Nothing is so uniquely personal to a man as his
memories. Our inner lives revolve around their contemplation, and in guarding
their privacy we seem almost to be protecting the very basiB of our
personalities. Most of our remembering is done in private and though we speak
of sharing our memories with others there seems to be a sense in which we could
no more share a memory than we could share a para , the best that we can do is
to try to describe it Yet unlike pains and aches, feelings of anger or of
amusement, there are no natural and public signs of memories. We do not have to
learn how to keep our recollections private as we have to learn to suppress
feelings of amusement, boredom and discomfort. To the prefatory expression “ I
remember ” there seems to attach the aura of a voluntary disclosure about
oneself. It would seem, then, natural and indeed essential to construe the
concept of remembering upon the model of an avowal about one’s state of mind,
about one’s inner and in- accessible experiences It is indeed traditional to
approach the concept of remembering as though it has this kind of logic ; in
this paper I shall argue that such an approach is radically at fault. Although
it is not my purpose either to examine particular theories of memory as they
bear upon the problem, or to do justice to the literature in the field by
subjecting it to detailed criticism, I shall attempt to mention what seem to me
to he typical and mistaken moves made in analysing the concept And I E J la ^U
3e Sbi by considering Hume’s analysis as it is presented in the xieatise,
because not only does it present in its purest form a thesis which I wish to
attack, but it has exerted a powerful influence upon subsequent analyses of
remembering. According to Hume, to remember something is to have a special kmd
of mental experience in the form of a mental image different from any other kmd
of image or idea. In part, of course, he was led to talk of * an idea of the
memory ’ hy his .? cu , ^ psychology, hut it is important to notice that
although facult 7 psychology are over we still feel compelled to me “ or y 111
a not very dissimilar way. Although anc * neurologists still know practically
nothing ..bout the brain mechanism » which enables us to recall past
experiences and previously acquired skills, it seems natural tothink of the
memory as a unitary function of some sort, and from this it is easy to conclude
that our memories, bemg the products of a single process, must m some way be
stamped with the sign of then manufacture. This is one feature of the problem
which suggests that the task set to any philosophical theory of memory is to
detect those characteristics of the mental experience of remembering that will
serve to isolate and define it. There is another puzzle which leads one in the
same direction How do we know that certain of our images and thoughts are
images of, and thoughts about, the past ? How do we know, if we are trying to
remember say the look of a town, that none of the images we can summon are
right, that none of them are memory images, and then, suddenly, that this one
is a memory image ? Hume’s general concept of the mi nd as an entity which can
perceive only its own thoughts, inevitably suggested an answer to these questions,
which also did justice to the solution suggested by a faculty psychology For if
one holds that a second order perception is involved in all thinking, it is
natural to apply to this second order perceiving an analysis that is obvious
and seems perfectly adequate to account for certain features of first order
perception The commonplace that one defines words referring to physical objects
by attempting to isolate those features of a physical object that are necessary
and unique to it was applied by Hume to the “ objects ” of second order
perception The impressions of sense, the ideas of memory and the ideas of
imagination differ from each other, he said, with respect to their strength and
vivacity, hence perception (first order), remembering and imagining may be
defined in terms of relative strength and vivacity. Ryle mentions the
absurdities involved in the classical theory of second order perception, but it
is worth pointing out here that the difficulties involved m talking of
perceiving an impression of sense (or a sense datum) are not by any means so
obviously involved m ta lking about perceiving one’s mental image. Most
students, when they first read Hume, are struck by the strangeness of his
suggesting that the impressions of sense differ from the images of memory only
m degree, in a way that they do not think it strange to suggest that the images
of memory and those of imagination might so differ This is not surprising, for
although no one has quite been able to describe how one should set about obeying
a request to attend to one’s impression of sense or sense datum of an object,
as distmct from looking at the object itself, everyone knows how to attend to a
mental image of an object In ordinary discourse we use the verbs of perception
in this second order sense quite naturally, as when we speak of hearing the
tune we heard last night or of seeing the accident as clearly as if it were
occurring in front of one’s eyes, and only a philosopher would feel obliged to
supply inverted commas for the verbs in this use Furthermore, not only can one
describe the contents of an image but one can also discriminate between and
report upon properties of the image as a whole ; for example, upon its
comparative vividness, intensity, blurriness, definition, and so on. I conclude,
then, that when Hume suggested that the images of memory and those of
imagination difier intrinsically in respect of their relative strength and
vivacity, he was not making a suggestion that is difficult to understand and
implausible in the way that Ins similar remarks about the impressions of sense
are It is generally agreed, however, that the characteristics of strength and
vivacity of an image fail to mark off unambiguously our rememberings from our
imaginings. For quite often the images of our imaginings and fantasies are very
much more vivacious and vivid than are many of our memory images. Usually this
standard criticism of Hume’s theory is made with the suggestion, explicit or
implied, that if only we were sufficiently attentive and ingenious we could
discern what combination of characteristics invariably attend our rememberings
and are absent when we are imagining A number have been suggested, eg. that our
rememberings are accompanied by a feeling of famibarity, that this feeling
makes us apply the concept of pastness to the image, and so on, though I think
it is rarely suggested that such characteristics provide the criteria of
remembering as Hume maintained his did. The trouble witb tbis criticism is that
it fails to expose tbe real nature of Hume’s failures and m fact it simply
encourages speculations which must prove equally inadequate Hume’s theory of
remembering is the purest example of what I might call the mental datum theory
: that to remember is to have a certain sort of mental datum or experience, and
to tell others what one remembers is to inform them of the details of tins
datum (usually thought to be an image). So far in this paper I nave been
chiefly concerned to point out considerations which make this a natural theory
to put forward. I wish now to show rt i 8 an “ n P oss ft , le thesis to
maintain in any f or m.. I I ^ person statement that asserts an inner
experience UJce the possession of an image, a certain sort of feeling or sensa-
tion^ can be corrected by a third person. It must be accepted as e or rejected
as a he ; it cannot be shown to be mistaken. If I say that I Lave a vivid image
of a tree before me, my bearers can, in principle, disbelieve me on the grounds
that I am lying, though it is very difficult to imagine what such grounds might
be. But it would make no sense to accuse me of being mistaken about the matter.
The concept of mistake only applies to cases where it is both theoretically
possible to obtain independent evidence on the matter and to explain how the mistake
arose. There is no way at present known of obtaining evidence independent of a
man’s word as to whether or not he has a mental image of the sort he claims to
have. It is sometimes suggested, indeed, that avowals of one’s state of mind or
body are m principle incorrigible and hence self-certifymg. But I suggest this
is an incorrect way of stating the point. "We are under no logical
obhgation to accept the truth of an avowal and avowals of certain types of
inner experience are regarded as corrigible by indirect evidence. To mention
only one example, claims to be in pam aresometimes rejected on the evidence of
medical authorities when there is a recognised correlation between the
described pam and a physiologically morbid condition But malingerers are lying,
not mistaken. The important logical difference between statements about one’s
inner and private experiences and statements about the external and public
world does not run along the cleavage line of corrigible and incorrigible
assertions, but along the gap separating claims that may be true, mistaken or
deceitful, and those that can only be true or deceitful. Sometimes, like George
IV, people have entirely delusive memory experiences ; more frequently, they
claim to remember something when there is independent evidence to show that
they must be mistaken m so thinking. It is this fact that theories of memory
like Hume’s cannot account for. It is plain that on Hume’s theory one must have
either veridical memories or be lying, for no one can be mistaken as to whether
or not he has an image of a certain strength and vivacity. This is the point at
which the analogy between first and second order perception ceases to hold. We
can explain how we made the mistake of taking an overcoat on the floor to be
the body of a man : the light was had, we had lost our spectacles, we were too
far away to see properly. But one needs no light by which to see a mental
image, no oculist can attend to the defects of the inner eye, and try as we may
we can neither approach nor retreat from our images. . We use no organs to
detect our images, states of mind and sensations ; they are separated from us
by no medium ; there is no mechanism to go wrong ; there is no inference made
into which error could creep The absurd necessity that Hume's theory would
impose upon us of declaring to be a liar anyone who thought himself to be
remembering when he was not, clearly follows equally from any revised version
of the theory. There are no special images, accompanying feelings of
familiarity, or intense convictions that one is truly remembering and so on,
from the experiencing of which it follows conclusively that one is indeed
remembering.This follows from the fact that any claim to remember, no matter
how confidently it may be based upon the possession of dear and distinct
images, feelings of fa mili arity and so on, may in principle he falsified by
evidence of a non-subjective kind. For instance, I may he absolutely certain
that I can remember meeting a friend in the street yesterday. Yet, if it were
proved that the friend whom I thought I remembered meeting had been at that
time a hundred miles away, I would have to accept the fact that I could not
possibly remember meeting bfm and that I must have imagined the occurrence. It
follows from this corrigibility of claims to remember, that no mental datum or
combination of mental data can possibly function as sufficient criteria of
remem- bering as the Humean type of theory suggests they do. Or, to put the
point in the way I have been doing, one can only maintain the enterprise of
taking mental data to he sufficient criteria at the expense of rendering it
impossible to talk of people making honestly mistaken memory claims. It is well
worth noticing thatmental data ofthe type I have been considering do not
function as necessary criteria of remembering either. Hume’s doctrine that one
remembers if one has an image of a certain kind has only recently been
abandoned in the face of a mass of psychological evidence to the contrary.
Indeed, some would seem to have abandoned the memory-image theory with the
poignant reluctance of the theorist confronted with impossibly indigestible
facts. The facts are certainly indigestible, hut the weak points in a
conceptual analysis (which eveiy philosophical theory of memory should be) may
be detected independently of experimental evidence, and in this case one can
certainly show without recourse to experimental evidence that the possession of
mental imager}' is not a necessary condition (or criterion) of remembering. For
example, if a barrister conducting a cross- examination attempted to tlirow
doubt on the reliabibty of a witness s memory by demonstrating, per impossible,
that the witness s account was unaccompanied by mental imagerv, no one m the
court, would understand lus point at all. Ye” have e s o eci e or to help us
decide whether or not people remember an . ome o t icse are tests for the
presence or absence of necessary remembering 317 conditions, but tbe possession
or lack of possession of images is not one of these tests By substituting for ‘
mental image 5 any other mental datum in the example above, one can see
similarly that no specific mental datum need be present before one can be said
to remember. To avoid misunderstanding, it should be mentioned that of course these
arguments do not apply to any non-introspectible concomitant of remembering,
c.g. such as a certain pattern of neural discharge It may veil be discovered
that phenomena of this kind are necessary to remembering, but
non-introspectible or unconscious mental phenomena in the nature of the case do
not, and could not, usefully function as cnteria of remembering, which is the
point in question Modem versions of the memory image theory avoid the notorious
flaw in Hume’s theory by attempting to account for the fact of honest but
mistaken memory claims The core of the modified version is the suggestion that
a memory image is a representative image of a past perceptual experience, and
when one makes an honest mistake of memory one is faithfully reporting or observing
an image that fails to represent the past experience. This is unobjectionable
so far as it goes, but if the argument above, showing that images have no
necessary role m remembering, is correct, it follows that this theory fails to
expose any part of the logical structure of the concept at all, and merely
describes a phenomenon that may or may not take place It is, furthermore,
obvious that anyone who assigns to the memory-image a central role m the
analysis of remembering must explain the connexion or lack of connexion between
our rememberings when memory-images naturally are likely to occur, as in our
memories of places and faces, and those when they are not, as for instance when
we remember how to tie a running bowline or the first four hues of Paradise
Lost It is worth considering one such attempted explanation, made by Professor
Broad in The JSlind and Its Place in Nature. In a chapter entitled “ Memory ” m
that work he says that the word “ memory ” is highly ambiguous m tbe sense of
covering “ a number of very diff erent acts ” ; thus we use the verb to
remember ” m different senses when we speak of remembering a set of
nonsense-syllables, a poem, a proposition in Euclid, how to swim, and people
and places, because in each case what we remember differs from tbe others Given
this technique of discriminating diff erent senses of the verb to remember ,
Broad is able to declare the sense m which we remember past perceptual
experiences (when imaging is most likely normally to occur), to be different from
other cases, most of which, he suggests, can be called instances of remembering
only by courtesy. Broad’s contention that ‘ remembering ’ is an ambiguous word
which has many senses would be of the first importance if true. There are,
however, several reasons for denying its truth, at least in the frm in which he
presents it In the first place it is plainly incorrect to assert that, for
example, in the claims ‘ I remember her face ‘ I remember her name and
telephone number ’, ‘ I remember how to rhumba ’, one could possibly mistake
what was being claimed, through an ambiguity of ‘ remember ’, in the way that
one might mistake ox misunderstand the claim 4 1 have been to the bank ’.
Neither is it apparent that more subtle distinctions of sense are involved asm
‘I feel a penny ’, ' I feel sick ’ and ‘ I feel happy ’. The differences of
sense involved in the latter cases can be indicated by the blatant
inappropriateness of certain questions asked of one or more of the claims,
which axe quite appropriate if asked of others, e g. what is the location of
what you feel ? what did you feel it with? and so on But Broad does not elicit
dis- tinctions of sense in the verb ‘ to remember ’ in the same straight-
forward way. Instead, he first states an implied analysis of the concept of
remembering from which distinctions can be seen to follow, by declaring that
remembering is an act, and then not unreasonably concludes that the very
different activities involved in, e g. remembering how to swim (bodily
activity), the lines of a poem (rote activity), someone’s face (the mental
activity of having an image), and so on, must be reflected in different senses
of the word we use to refer to these differing acts. But such distinctions rest
upon the highly contentious assertion that remembering is the name of an act or
set of diffe rent acts, and is m no way a straight-forward statement about
usage as the previous examples were. Indeed, the implausible conclusion which
follows from thistheory, and which Broad draws, that there is no connexion
whatever between the senses of remember elicited, might be taken as prima facie
evidence of its falsity. The only way to. decide whether remembering and its
cognates are radically multivocal, or substantially univocal as I wish to
maintain, is to re-analyse the concept to see whether or not a uniform core of
meaning is preserved m its use in different con- texts. This I shall attempt to
do, and m the course of my argument it will, I think, become quite clear that
it is not possible o construe remembering as an act, except of course m the
entirely empty sense in which one might say that eveiy active verb mast- denote
an act. Before I proceed to this analysis something further is needed to do
justice to at least one of the points which Broad wished to make For anyone,
irrespectiveof whether or not he takes remembering to be simply an activity,
might well be greatly struck by the difference between remembering a past
perceptual experience, and remembering a poem or how to swim The difference
seems to lie in the fact that whereas it in no way seems necessaiy for one’s
remembering the lines of a poem or how to swim to be accompanied by
introspectible mental experiences, it is difficult to understand how one could
remember a perceptual experience without an experience analogous to the
original one taking place For example, what would it be like to remember the
very tones of a voice without m some sense hearing the voice again, or to
recollect in detail the view up the High from Magdalen Bridge without seeing it
in one’s mind’s eye ? Then again, when one goes over the events of the day one
usually does so not by telling oneself the story of what occurred but by
seeing, hearing and feeling again in memory fragments of one’s perceptual
experiences, in short, by a sort of reliving of the day’s events. What I shall
call, for want of a better phrase, reliving, is undeniably typical of our
remembering of perceptual experiences, and the memory-image theory is an
attempt to do justice to this fact, as also is Broad’s assertion that
remembering has different senses. Whether the phenomenon of reliving is marked
by a distinction m sense of ' remember ’ is a question that may be decided the
better when the remaining analysis has been made. It is fairly obvious,
however, that the notion of reliving is capable far better than that of a
memory image of accommodating the recall of non-visual perceptual experiences
and, hence, that the memory-image theory has the trivial defect of
over-narrowness. What is less obvious is whether the argument against the
memory- image theory presented earlier has equal weight against the broader
reliving theory. . It is certainly no more a standard test of remembering^ to
enquire whether a person is in some way reliving what he damns to remember, than
it is to enquire if he has an image of it -But one might now feel tempted to
argue that it does not follow from the fact that this is not a standard test,
that reliving is never theless not a necessary ingredient of remembering P as
evpen cnees We may investigate this possibility by se • => _ U P e
hypothetical case of a man who was perfectly well able to describe his past
perceptual experiences and yet denied that he underwent the experience of
reliving in any way at all. Some people might wish to argue that he must be
reliving the experiences he describes — otherwise how could he describe them?
and that either he fails to understand what we mean by the phrases ‘ reliving ‘
seeing or hearing vividly in recollection ! and so on, or that he undergoes his
reliving in a very curious way (as, for example, some hold that people with
freakish ability to calculate in their heads must perform sums terribly fast
and unbeknown to themselves ). 1 It would take us too far off the course this
paper must follow to consider the really interesting points this argument
involves. Two, however, may be noted. First, the ability to image sensory
experiences does vary widely from person to person, so the disagreement may
well have a factual basis . 2 Second, it is a genuine puzzle sometimes to know
what is to count as an image. For instance, what the writer pi esumes is his
memory image of the High from Magdalen Bridge is so fleeting, blurred and thin
that, if, as it were, it could be captured for the requisite time, it would undoubtedly
prove impossible to draw it ; yet he can describe the view to himself and
others. Would this count as an image, a reliving ? One tends to put an end to
such a question, I think, by wearily agreeing that it must be an image. The
really important point at issue, though, may he decided, whether or not this
preliminary question can be. If reliving is a necessary condition of
remembering a past experience, then, were we to find someone who could describe
to himself and to others his experiences without any reliving of them, it would
have to follow that he was not really remembering. I do not think that this
point could be sustained. Our subject would give a perfectly adequate
memoiy-performance ; he would pass all the standard tests of remembering ; we
could not even say that he is not good at remembering, in the usual sense of
the phrase. All that we could say of him is that he does his remembering in a
curious fashion, and, at the most, that remembering is for us a much richer
experience than it is for him, that, perhaps, it means more to us than it does
to him. But the phrase * means more 5 in this context has somewhat the same
force that it has in the observation that doing addition means more to me than
it does to a bank teller ; we both add, but whereas his answers come 3 A
phenomenon interesting in tins connexion is reported in a recent note on “ Loss
of Visualisation ’’ by Sir Bussell Brain, Proc of the Royal Society of Meihrmc,
Apn! 19J4, Vol. 47, No 4 3 An informative mid brief account of such differences
is given in “The Measurement of Mental Images ” by P. L Short, Penguin Science
Rcics, No. 24. almost automatically, I leach mine by means of agonised and
laborious little sums If only because we are taught to add, there is little
temptation for us to confuse our personal methods of doing it with the notion of
adding itself. It is perhaps largely because remembering is a natural
phenomenon, something which we do not have to learn, that we feel ourselves to
be authorities on the subject and that our personal methods and techniques will
have some necessary connexion with the logical structure of the concept. But a concept
used in public discourse could not be so dependent upon the vagaries of private
experiences, the nature of which, as we have seen, it is not even easy to describe
3?or it to have a stand- ard meaning its use must be standardised, and
reference to the experiences of reliving undergone by individuals, plainly,
could hardly be suitable for this In fact, because of our preoccupation with
our experiences of remembering, we tend to simply ignore the standard uses to
which we put the concept in our discourse It is to these that we must now turn I
referred earlier to the fact that a claim to remember is m principle
falsifiable or verifiable by observations which are in no way connected with
the state of mmd of the person making the claim The following example lEustrates
still further points of difference between the logic of statements about one’s
sate of mmd and statements containing the verb ‘ to remember ’ or its cognates
But this is incidental to the present purpose of the example, which is to
provide further material for the study of how the concept actually behaves when
used m discourse. Suppose two men, each of whom is thoroughly acquamted with
the painting of a certain artist. This artist has painted a view fa mili ar to
each, and one man has seen the painting and the other has neither seen it nor
had it described Now suppose we ask each man to try and picture the painting to
himself and then to tell us what the painting is like The man who has seen the
painting before will probably claim to remember it, and we can test his claim
by getting him to describe it to us Should his statement be such that it would
count as a description of the painting, it must be allowed that he remembers it
Should his statement not be a description of the painting, 1 or shouldhe be
unable even to begin a description, Tre would have to declare tliat lie did not
remember the painting ; in the first case that either he was guessing or
confusing the painting with another one ; in the second, unless he suffered
from ° r "° fc C ° lmt aB a descn P tl0n 111 thls of context a speech
defect or the painting was such that a verbal description presented great
difficulty, simply thathe had failed to remember it.We could hardly expect the
other man to be able to describe the painting, but it is just possible that,
knowing the scene and being familiar with the artist’s ' vision palette and so
on, he could tell us sufficiently well what the painting was hbe. But even were
his answer to be in substance exactly the same as that of the man who remembered
the painting, and even if both were to have similar mental pictures, the second
man would not be remembering the painting but guessing what it was like, and
even if he were honestly to believe himself to be remembering it, it could not follow
that he was. Alternatively, if the first man had quite forgotten that he had
seen the picture and had then told us what it. was like, thinking he was
guessing, we should be forced to declare that in fact he was remembering the
picture although he was unaware that he was domg so. The obvious point which
this example illustrates is the in- dependence between on the one hand, the
state of mind, mental imagery and so on, of the person who claims to remember
or not remember the painting and, on the other, the factors which, on appeal,
decide whether the claim is to be accepted or rejected and reformulated as a
guess or an imagining. As was mentioned earlier, that memory claims are
verifiable m principle by recourse to pubbcly ascertainable facts 1 indicates a
marked difference between the logic of these assertions and those reporting a
mental experience An even more staking distinction hes in the fact that if a
claim to remember is rejected in toto, it is im- mediately reclassified, as for
instance * you couldn’t remember such an occurrence because it never took place
; you must have imagined it or guessed it. or made it up ’. Each of us has been
subject to such corrections and unquestionably we were not being convicted of
linguistic incompetence : neither, as we have seen,could it be for mistaking
the nature of our (conscious) mental experience. What, sort of mistake, then,
were we committing ? An answer suggests itself most strongly when one notices
the way m which rejected memory-claims are corrected : you didn’t remember, you
imagined, dreamt, guessed it, and so on. We use these forms of emendation when
certain of the conditions hich must he fulfilled before remembering can take
place, have This is not aht ays possible, of course, eg. it hen ne remember our
dreams feelings and so on But treat our memories of such tilings nx though they
arc verifiable independently, m as much as everyone it ould admit that it is
possible that his memory of, e g lus dream, is mistaken or faulty. not been
fulfilled, for example, when someone claims to remember seeing an occurrence
which m fact never took place, or, if it did, winch he could not have been m a
position to witness. In such a case, the statement presented as a memory-claim
or the unexpressed thought which is taken to be a memory, cannot have come to
mind as a result of the memory process, t e as the retention of past
experience, for the experience never took place To correct the claim with ‘ you
must have imagined, dreamt, guessed it’, and so on, answers the question which
the demal that remembering took place poses, namely, How then did he come to t
hink of it? by ascribing to him a mental process different to the one
originally claimed. I think that it would be true to say that the everyday view
of remembering is simply that it is the final stage of a causal process and
that the memory is some sort of causal device or mechanism. The fact that in
our language remembering is opposed by other process words like imagining,
guessing, inventing, making-up, dreaming, and so on, is itself evidence of this
belief The view that remembering should he thought of as part of a causal
process is, of course, fundamental to psychology and to neurologists attempting
to find the brain mechanism responsible for the phenomenon The process view
also underlies the extensions made to the concept of memory when, under the
influence of the new evolutionary biology, the notion was apphed to races and groups,
or m our own day when we apply it to inanimate objects capable of certain
involved causal processes, as when we speak of calculating machines having a
memory. The fact that it makes some sense (although also different senses) to
talk of human memory, race memory, machine memory and so on, indicates how
central to the concept of memory is the process-analysis Add to this the point
that if we are to explain the phenomenon of memory we undoubtedly have to
assume that a process of some sort is responsible, and one is led to enquire whether
the analysis of remembering into a process-concept may not solve the problems
which the analyses so far mentioned have been unable to meet For one thing,
reference to an underlying mental processprovides a common factor m our use of
the memory words over a wide range of differing contexts, and would thus appear
to explain our usage For another, it would seem to avoid the difficulty raised
by honest but mistaken memory- claims, as there is no reason why privileged
access should extend to unconscious mental processes There is, however,
something very curious entailed by this suggestion On the one hand, even now
very little is known about the processes involved m human memoiy . 1 On the
other, it is frequently possible to establish with certainty that a person remembers
something The consequence of the process analysis would be, then, that we can
establish with certainty that on oc- casions the working of an assumed and
unknown process has taken place. It also involves the novel information that
when we claim to remember, what we are really claiming is that we are undergoing
a certain mental process. If this were so it is undoubtedly true that the vast
majority of people when they claim to remember something, simply do not know
what it is that they are claiming. These conclusions are quite unacceptable But
the difficulties involved m construing the concept as a process concept do not necessitate
the equally unpalatable course of maintaining that it is not a process concept.
The assertion that a person remembers something does mvolve, or is taken to
involve, the ascription to that person of a certain mental process undergone.
But it also involves far more, and that of a character vastly more important to
the purposes of everyday life m which the concept finds employment. In its
constant everyday use it finds employment, I suggest, as one of a group of
concepts which we use to classify statements according to their truth-value. The
group described earlier as process concepts opposed to remembering likewise
serve the same purpose. But the properties which, ru the previous context, it
was natural to assume were properties belonging to the utterer of a statement —
that lie is guessing, imagining, inventing, dreaming, etc — I wish now to point
out are properties which, in the first place, belong to the statement itself. A
statement is classified as a guess when it is not backed by evidence which
would yield it as a conclusion ; an inference when it is so backed ; an
invention, story, dream or imagining when it bears no relation, descriptive or
evidential, to the facts which it purports to he about, when the statement is
presented as a claim to remember. (To preface a statement with, e g. ' this story
’, * my dream etc , is to declare that it does not purport to be about any
facts.) These rough summaries, which are not meant to he characterisations let
alone definitions, serve to bring out two pomts. First, that to classify a
statement under any one of these or similar heads is to label ltwith regard to
Its truth-value. 1 There are. of course, highly informed speculations about its
nature See, c g The neurophysiological Basis of Mind, by J. C Eceles, Oxford For
a discussion of certain special difficulties that accounts of the nature of
tlie memory mechanism must face, see, “ In Search of the Engram ’ by K. S
Lashlov, S.E B Symposia, vol. IV, Academic Press, HT.X , 1950. Second, that it
is, so to speak, to write upon tlie label tbe support or lack of it which the
statement possesses. Thus the labelling of an assertion as a guess informs
peoplethat the support or grounds hacking the assertion is of a certain kind,
and that although the information asserted is unlikely to be true, it just may
be so (it may be a shrewd guess). Though the remaining process verbs I
mentioned, and the far larger set that I have not mentioned, would each need
individual treatment (which I shall shortly give in the case of remembering) m
order to demonstrate that they are used to classify assertions, the sample that
I have given is suffi- cient to indicate the nature of this linguistic
function. It may be observed that it is clearly necessary m the interests of
efficient communication that we should apprise one another, where possible, of
the logical status of the assertions we make. The enormous difficulties and
frustrations reported by people who have experienced living m primitive
societies where such distinctions are not made is sufficient witness of this.
On the other hand, except in certain rare instances, it is not apparent that
the constant exchange of autobiographical prefaces to our remarks would be
particularly useful or interesting The man who purveys information solely about
himself is a bore Although the fact that it is grammatically correct to refer
the actions denoted by active verbs to the actor (I guess, he guesses, etc )
clearly plays a large part m leading us to misconstrue sentences containing
verbs of the group which concerns us simply as sentences giving information
about the actor, this linguistic fact is not the whole of the matter Even though
the logical propriety of employing active verbs at all in these contexts might now
seem dubious, it equally seems unavoidable On the one hand, that the making of
assertions or the thinking of thoughts of logically different lands necessarily
involves a doing or activity seems guaranteed by the “ causal principle ” ; on
the other, it is a matter of experience that frequently the production of
different sorts of assertions (or thoughts) is preceded by typically di ff
erent mental doings, experiences or processes The fact of the matter is that
these verb forms play a multiple role m discourse , they are used
simultaneously to label the logical status of an assertion or thought, and to
refer to the activities or processes whicare causally responsible for the
assertion. Neither role can be reduced to the other, but it is important to see
that one is logically primary. That the process role is secondary showed itself
m the case of remembering, m that no types of mental experiences or thought processes
were found to be either necessary or sufficient conditions of remembering.
Equally, the primacy of the logical status marking role appears when. it is
realised that the conditions which are necessary and sufficient are those
relating to the truth value and truth conditions of the statement of what is
remembered, e g. my claim to remember seeing Jones hit Smith is correct only if
Jones did hit Smith and I witnessed the occurrence. Once "the relationship
existing between the two roles is dear it is not difficult to see why the
experiences which typically enter into our remembering have no part in the
logical structure of the concept. They could never provide conclusive tests of
whether remembering has taken place or not because what the tests must he
designed to determine is whether the putative memorr is veridical {eg. whether
Jones did hit Smith, etc.). If the assertion ' I remember p 5 is true then it
follows that one’s memory processes worked correctly, but the truth of the
assertion is not logically dependent on the workings of the memory process.
This point can be seen more clearly in the following logically analogous case The
test of whether an electronic calculating machine is working correctly (and was
designed correctly) hes in the correctness of its calculations. The tests of
correctness are of course logically related to the rules of the calculus
employed, not to an electronic process. The production of a calculation is
causally dependent upon the functioning of some process, mechanical or mental, which
employs certain mathematical procedures, just as the production of a memory is
causally dependent npon some individual’s memory processes. But logical
dependence cannot be assimilated to cansal dependence (or vice versa ) as the
theories of remembering examined earlier in fact attempt to do. For instance,
even if a totally error-free calculating machine were developed, so that it
became practicable to say that the correct answer to a complex calculation is
the answer given by the machine, the machine’s answer would still in principle
he verifiable and the relations between logical and causal dependence remain
unchanged Human memories are not perfect, and when- ever anything of importance
hangs npon an individual's meznoiy claim we endeavour to verify it. But
although in practice we never accept as quite conclusive those experiences
whatever they may be, which lead a man to state with honest conviction I know I
remember , we do accord them the staus of strongly presumptive signs of
remembering. If our memories were uniformly excellent then undoubtedly we would
drop our practice of verifying claims to remember, except as a check for
mendacity, and treat them as if they were self-certifying. But. even in thi* remote
contingency, the primacy of the status labelling role would remain unchanged. What
I liave referred to as the ‘ logical status labelling ! role played by tbe
mental process verbs must be elucidated further m the case of remembering. To
preface one’s remarks with the phrase ‘ I remember . . . ’ (or a cognate) is to
indicate to one’s audience that you certify the truth and accuracy of the
infor- mation you are about to give or which you claim to be able to give or to
the correctness of the performance you will or could under- take The nature of
the status-label affixed to p m a statement of the form ‘ I remember p ’,
might, m part, be paraphrased * p is true (or this performance is an instance
of p) and you have my word for it ’. In this, the role of these expressions is
notably parallel to that of ‘ I know ’, and this comes out in the fact that very
frequently we can employ either verb with indifference both to the intended and
understood sense of the utterance, eg ‘do you know/remember Ins name* ‘ do you
know/remember Ohm’s Law* ’ and so on It similarly shows itself m the fact that if
one remembers p it entails that one knows p The reverse, of course does not.
hold. One may use the verb ‘ to remember ’ only to certify statements or
performances relating to the past, whereas we can, by the use of * know ’
certify statements about the past, present or future I propose to mark tlus
common linguistic role by describing each concept as a certificatory concept We
may now understand the concept of knowledge to be our most general
certificatory concept, and the concept of remembering to be specialised m the
respect just mentioned It might at first seem that the certificatory role is at
once too obvious and too unimportant to be worth the mention For the norm of
communication is essentially the exchange of infor- mation supplied m all
sincerity. We expect perfectly ordinary statements like ‘ the car is outside ’,
* it was raining yesterday ’, I can see him coming ’ to be true, and lienee
there is a perfectly good sense in which one can say that the mere utterance of
ap- parently informative statements commits the utterer to standing by the
truth of lus statements. But this very fact makes it obviously desirable to
have expressions which underline our committal to the truth of our assertions,
and which can be used to stress the fact that the information is certified. I
shall turn shortly to consider the contexts in which we do and do not use remember
’ , here, it may be noticed that a phrase like * body of knowledge ’ can be
translated into ‘ body of certified informa- tion and ‘ theory of knowledge ’
into ‘ theory of certification ’ with some gam m illumination A further gam
stems from the power to explain certain features of the logical grammar of the concepts
which this way of loo kin g at them allows. If one proffers information
accompanied by the formula 'I remember (that) p 5 or ‘I know (that) p’, then,
should p turn out to be false, to be misinformation, one is forced not merely
to admit the falsity of the information, but also that one did not remember,
that one did not know. One is forced by the rules of language formally to eat
one’s own words. One may attempt to explain the existence of such a rule by
pointng out that, at least in the case of the verb to remember and the verbs of
perception, which are also subject to this rule, one is dealing with what Ryle
has called achievement words. This is both true and useful, for one can talk
here of trying or of failing to achieve the desired result, eg oi trying or
failing to remember, to see, to hear and so on ; and success may sometimes
indeed be ac- companied by a very real feeling of achievement. But one cannot
make this point of the verb ‘ to know ’ : it is not clear what could be meant
by ‘ trying to know or ' failing to know ’, except in the acquaintance sense of
the word where the rule does not apply. The reason for this difference is
undoubtedly that the verbs of ’ achievement ’ are also process (or procedure)
verbwhereas the verb ‘ to know ’ in its relevant sense is not Processes may or
may not work, they need suitable conditions (‘ the light is too bad to see ‘ it
happened too long ago for me to remember the details ’, * my ears are full of
water ’) ; and sometimes they can be made to work (‘ turn on the light then
you’ll see ’, ‘ if you remember what you did before that it might come back ‘
you’d better see a doctor ’) If a process fails to work one must with- draw a
claim which implies that it has worked But the fact that this rule of formal
withdrawal applies equally to the verb to know, which is not a process verb,
suggests that there must be more behind the rule than reference to processes
which may or may not have taken place The remaining explanation emerges, I
suggest, if one sees the rule also as a device, embodied m the language, to
protect the integrity of certificatory expressions Words may be abused, suffer
debasement and lose their force, and if it were not for the presence in the
language of a formal rule of this nature, certificatory expressions would soon
lose the special emphasis which makes them so valuable. It is important to
notice that because we use the verb 'to remember ’ as a mark that the
information we are giving is true and correct, it does not follow that memory
can never play us false, that we cannot make a mistake in our remembering, that
one either remembers or one doesn’t. If a man were to make three mistakes in a
recitation of the Ode to a Nightingale no one could sensibly accuse him of
failing to remember the poem, unless it happened to be an occasion when
perfection was required. On the other hand, if he were to get his telephone
number wrong, we would say that he simply doesn’t remember it rather than say merely
that he made some mistakes "We have no hard and fast rules for what is to
count as a correct description, an accurate sum- mary, getting an account
right, knowing a street or an argument or a poem Hence, we cannot state hard
and fast rules for what is to count as remembering, for we treat remembering as
a function of the truth, correctness and accuracy of a statement (or perform- ance).
We evaluate the truth or accuracy of a statement by taking mto account the
demands of the contest and situation in which it is made, and express this
evaluation by choosing terms from, so to speak, a rough scale of expressions
For example: ‘ completely accurate ’, * fairly accurate ’, * inaccurate ’, 1
quite true ’, ‘ partly true ’ and so on. Likewise we evaluate and express the
truth or accuracy of what is remembered For example, * he remembered it
perfectly ‘ he half-remembered it ’, ‘ he didn’t remember it at all ’ and so
on. Similarly we may dimini sh the claim to correctness implied by the use of
the verbs * to remember ’, ‘ to recollect ’, * to know ’ by prefacing them with,
eg. ‘ I seem to . . ’, ‘ I think I . . . ‘ I believe I . . . ’ and so on The
object of such qualifications is of course to warn the listener that there is,
to a varying degree, some doubt about the correctness of the information which
will follow and that, having given due warning, the speaker cannot be blamed if
his listener puts too much weight upon his words A noteworthy consequence of
the certaficatory role of remem- bering may be seen in the fact that it is only
rarely necessary to bring up the notion of remembering m our everyday
discourse. Now one could generate a sense of the verb to remember such that from
the demonstration that one has not forgotten p, i e that one has produced or
performed p, it would follow that one remembers p This sense would fully accord
with the requirements of the process concept of memory, as the latter embodies
precisely the rule just used to generate the new sense of remember. Hence, the
skills and information that may be said to be memory- dependent, i e. which we
may forget (perhaps as a result of injury to the brain) may now be said to beremembered
when they are aetualised. Thus one could speak of Englishmen conversing or
writing in E nglis h as * remembering words in the English language ’, of
accountants doing accounts as e remembering how to add ’, and one might murmur
as one signs one’s name ‘ I’ve remembered my name agam ’. The absurd
inappropriateness of these examples if ‘ remember ’ is understood in its usual
sense, illustrates the opposition between the two senses. It is not, of course,
an opposition that permits the crude exposure of its existence by denying that
in these examples one remembers one’s name or one’s language, for such a denial
would for each sense entail that one had forgotten them The inappropnateness
would he in bringing up the notion of remem- bering in its usual sense at all
in such connexions. Two -very closely related factors determine when it is
appro- priate to bang up the notion of remembering m ordinary discourse It
would clearly be nearly as pointless to remark the functioning of one’s memory
processes each time they work as it would be to remark the fact that one
breathes and is m full possession of one’s faculties ; that one has possession
of one’s faculties is usually sufficiently evident. The introduction of one’s
remarks with the phrase ‘ I remember ’ or the ascription to the remarks or performances
of others as remembered has pomt just because we reserve the use of these
expressions for occasions when there is some possibility that one may not
remember what- ever happens to be m question. Thus the absurd examples given
above would be sensible remarks only if made m a context in which there was
reason to believe that the person of whom they are made was suffering an
impairment of his faculties, or was a child who was actually learning this
information or these skills As a result of this restriction of application, the
very bringing up of the question of remembering actually implies the possibility
of forgetting Compare the rudeness of ‘ do you remember your name* ’ with ‘
what is your name* ’or ‘do you remember what you had for breakfast today* ’
with ‘ do you remember what you had for breakfast three weeks ago* ’ Part of
the absurdity of the earlier examples lies m the ineptness of implying that,
for instance, a sane and sober accountant might have forgotten how to add Si m
ilar considerations determine the occasions on which it would be sensible to
use a certificatory expression We never bring up the notion of remembering nnless
there are grounds for supposing that an assertion ma)' need checking or that a performance
might be faulty, and in such circumstances it is obviously fitting to employ a
certifying expression. By the same token it would he otiose to employ an expression
with this force when one’s hearers stand m no need of personal assurances about
the truth of what is uttered For instance, no one would say either Tremember’
or ‘Iknow that 2 + 2 = 4’ although he certainly does know it and, in the
special first sense, he certainly does remember it. Tlie contiast ■which I have
drawn between the special sense and the ordinary sense of the verb to remember
lies, of course, more properly, between the concept of memory and the concept of
remembering The concept of memory is the concept of a storage system, but the
concept of remembering is not its natural corollary, that of the wholesale
removal from store of the goods and chattels of experience Rather, as I have
briefly attempted to show, it is devoted to the removal, not of special
articles, but of any articles when conditions are such that the transaction deserves
attention. It is now' possible to attempt an answer to the question which we
deferred, namely, whether remembering has a unitary sense maintained in all
contexts, or whether it is importantly multivocal If the arguments put forward
m this paper are correct, it is plain that in their primary linguistic role as
certificatory concepts the verb to remember and its cognates preserve a unitary
sense in all contexts Things ns various ns assertions, thoughts, images, feelings,
bodily performances and so on, may be similar in respect of their logical
status as lmvmg been remembered It is the secondary process attributing lole
that misleads theorists on the topic and invites speculations about differing
senses of the verb. Whet tier there is a single process responsible for the
phenomenon of remembering is a question on which no lay opimon would merit consideration,
and m the absence of an accepted view about the nature of the process it seems
correct to suggest that generally the verb has an utterly vague secondary
sense, rather than a cluster of differing ones But it remains quite open to
individuals to nominate specific process references should they wish to, and it
is apparently the case that sometimes this does occur, as when people,
impressed by the characteristic way m which their own memories come to them,
take the verb to have reference to these private happenings In such cases there
seems no reason why one should not talk of differing secondary senses of the
verb, so long as it is clearly understood that such senses are private ones, and
do not provide the material upon which an analysis of the concept must be
founded.
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment