of speaking that seem to be similar (relative to our interests),
but such groupings have no real scientific merit. As a subject of natural
inquiry, the key object of study has to be the language faculty and its set of
possible parametric variations. One might think it possible to retreat slightly
by giving up on the idea of an E-language and endorsing a notion of E-dialect
or E-idiolect, but even this retreat will not save the
language-as-external-object position, according to Chomsky. Considerations that
make it arbitrary when to say that two individuals speak the “same language”
also apply to saying when they speak the “same dialect.” Furthermore, we have
no way of identifying the linguistic forms that would be part of a given
individual A’s E-idiolect. In the first place, A speaks in different ways with
different groups of individuals (say A uses a different vocabulary among
philosophers than among family members) and indeed at different stages of life
(contrast A’s use of language at age 3 and age 30). Do all of these ways of
speaking count as being part of the same idiolect? What unifies them other than
that they are ways in which A happens to have spoken? Still worse, we certainly
can’t identify A’s E-idiolect with some corpora of utterances and inscriptions,
for these intuitively include speech and spelling errors. On the basis of what
can we say that a given hiccup is an error and not part of the spoken corpus of
A’s E-idiolect? If we try and identify errors by appealing to A’s language
community, that lands us back in the problem of individuating E-languages and
E-dialects; there is simply no fact of the matter about which language
community A belongs to. On the I-language approach, however, this problem takes
the form of a well-defined research project. The idiolect (I-idiolect) is
determined by the parametric state of A’s NOAM CHOMSKY 421 language faculty;
the language faculty thus determines A’s linguistic competence. Speech
production that diverges from this competence can be attributed to performance
errors. Thus, the competence/performance distinction is introduced to
illuminate the distinction between sounds that are part of A’s grammar and
those that are simply mistakes. The E-language perspective has no similar
recourse. For Chomsky, these are among the myriad reasons we have for
abandoning the idea that language (as studied by the linguist) is a social
object, and adopting the perspective that it is a natural object. But what kind
of natural object? Since children acquire their linguistic competence without
serious formal training (certainly none that would cover the facts in (1)–(4))
and indeed with impoverished data, Chomsky hypothesizes that there must be an
innate language acquisition device which accounts for this competence. The task
of the linguist is to learn the initial state of this device, and to determine
the possible parametric variations of the device that are brought about by
exposure to linguistic data. This thesis has led to controversy; indeed, it has
come to be at the center of recent innateness debates between Chomsky and
Piaget, and Quine among others (see QUINE). The debates have turned on whether
language acquisition requires a dedicated language faculty or whether “general
intelligence” is enough to account for our linguistic competence. Chomsky
considers the “general intelligence” thesis hopelessly vague, and argues that
generalized inductive learning mechanisms make the wrong predictions about
which hypotheses children would select in a number of cases. Consider the
following two examples from Chomsky (1975, 1980a). 5 The man is tall. 6 Is the
man tall? Chomsky observes that confronted with evidence of question formation
like that in (5) and (6) and given a choice between hypothesis (H1) and (H2),
the generalized inductive learning mechanism will select (H1). (H1) Move the
first “is” to the front of the sentence. (H2) Move the first “is” following the
first NP to the front of the sentence. But children apparently select (H2),
since in forming a question from (7) they never make the error of producing
(8), but always opt for (9). 7 The man who is here is tall. 8 *Is the man who
here is tall? 9 Is the man who is here tall? Note that this is true despite the
fact that the only data they have been confronted with before encountering (7)
is simple data like (5) and (6). Chomsky’s conclusion is that whatever accounts
for children’s acquisition of language it cannot be generalized inductive
learning mechanisms, but rather must be a system with structure-dependent
principles/rules. In effect, one has to think of the language faculty as being
a domainspecific acquisition module. 3 Obviously the distinction between
I-language and E-language puts Chomsky at odds with a number of philosophers on
the nature of language, but it also leads to a number of subsidiary
philosophical disputes, not least of which are those disputes that are PETER
LUDLOW 422 driven by questions about the nature of rules and representations
(or principles and parameters) in cognitive science. For example Quine extends
his “gavagai” argument and attendant skepticism about meanings to similar
skepticism about grammatical rules. At the core of Quine’s worry is the idea
that if several rule systems are consistent with the linguistic behavior of an
individual, then there can be no fact of the matter about what set of rules is
actually being employed (see QUINE). Chomsky (1969, 1975, 1980) has made
several responses to this argument. In the first place, Chomsky takes Quine’s
argument to be a rehash of the standard scientific problem of the underdetermination
of theory by evidence. So, for example, even if there are several grammars that
are consistent with the available linguistic facts (not linguistic behavior,
for Chomsky, but intuitions about acceptability and possible interpretation) we
still have the additional constraint of which theory best accounts for the
problem of language acquisition, acquired linguistic deficits (e.g. from brain
damage), linguistic processing, etc. In other words, since grammatical theory
is embedded within cognitive psychology, the choice between candidate theories
can, in principle, be radically constrained. But further, even if we had two
descriptively adequate grammars, each of which could be naturally embedded
within cognitive psychology, there remain standard best theory criteria
(simplicity, etc.) which can help us to adjudicate between the theories. A more
recent assault on rules and representations has come from Kripke’s
reconstruction of Wittgenstein’s private language argument (see KRIPKE).
According to that argument, there can be no fact of the matter about what rules
and representations a system of unknown origin may be following. Kripke
concludes: if statements attributing rule-following are neither to be regarded
as stating facts, nor to be thought of as explaining our behavior . . . it
would seem that the use of the idea of rules and of competence in linguistics
needs serious reconsideration, even if these notions are not rendered
meaningless. (1982: 31 n. 22) Chomsky’s initial (1986b: ch. 4) response to the
Kripke/Wittgenstein argument appears to be that there is a fact of the matter
about what rules a computational system is operating on, but in more recent
articles (1993, 1994b, 1995a) he has argued that the Kripke/Wittgenstein
argument applies only to artifacts and not to natural objects. That is,
computers are artifacts – the products of human intentions – and hence there is
no fact about their design that exists apart from those intentions. The
principles and parameters of the language faculty, on the other hand, are
embedded within cognitive psychology and ultimately facts about human biology.
Therefore the structure of the language faculty is no less grounded than, for
example, the human genome. Chomsky has also clashed with Searle over the possibility
of rules in cognitive science that are “in principle” inaccessible to
consciousness. Can there be aspects of the mental which are not “in principle”
accessible to consciousness? Searle argues that there cannot be (see SEARLE).
Chomsky (1990, 1994a) argues that the notion of “in principle” in Searle’s
argument is vacuous. For example, what evidence is there that the grammatical
principles governing our judgments about examples (1)–(9) can’t be accessible
to consciousness? Is it a law of logic that there could not be a species with a
language faculty just like ours but with full conscious access to its
principles and NOAM CHOMSKY 423 parameters? Chomsky also notes that Searle must
introduce the notion of “blockage” to cover those cases in which an individual,
perhaps through brain damage, is able to correctly solve a problem, but be
unable to say how it was solved. On Searle’s theory, such a person has “in
principle” access but suffers from “blockage.” But Chomsky observes that it is
entirely arbitrary as to what counts as blockage and what counts as in
principle inaccessibility (e.g. perhaps an unfortunate mutation blocked our
access to the language faculty). Accordingly, Chomsky argues that such notions
have no role in naturalistic inquiry into the nature of the mental (and indeed,
cognitive science rightly ignores such notions). For Chomsky, it is not enough
to defend the idea that rules and representations (principles and parameters)
be a part of our naturalistic investigation into the mind, their character must
also be individualistically determined. That is, there is a brute fact about
the state of an individual’s language faculty and that fact is determined in
turn by facts about the individual in isolation, not by the environment in
which the individual is embedded. The thought is that if the language faculty
is part of our biological endowment, then the nature of the representations
utilized by the language faculty are fixed by our biology and are not sensitive
to environmental issues such as whether we are moving about on Earth or Twin
Earth. This appears to put Chomsky on a collision course with figures such as
Tyler Burge, who argues in “Individualism and Psychology” that the content of
the representations posited in psychology are determined at least in part by
environmental factors. If the notion of content involves externalist or
environmental notions, then Chomsky is dubious that it can play an interesting
role in naturalistic inquiry in cognitive psychology. Furthermore, since for
Chomsky “the mental” is simply an aspect of the natural world that is
investigated by sciences such as cognitive psychology (see Chomsky 1994a), the
nature of the mental itself must be individualistically and not environmentally
determined. Thus Chomsky (1993, 1995a) rejects the contentions of figures such
as Putnam (“The Meaning of ‘Meaning’ ”), Burge (“Individualism and the
Mental”), and Davidson (“Knowing One’s Own Mind”) that the contents of our
mental states are environmentally determined. More accurately, he dismisses the
talk of “contents” as ill-defined. Indeed, he is dismissive of the thought
experiments (Putnam’s “water/twater,” Burge’s “tharthritis,” and Davidson’s
“Swampman”) that purport to support externalism, and suggests that they reflect
philosophical prejudice more than any genuine facts about the mind/brain. If
environmentalism is to be rejected in psychology, then it naturally must be
rejected in semantics as well. That is, if the task of the linguist is to
investigate the nature of Ilanguage, and if the nature of I-language is a
chapter of cognitive psychology, and if cognitive psychology is an
individualistic rather than a relational science, semantics will want to eschew
relational properties like reference (where reference is construed as a
relation between a linguistic form and some object in the external
environment). Thus Chomsky (1981, 1995b) rejects the notion of reference that
has been central to the philosophy of language since about 1970, characterizing
it as an ill-defined technical term (certainly one with no empirical
applications), and suggesting that in the informal usage of “refer,”
individuals refer but linguistic objects do not. It also follows that semantic
theories that employ the technical notion of reference should be rejected in favor
of semantical theories which do not purport to state lanPETER LUDLOW 424
guage/world relations or, following Chomsky (1975a), in favor of a
Wittgensteinian approach in which there is no semantics per se, but rather one
in which the lingustic forms are used in certain ways. With this rejection of
referential semantics also comes a rejection of any attempt to use the
semantics of natural language to gain insights into ontology. It is no good to
argue from the structure of language to the existence of events, or plural
objects, or times, etc. As Chomsky has argued, there are a number of
constructions where the structure of language and the structure of the external
world diverge. For example, some noun phrases intuitively have counterparts in
the world (for example, the noun phrase “coats in the closet”) while others do
not (“flaws in the argument”): If I say “the flaw in the argument is obvious,
but it escaped John’s attention,” I am not committed to the absurd view that
among things in the world are flaws, one of them in the argument in question.
Nevertheless, the NP the flaw in the argument behaves in all relevant respects
in the manner of the truly referential expression the coat in the closet.
(1981: 324) Still more, Chomsky holds that there is a deep reason why our
ontology cannot be reflected in natural language: ontology is determined by
human intentions, while the representations in the language faculty are
naturalisitically determined. We do not regard a herd of cattle as a physical
object, but rather as a collection, though there would be no logical
incoherence in the notion of a scattered object, as Quine, Goodman, and others
have made clear. But even spatiotemporal contiguity does not suffice as a
general condition. One wing of an airplane is an object, but its left half,
though equally continuous, is not. . . . Furthermore, scattered entities can be
taken to be single physical objects under some conditions: consider a picket
fence with breaks, or a Calder mobile. The latter is a “thing,” whereas a collection
of leaves on a tree is not. The reason, apparently, is that the mobile is
created by an act of human will. If this is correct, then beliefs about human
will and action and intention play a crucial role in determining even the most
simple and elementary of concepts. (1975b: 204) The upshot is that pursuing
metaphysical questions by appeal to natural language (Ilanguage) is a dead end.
Perhaps less clear are the prospects for recent philosophical attempts to
employ the resources of generative grammar in carrying out Davidson’s program
of defining truth in natural language (see DAVIDSON). Chomsky’s view appears to
be that everything depends upon how these enterprises are interpreted. If they
are taken to be ways of executing a referential semantics, then they are
misguided. If the “semantic values” of these theories are taken in a
non-referential way then there is presumably room for interesting theorizing.
In this entry I’ve only scratched the surface of work by Chomsky that is
potentially of interest to philosophers (analytic or otherwise). One glaring
omission is his writing on social issues (see, for example, Chomsky 1987) and
on the media (see Herman and Chomsky 1988). I’ve also passed over his
contributions for formal language theory (Chomsky 1956, 1959) and general
issues in epistemology (Chomsky 1981). Finally, there is much that could have
been said about his earlier syntactic work (1957, 1965, NOAM CHOMSKY 425 1975a)
and the influence that it had in the philosophy of language in the 1960s and 1970s.
I hope, however, that the forgoing discussion has helped to illuminate some of
Chomsky’s work and placed it in the context of the debates that have taken
place in analytic philosophy since the mid-twentieth century, debates which
remain open largely due to his efforts.4 Notes 1 Chomsky often suggests that if
one digs beneath the surface, one finds that these philosophers (even the
behaviorists) are also believers in a language faculty which is part of our
biological endowment. See his discussion of Quine in Chomsky 1975b: 198ff. On
Chomsky’s view, of course, no coherent story can be told without this
assumption. 2 In Chomsky 1975b, 1977, for example, the idea is that (1)
represents a subjacency violation; formation of the question would require the
wh-element “who” to move out of both an NP (noun phrase) and an S (clause)
without a safe intermediate landing site. For more current accounts of these
constructions see Chomsky 1986a, 1995b. 3 However, Chomsky observes that it is
not modular in the sense of Fodor’s Modularity of Mind, but is an acquisition
module more in the sense of Gallistel in The Organization of Learning. 4 I am
indebted to Noam Chomsky, Richard Larson, and A. P. Martinich for comments on
an earlier draft of this article. Bibliography Works by Chomsky 1956: “Three
Models for the Description of Language,” I.R.E. Transactions of Information
Theory, IT-2, pp. 113–24. 1957: Syntactic Structures, The Hague: Mouton. 1959:
“On Certain Formal Properties of Grammars,” Information and Control 2, pp.
137–67. 1965: Aspects of the Theory of Syntax, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 1966:
Cartesian Linguistics, New York: Harper and Row. 1969: “Quine’s Empirical
Assumptions,” in Words and Objections: Essays on the Work of W. V. Quine, ed.
D. Davidson and J. Hintikka, Dordrecht: D. Reidel. 1971: Problems of Knowledge
and Freedom: The Russell Lectures, New York: Vintage Books. 1975a: The Logical
Structure of Linguistic Theory, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
(Originally appeared in unpublished manuscript form in 1955.) 1975b:
Reflections on Language, New York: Pantheon. 1977: “Conditions on Rules of
Grammar,” in Essays on Form and Interpretation, Amsterdam: Elsevier North
Holland, pp. 163–210. 1980a: “On Cognitive Structures and their Development: A
Reply to Piaget,” in Language and Learning: The Debate between Jean Piaget and
Noam Chomsky, ed. M. Piatelli-Palmerini, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press, pp. 35–54. 1980b: Rules and Representations, New York: Columbia
University Press. 1981: Lectures on Government and Binding, Dordrecht: Foris
Publications. 1982: Some Concepts and Consequences of the Theory of Government
and Binding, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 1986a: Barriers, Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press. 1986b: Knowledge of Language, New York: Praeger. 1987: The Chomsky
Reader, New York: Pantheon Books. PETER LUDLOW 426 1990: “Accessibility ‘in
Principle’,” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13, pp. 600–1. 1992: “Explaining
Language Use,” Philosophical Topics 20 (Spring), pp. 205–31. 1994a: “Naturalism
and Dualism in the Study of Language and Mind,” International Journal of
Philosophical Studies 2, pp. 181–209. 1994b: “Noam Chomsky,” in A Companion to
the Philosophy of Mind, ed. S. Guttenplan, Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, pp.
153–67. 1995a: “Language and Nature,” Mind 104, pp. 1–61. 1995b: The Minimalist
Program, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 1988 (with Herman, E.): Manufacturing
Consent: The Political Economy of the Mass Media, New York: Pantheon Books.
Works by other authors George, A. (ed.) (1989) Reflections on Chomsky, Oxford:
Blackwell Publishers. Harman, G. (ed.) (1974) On Noam Chomsky: Critical Essays,
Garden City: Anchor Books. Hornstein, N. and Antony, L. (eds.) (forthcoming)
Chomsky and His Critics, Oxford: Blackwell Publishers. Kripke, S. (1982)
Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press. NOAM CHOMSKY 427 428 35
No comments:
Post a Comment